Philipe M. Bujold’s research while affiliated with University of Cambridge and other places

What is this page?


This page lists works of an author who doesn't have a ResearchGate profile or hasn't added the works to their profile yet. It is automatically generated from public (personal) data to further our legitimate goal of comprehensive and accurate scientific recordkeeping. If you are this author and want this page removed, please let us know.

Publications (10)


Experimental design and measures of risky and riskless choices. a Binary choice task. The monkeys chose one of two gambles with a left–right motion joystick. They received the blackcurrant juice reward associated with the chosen stimuli after each trial. Time, in seconds, indicate the duration of each of the task’s main events. b Schema of visual stimuli. Rewards were visually represented by horizontal lines (one or two) set between two vertical ones. The vertical position of these lines signalled the magnitude of said rewards. The width of these lines, the probability that these rewards would be realized). c Estimating certainty equivalents from risky choices. Monkeys chose between a safe reward and a risky gamble on each trial. The safe rewards alternated pseudo-randomly on every trial—they could be of any magnitude between 0 and 0.5 ml in 0.05 ml increments. Each point is a measure of choice ratio: the probability of choosing the gamble option over various safe rewards. Psychometric softmax functions (Eq. 1) were fitted to these choice ratios, then used to measure the certainty equivalents (CEs) of individual gambles (the safe magnitude for which the probability of either choice was 0.5; black arrow). The solid vertical line indicates the expected value (EV) of the gamble represented in the box. d Estimating the strength of preferences from riskless choices. Riskless safe rewards were presented against one another, the probability of choosing the higher magnitude option (A) is plotted on the y-axis as a function of the difference in magnitude between the two options presented (Δ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\Delta$$\end{document} magnitude). The differences in magnitude tested were 0.02 ml, 0.04 ml, 0.06 ml, and a psychometric curve, anchored with its inflection anchored at a Δ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\Delta$$\end{document} magnitude of 0, were fitted on the choice ratios measured (Eq. 2). These functions were fitted to different magnitude levels, and the temperature of each curve was linked to the strength of preferences at each of these different levels
Estimating risky utilities using the fractile procedure. a Fixed utilities are mapped onto different reward magnitudes. The gambles that monkeys experienced are defined from bisections of the range of possible reward magnitudes. For each step the gambles were held fixed; safe magnitudes varied by 0.05 ml increments. b Estimation of utility using the stepwise, fractile method. In step 1, the monkeys were presented with an equivariant gamble comprised of the maximum and minimum magnitudes in the tested reward range. The CE of the gamble was estimated and assigned a utility of 50%. In step 2, two new equivariant gambles were defined from the CE elicited in step 1. The CEs of these gambles were elicited and assigned a utility of 25% and 75%. Two more gambles are defined in step 3, from the CEs elicited in step 2. Their CEs were then assigned a utility of 12.5% and 87.5%. Parametric utility functions, anchored at 0 and 1, were fitted on these utility estimates (see methods). c Utility functions estimated from choices. Data points represent daily CEs (semi-transparent) and their median values (red filled circles) tied to specific utility levels, as estimated through the fractile procedure. Both monkeys exhibit risk-seeking behaviour for low-magnitude rewards, and risk-aversion for high-magnitude ones. The data represent individual utility estimates gathered over 22 sessions for monkey A, and 7 sessions for monkey B. The red curves were obtained by fitting piecewise polynomial functions to the measured CEs (cubic splines with three knots)
Estimating riskless utilities from the stochasticity in safe–safe choices. a Measuring stochasticity in choices between safe two reward options. Example visual stimuli (top) representing choices between safe rewards (A: low, B: high) resulting in different percentage of choices for the high option (bottom; black dots). This was repeated for different reward option sets, centered at different increments (midpoints). For each midpoint, the likelihoods were fitted with a softmax curve (dashed), used to estimate the probability of choosing the larger option for a gap of 0.03 ml (gray dot). b Choice ratios as differences in utility. The likelihoods that monkeys would pick the better reward were transformed using the inverse cumulative distribution function (iCDF) of a logistic distribution. The utility of different rewards took the form of equally noisy distributions centered at the true utilities. The output of iCDFs is the distance between these random utilities (i.e. the marginal utility). c From marginal utilities to utility. The cumulative sum of marginal utilities approximated a direct utility measure for each midpoint. These measurements were normalized whereby the utility of the highest midpoint was 1, and the starting midpoint had a utility of 0. d Daily strength of preference estimates. Each point represented the temperature of the softmax curve fitted on the choice ratios (blue points: average across days). The lower the temperature parameter, the steeper was the softmax curve and the more separable were the random utilities. Lower values meant higher marginal utility measurement (steeper utility function), higher ones meant lower marginal utility (flatter function). e Daily choice ratio estimates from softmax fits. Estimates from the same day are linked by grey lines. Ratios of 0.5 meant that the random utility of the two options were fully overlapping (i.e. flat utility function); choice ratios closer to 1 meant random utilities that were fully dissociated and non-overlapping. f Utility functions. Utilities estimated in single days (grey lines) and averages (blue), normalized relative to the minimum and maximum midpoint
Discrete choice estimates differ between risky and riskless choices. a Utility functions in risky choice. Median parametric estimates for utility functions and probability weighting functions fitted to risky choices. Shaded area: 95% C.I. on the median of these functions. Two versions of the discrete choice model were fitted: the expected utility theory (EUT) model predicted choices solely based on reward options’ utilities (without probability weighting); the prospect theory (PT) model, predicted choices based on utilities and probability weighting. An expected value (EV) based model was included for comparison. Monkeys were risk-seeking, but where the PT model accounted for this mainly through probability weighting, the EUT model accounted for it through a more convex utility. b Comparison of risky choice models. The PT model described individual choices better than EUT and EV. Bayesian information criterions (BIC) were calculated from the log likelihoods of the daily best-fitting PT and EUT discrete choice models. c Utility functions in riskless choice. Median parametric estimates for utility functions fitted to riskless choices (shaded area: 95% C.I. on the median). The discrete choice model predicted choices from the expected utilities of rewards (no probability weighting). Utilities were mostly linear, though slightly concave
Risky utilities do not predict riskless ones, and vice versa. a Median utility function estimates for risky and riskless choices. The shaded area represents the 95% C.I. on the median of these functions. For riskless choices, utility estimates were mostly linear (though slightly concave). For risky utilities, the two different versions of the discrete choice model predicted S-shaped utilities, but risky EUT utility functions were more convex than PT utility functions. b Absence of correlation for utility parameters in risky vs. riskless choices. Pearson’s correlations were run on the parameters from risky and riskless scenarios. Red squares highlight Pearson’s R for the correlation of the α and inflection parameters between risky and riskless choices. Asterisks (*) indicate significant correlations (p < 0.05)
Comparing utility functions between risky and riskless choice in rhesus monkeys
  • Article
  • Full-text available

April 2022

·

175 Reads

·

7 Citations

Animal Cognition

Philipe M. Bujold

·

Leo Chi U. Seak

·

Wolfram Schultz

·

Decisions can be risky or riskless, depending on the outcomes of the choice. Expected utility theory describes risky choices as a utility maximization process: we choose the option with the highest subjective value (utility), which we compute considering both the option’s value and its associated risk. According to the random utility maximization framework, riskless choices could also be based on a utility measure. Neuronal mechanisms of utility-based choice may thus be common to both risky and riskless choices. This assumption would require the existence of a utility function that accounts for both risky and riskless decisions. Here, we investigated whether the choice behavior of two macaque monkeys in risky and riskless decisions could be described by a common underlying utility function. We found that the utility functions elicited in the two choice scenarios were different from each other, even after taking into account the contribution of subjective probability weighting. Our results suggest that distinct utility representations exist for risky and riskless choices, which could reflect distinct neuronal representations of the utility quantities, or distinct brain mechanisms for risky and riskless choices. The different utility functions should be taken into account in neuronal investigations of utility-based choice.

Download

Adaptation of utility functions to reward distribution in rhesus monkeys

September 2021

·

14 Reads

·

6 Citations

Cognition

This study investigated how the experience of different reward distributions would shape the utility functions that can be inferred from economic choice. Despite the generally accepted notion that utility functions are not insensitive to external references, the exact way in which such changes take place remains largely unknown. Here we benefitted from the capacity to engage in thorough and prolonged empirical tests of economic choice by one of our evolutionary cousins, the rhesus macaque. We analyzed data from thousands of binary choices and found that the animals' preferences changed depending on the statistics of rewards experienced in the past (up to weeks) and that these changes could reflect monkeys' adapting their expectations of reward. The utility functions we elicited from their choices stretched and shifted over several months of sequential changes in the mean and range of rewards that the macaques experienced. However, this adaptation was usually incomplete, suggesting that – even after months - past experiences held weight when monkeys' assigned value to future rewards. Rather than having stable and fixed preferences assumed by normative economic models, our results demonstrate that rhesus macaques flexibly shape their preferences around the past and present statistics of their environment. That is, rather than relying on a singular reference-point, reference-dependent preferences are likely to capture a monkey's range of expectations.


Nonhuman Primates Satisfy Utility Maximization in Compliance with the Continuity Axiom of Expected Utility Theory

February 2021

·

58 Reads

·

14 Citations

The Journal of Neuroscience : The Official Journal of the Society for Neuroscience

·

Philipe M. Bujold

·

Fabian Grabenhorst

·

[...]

·

Wolfram Schultz

Expected Utility Theory (EUT), the first axiomatic theory of risky choice, describes choices as a utility maximization process: decision makers assign a subjective value (utility) to each choice option and choose the one with the highest utility. The continuity axiom, central to EUT and its modifications, is a necessary and sufficient condition for the definition of numerical utilities. The axiom requires decision makers to be indifferent between a gamble and a specific probabilistic combination of a more preferred and a less preferred gamble. While previous studies demonstrated that monkeys choose according to combinations of objective reward magnitude and probability, a concept-driven experimental approach for assessing the axiomatically defined conditions for maximizing subjective utility by animals is missing. We experimentally tested the continuity axiom for a broad class of gamble types in four male rhesus macaque monkeys, showing that their choice behavior complied with the existence of a numerical utility measure as defined by the economic theory. We used the numerical quantity specified in the continuity axiom to characterize subjective preferences in a magnitude-probability space. This mapping highlighted a trade-off relation between reward magnitudes and probabilities, compatible with the existence of a utility function underlying subjective value computation. These results support the existence of a numerical utility function able to describe choices, allowing for the investigation of the neuronal substrates responsible for coding such rigorously defined quantity.SIGNIFICANCE STATEMENTA common assumption of several economic choice theories is that decisions result from the comparison of subjectively assigned values (utilities). This study demonstrated the compliance of monkey behavior with the continuity axiom of Expected Utility Theory, implying a subjective magnitude-probability trade-off relation which supports the existence of numerical subjective utility directly linked to the theoretical economic framework. We determined a numerical utility measure able to describe choices, which can serve as a correlate for the neuronal activity in the quest for brain structures and mechanisms guiding decisions.


Comparing utility functions between risky and riskless choice in rhesus monkeys

January 2021

·

55 Reads

·

1 Citation

Decisions can be risky or riskless, depending on the outcomes of the choice. Expected Utility Theory describes risky choices as a utility maximization process: we choose the option with the highest utility, which we compute considering both the value of the option and its associated risk. According to the random utility maximization framework, riskless choices could also be based on a utility measure. Neuronal mechanisms of utility-based choice may thus be common to both risky and riskless choices. This assumption would require the existence of a utility function that accounts for both risky and riskless decisions. Here, we investigated whether the choice behavior of macaque monkeys in riskless and risky decisions could be described by a common underlying utility function. We found that the utility functions elicited in the two choice scenarios were different from each other, even after taking into account the contribution of subjective probability weighting. Our results suggest that distinct utility representations exist for riskless and risky choices, which could reflect distinct neuronal representations of the utility quantities, or distinct brain mechanisms for risky and riskless choices. The different utility functions should be taken into account in neuronal investigations of utility-based choice.



Height and temperature parameters from fractile-derived and DCM-derived utilities
Adaptation of utility functions to reward distribution in rhesus monkeys

May 2020

·

78 Reads

This study investigated the influence of experienced reward distributions on the shape of utility func-tions inferred from economic choice. Utility is the hypothetical variable that appears to be maximized by the choice. Despite the generally accepted notion that utility functions are not insensitive to external references, the exact occurrence of such changes remains largely unknown. Here we benefitted from the capacity to perform thorough and extensive experimental tests of one of our evolutionary closest, experimentally viable and intuitively understandable species, the rhesus macaque monkey. Data from thousands of binary choices demonstrated that the animals' preferences changed dependent on the sta-tistics of recently experienced rewards and adapted to future expected rewards. The elicited utility functions shifted and extended their shape with several months of changes in the mean and range of reward distributions. However, the adaptations were usually not complete, suggesting that past expe-riences remained present when anticipating future rewards. Through modelling, we found that rein-forcement learning provided a strong basis for explaining these adaptations. Thus, rather than having stable and fixed preferences assumed by normative economic models, rhesus macaques flexibly shaped their preferences to optimize decision-making according to the statistics of the environment.


Figure 1. Experimental design and consistency of choice behavior. (a) Trial sequence. Monkeys chose between two options by moving a cursor (gray dot) to one side of the screen. After a delay, the reward corresponding to the selected cue was delivered. (b) Visual cues indicated magnitude and probability of possible outcomes through horizontal bars' vertical position and width, respectively. (c,d,e) Continuity axiom test. The continuity axiom was tested through choices between a fixed gamble B and a probabilistic combination of A and C (AC). A, B and C were ordered reward magnitudes (c); AC was a gamble between A and C, with probabilities pA and 1-pA respectively (d); different shades of blue correspond to different pA values (darker for higher pA). The continuity axiom implies the existence of a unique AC combination (pA=α) corresponding to choice indifference between the two options (B~AC, vertical line in e), with the existence of a pA for which B≻AC and of a different pA for which AC≻B (vertical dashed lines). The value of α was identified by fitting a sigmoid function (red line) to the proportion of AC choices (blue dots). (f,g,h) Consistency of choice behavior. The standardized beta coefficients from logistic regressions of single trials' behavior (f) showed that the main choice-driving variables were reward magnitude (mR, mL) and probability (pR, pL) for all animals, both for left (L) and right (R) choices; previous trial's chosen side (preChR) and reward (preRewR) did not consistently explain animals' choices (error bars: 95% CI across sessions; * p<0.05, one-sample t test, FDR corrected; no. of sessions per animal: 100 (A), 81 (B), 24 (C), 15 (D)). In choices between options with different probability of delivering the same reward magnitude, the better option was preferred on average by all animals, demonstrating compliance with FSD (g) (error bars: binomial 95% CI; no. of tests per animal: 28 (A), 24 (B), 15 (C), 23 (D); average no. of trials per test: 12 (A), 13 (B), 11 (C), 34 (D)). In choices between sure rewards (bars: average across all sessions; gray dots: single sessions; error bars: binomial 95% CI) animals preferred A to B, B to C and A to C (h), complying with both weak and strong stochastic transitivity (WST: proportion of choices of the better option >0.5 (blue dashed line); SST: proportion of A over C choices (red line) ≥ other choice proportions).
Figure 2. Experimental test of the continuity axiom. (a,b,c) Compliance with the continuity axiom. The axiom was tested through choices between a gamble B and a varying AC combination (left: visual stimuli for an example choice pair with pA=0.5 (a,b) or pA=0.375 (c)); increasing pA values resulted in gradually increasing preferences for the AC option. In each plot, gray dots represent the proportion of AC choices in single sessions, black circles the proportions across all tested sessions with vertical bars indicating the binomial 95% confidence intervals (filled circles indicate significant difference from 0.5; binomial test, p<0.05). The tests were repeated using different A and B values (b) as well as non-zero C values in a modified task (c). All four animals complied with the continuity axiom by showing increasing preferences for increasing probability of gamble A (rank correlation, p<0.05), with the AC option switching from non-preferred (pchoose AC<0.5) to preferred (pchoose AC>0.5) (binomial test, p<0.05). Each IP (α, vertical line) was computed as the pA for which a data-fitted softmax function had a value of 0.5 (horizontal bars: 95% CI); α values shifted coherently with changes in A and B values in all four animals, indicating a continuous magnitude-probability trade-off relation.
Figure 3. Indifference curves in the MP space. (a) Representation of the continuity axiom test in the MP space. The gambles used for testing the axiom can be mapped into the magnitude-probability diagram. Preference in choices between B (circle) and combinations of A and C (graded blue dots) is represented by an arrow pointing in the direction of the preferred option (bottom), consistently with the proportion of choices for the AC option (top). Each continuity axiom test resulted in an IP (vertical line, top), represented as a black dot in the MP space (bottom). (b) Indifference curve. IPs (gray dots: single sessions; black dots: averages; bars: SE) obtained using different A values (step 0.01 ml) shifted continuously, producing an IC in the MP space. Curve: best fitting power function. Data from monkey A (5 sessions, 1781 trials). (c,d) Indifference map. ICs for different B values (colored curves), described the gradual variation of the average IPs (colored dots, with SE bars) for each B. Small dots represent IPs measured in single sessions. Both sure rewards (c) and probabilistic gambles (d) as B options, produced coherent indifference maps, with smooth and non-overlapping ICs.
Compliance with the continuity axiom of Expected Utility Theory supports utility maximization in monkeys

February 2020

·

129 Reads

Expected Utility Theory (EUT), the first axiomatic theory of risky choice, describes choices as a utility maximization process: decision makers assign a subjective value (utility) to each choice option and choose the one with the highest utility. The continuity axiom, central to EUT and its modifications, is a necessary and sufficient condition for the definition of numerical utilities. The axiom requires decision makers to be indifferent between a gamble and a specific probabilistic combination of a more preferred and a less preferred gamble. While previous studies demonstrated that monkeys choose according to combinations of objective reward magnitude and probability, a concept-driven experimental approach for assessing the axiomatically defined conditions for maximizing subjective utility by animals is missing. We experimentally tested the continuity axiom for a broad class of gamble types in four male rhesus macaque monkeys, showing that their choice behavior complied with the existence of a numerical utility measure as defined by the economic theory. We used the numerical quantity specified in the continuity axiom to characterize subjective preferences in a magnitude-probability space. This mapping highlighted a trade-off relation between reward magnitudes and probabilities, compatible with the existence of a utility function underlying subjective value computation. These results support the existence of a numerical utility function able to describe choices, allowing for the investigation of the neuronal substrates responsible for coding such rigorously defined quantity. SIGNIFICANCE STATEMENT A common assumption of several economic choice theories is that decisions result from the comparison of subjectively assigned values (utilities). This study demonstrated the compliance of monkey behavior with the continuity axiom of Expected Utility Theory, implying a subjective magnitude-probability trade-off relation which supports the existence of numerical subjective utility directly linked to the theoretical economic framework. We determined a numerical utility measure able to describe choices, which can serve as a correlate for the neuronal activity in the quest for brain structures and mechanisms guiding decisions.




Figure 2. Basic choice behavior and estimation of certainty equivalents. a, Logistic regression of choice behavior.
Figure 2-1. Response time vs EV. Top: Mean RT (± SEM across sessions) as a function of EV difference between
Probability Distortion Depends on Choice Sequence in Rhesus Monkeys

January 2019

·

74 Reads

·

26 Citations

The Journal of Neuroscience : The Official Journal of the Society for Neuroscience

Humans and other primates share many decision biases, among them our subjective distortion of objective probabilities. When making choices between uncertain rewards we typically treat probabilities nonlinearly: overvaluing low probabilities of reward and undervaluing high ones. A growing body of evidence, however, points to a more flexible pattern of distortion than the classical inverse-S one, highlighting the effect of experimental conditions in shifting the weight assigned to probabilities, such as task feedback, learning, and attention. Here we investigated the role of sequence structure (the order in which gambles are presented in a choice task) in shaping the probability distortion patterns of rhesus macaques: we presented 2 male monkeys with binary choice sequences of MIXED or REPEATED gambles against safe rewards. Parametric modeling revealed that choices in each sequence type were guided by significantly different patterns of probability distortion: whereas we elicited the classical inverse-S-shaped probability distortion in pseudorandomly MIXED trial sequences of gamble-safe choices, we found the opposite pattern consisting of S-shaped distortion, with REPEATED sequences. We extended these results to binary choices between two gambles, without a safe option, and confirmed the unique influence of the sequence structure in which the animals make choices. Finally, we showed that the value of gambles experienced in the past had a significant impact on the subjective value of future ones, shaping probability distortion on a trial-by-trial basis. Together, our results suggest that differences in choice sequence are sufficient to reverse the direction of probability distortion. SIGNIFICANCE STATEMENT Our lives are peppered with uncertain, probabilistic choices. Recent studies showed how such probabilities are subjectively distorted. In the present study, we show that probability distortions in macaque monkeys differ significantly between sequences in which single gambles are repeated (S-shaped distortion), as opposed to being pseudorandomly intermixed with other gambles (inverse-S-shaped distortion). Our findings challenge the idea of fixed probability distortions resulting from inflexible computations, and points to a more instantaneous evaluation of probabilistic information. Past trial outcomes appeared to drive the “gap” between probability distortions in different conditions. Our data suggest that, as in most adaptive systems, probability values are slowly but constantly updated from prior experience, driving measures of probability distortion to either side of the S/inverse-S debate.

Citations (5)


... These two abilities can depend on how memory interacts with reward value processing. Timing intervals between food experiences are encoded automatically as a part of reward sensitivity (Bouton et al., 2013;Bujold et al., 2022;Vestergaard and Schultz, 2015) and alterations in encoding reward value dependent upon the time interval (seconds to minutes versus 24 h.) could reflect impairments that impact short-term versus long-term memory retrieval or altered interactions between memory and sensory processing (Plowright, 1993;Sargisson and White, 2004;Sargisson and White, 2007). Finding limited within-session discrimination might be related to the fact that discrete stimuli were not implemented in this study, and that predictive cues (test chamber and the houselight stimulus) were not specific to particular outcomes and their related values. ...

Reference:

Altered reward sensitivity to sucrose outcomes prior to drug exposure in alcohol preferring rats
Comparing utility functions between risky and riskless choice in rhesus monkeys

Animal Cognition

... First, the encoding scheme may be only partially adaptive to the environment, as assumed in the bounded log-odds model (Zhang et al., 2020), and approximate implementations of resource rationality, such as the Decision by Sampling model (Stewart et al., 2006), may better capture human behavior than exact resource-rational agents (Heng et al., 2020). Second, the encoding scheme typically adapts to the environment over the long run (Stewart et al., 2006;Wei & Stocker, 2015) rather than on shorter time scales of minutes or hours (Alempaki et al., 2019;Bujold et al., 2021;Frydman & Jin, 2021;Ren et al., 2018), while the adaptation of the decoding scheme may be much faster, as suggested by the Bayesian literature (Maloney & Zhang, 2010;Petzschner et al., 2015). What is explored in the ARRM framework above are theoretical possibilities, while how humans may behave like resource-rational agents is an empirical question. ...

Adaptation of utility functions to reward distribution in rhesus monkeys
  • Citing Article
  • September 2021

Cognition

... We assessed the influences of reward probability, magnitude, expected value and risk on behavior in a choice task, performed during the period of neuronal recordings but mostly on separate testing days (Fig. 1e). Initial tests during training confirmed that both monkeys consistently chose higher reward magnitude options in the absence of probability differences and higher probability options (cued by either sector or fractal stimuli) in the absence of magnitude differences 48 . ...

Nonhuman Primates Satisfy Utility Maximization in Compliance with the Continuity Axiom of Expected Utility Theory

The Journal of Neuroscience : The Official Journal of the Society for Neuroscience

... Successive empirical CEs can also be used to estimate complete utility functions using a fractile method (e.g. Machina, 1987;Genest et al., 2016;Bujold, Ferrari-Toniolo & Schultz, 2021). In Section VI.2.a, we derive CEs as indifference points that are theoretically predicted rather than observed. ...

Adaptation of Utility Functions to Reward Distribution in Rhesus Monkeys
  • Citing Article
  • January 2020

SSRN Electronic Journal

... Effect of previously experienced effort on effort disutility Following this observation that sensitivity to effort was decreasing during each session, we wanted to test whether the changes in effort were dependent on the experience of previous effort, as opposed to just time in the session. Previous studies in rodents, nonhuman primates and humans have identified that choice adaptation effects can explain seemingly irrational choices (Ferrari-Toniolo et al., 2019;Beron et al., 2022;Glimcher, 2022). To quantify the effect of previous trials, we performed a logistic regression adding the previously chosen effort level as interaction term for the variable on effort difference in Eq. 3. In a stepwise process, the explanatory power of further lagged terms was tested. ...

Probability Distortion Depends on Choice Sequence in Rhesus Monkeys

The Journal of Neuroscience : The Official Journal of the Society for Neuroscience