Stephen Houlgate’s research while affiliated with University of Warwick and other places

What is this page?


This page lists works of an author who doesn't have a ResearchGate profile or hasn't added the works to their profile yet. It is automatically generated from public (personal) data to further our legitimate goal of comprehensive and accurate scientific recordkeeping. If you are this author and want this page removed, please let us know.

Publications (20)


In Memoriam Zbigniew Andrzej Pełczyński OBE (29 December 1925–22 June 2021)
  • Article

June 2022

·

6 Reads

Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain

Stephen Houlgate


„Wie man der hegelschen Philosophie beibringt, Englisch zu sprechen“

September 2018

·

52 Reads

Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie

Stephen Houlgate is one of the leading Hegel scholars of the English-speaking world. In this interview he explains how he became a “Hegelian” while studying in Cambridge, and he offers a fundamental profile of his account of Hegel. The interview addresses the following questions: Why does Houlgate consider Hegel’s philosophy to be the “consummate critical philosophy”? What are the main barriers to a proper access to Hegel’s thought? Why is logic as dialectical logic still indispensable for philosophical thought? And finally, what can both analytical and “continental” philosophers learn from Hegel?


Hegel, McDowell, and Perceptual Experience: A Response to John McDowell: Perceptual Experience, Thought and Action

January 2018

·

49 Reads

·

6 Citations

In this essay I examine Hegel’s conception of perceptual experience and respond to criticisms by John McDowell of an earlier essay of mine on the same topic. I argue that, for Hegel, sensation takes in the look or shape of things, but that consciousness and intuition actively “posit” what we see and feel as a world of objects. In McDowell’s view, this commits my Hegel to “subjective idealism.” I argue, by contrast, that Hegel avoids such idealism, because in positing what we see to be an object, consciousness thinks it to be the object it is: the activity of consciousness presents us with the object itself. I also argue, pace McDowell, that, for my Hegel, human beings do not first admit sensory content to an antechamber of the mind and then admit it to consciousness at the cost of being conceptualised, but that sensory content is taken into consciousness, and endowed with objectivity, as it is being received. To conclude, I note that, whereas, for Hegel, sensory content is received into consciousness by being actively taken up into it, for McDowell, experience involves no such activity but conceptual capacities are drawn into operation passively in the deliverances of sensibility.


Enseñando a hablar inglés a la filosofía hegeliana Entrevista a Stephen Houlgate
  • Article
  • Full-text available

December 2017

·

16 Reads

·

1 Citation

Ideas y Valores

Download


Hegel

August 2017

·

14 Reads

·

1 Citation

G. W. F. Hegel (1770–1831) was the last and greatest of the German Idealists and exercised an unparalleled influence on nineteenth‐ and twentieth‐century thought. His legacy includes the idea that human existence is essentially historical, that history is the development of the consciousness of freedom, and that true freedom involves living in an ethical community whose members accord one another reciprocal recognition and respect. Through his emphasis on human historicity and freedom, as well as his analysis of concepts such as “alienation” and “dialectic,” Hegel's thought helped spawn such divergent philosophical movements as Marxism, existentialism, pragmatism, hermeneutics, and deconstruction. He also had a profound impact on modern social theory and modern (especially, Protestant) theology; and he has even been called the “father” of art history.


Right and Trust in Hegel’s Philosophy of Right

May 2016

·

34 Reads

·

4 Citations

Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain

According to Hegel, true freedom consists not just in arbitrariness, but in the free willing of right. Right in turn is fully realised in the laws and institutions of ethical life. The ethical subject, for Hegel, is a practical subject that acts in accordance with ethical laws; yet it is also a theoretical, cognitive subject that recognizes the laws and institutions of ethical life as embodiments of right. Such recognition can be self-conscious and reflective; but it can, and indeed must, also be a felt recognition and as such it takes the form of trust. In Hegel’s view, therefore, the proper stance to adopt towards ethical institutions is that of trust; moreover, there is a distinctive freedom to be found in trust itself. Trust is appropriate, however, only when the institutions of ethical life are themselves worthy of it. Hegel is well aware that not all states and their institutions merit trust, but in his view a life without trust in institutions is a life without true freedom.



Hegel, Kant and the Antinomies of Pure Reason

January 2016

·

117 Reads

·

4 Citations

Kant Yearbook

Hegel argues that Kant’s antinomies of pure reason are important because they implicitly show the categories of thought to be contradictory. In so doing Hegel disregards much of what interests Kant about the antinomies and interprets the latter “against Kant’s intention”. He also gets Kant wrong when he claims that Kant’s “trivial” resolution of the antinomies simply shifts contradiction from things in themselves to appearances. Nonetheless, I contend that Hegel’s interpretation is defensible, insofar as the antinomies do, indeed, show (what Hegel regards as) the categories of the “infinite” and the “finite” to be both opposed to and inseparable from one another. I also argue that Hegel is right to maintain that Kant’s proofs of the theses and antitheses in the antinomies assume what they are meant to prove and that Kant’s resolution of the antinomies is unsatisfactory.


Citations (4)


... What is important to note is that both the psychologically (or psychoanalytically) oriented reading and this epistemologically oriented one share a common commitment to separability (see for instance Winfield 2007Winfield , 2010Houlgate 2006Houlgate , 2018deVries 1988deVries , 2013: both interpretations share the view that a certain set of capacities is independent and can be isolated from higher ones without being altered. To see how this assumption works-and highlight its problems-let me now focus more closely on Hegel's theory of sensation. ...

Reference:

Hegel's Later Theory of Cognition: An Additive or Transformative Model?
Hegel, McDowell, and Perceptual Experience: A Response to John McDowell: Perceptual Experience, Thought and Action
  • Citing Chapter
  • January 2018

... 180-184);Baxley ( , 2008;Beiser (2008b);Deligiorgi (2006);Guyer (1993, pp. 335-393);Houlgate (2008);Macor (2012);Moggach (2008);Stern (2012, pp. 104-135); andWaibel (2008).23 ...

Schiller and the Dance of Beauty∗
  • Citing Article
  • February 2008

... What is important to note is that both the psychologically (or psychoanalytically) oriented reading and this epistemologically oriented one share a common commitment to separability (see for instance Winfield 2007Winfield , 2010Houlgate 2006Houlgate , 2018deVries 1988deVries , 2013: both interpretations share the view that a certain set of capacities is independent and can be isolated from higher ones without being altered. To see how this assumption works-and highlight its problems-let me now focus more closely on Hegel's theory of sensation. ...

Thought and Experience in Hegel and McDowell
  • Citing Article
  • July 2006

European Journal of Philosophy

... The discipline that was once concerned with the evaluation of visual art according to rational principles, relied for its operations on notions of artistic genius and its eternal bedfellows: talent, perception, interpretation and speculation; yet these attributes can today only mask the complex phenomena that underpin art in the age of advanced technology, mass media and (dis)information. Since Hegel's influential Lectures on Aesthetics, academic art criticism (from kritēs -judge) embraced dialectical reasoning as the means for clarity and the explicit exposition of all the steps that lead towards a conclusion (Houlgate, 2007). But implicitly art criticism feeds on the liberal fiction of universal communicability and transparency of thoughts and artworks ...

Hegel and the Arts
  • Citing Article
  • January 2007