Nick Trakakis’s research while affiliated with Deakin University and other places

What is this page?


This page lists works of an author who doesn't have a ResearchGate profile or hasn't added the works to their profile yet. It is automatically generated from public (personal) data to further our legitimate goal of comprehensive and accurate scientific recordkeeping. If you are this author and want this page removed, please let us know.

Publications (14)


O CARMA E O PROBLEMA DO MAL: UMA RESPOSTA A KAUFMANKARMA AND THE PROBLEM OF EVIL: A RESPONSE TO KAUFMAN
  • Article
  • Full-text available

October 2022

·

1 Read

Gabriel R. De Oliveira

·

Monima Chadha

·

Nick Trakakis

A doutrina do carma, conforme elaborada nas tradições religiosas hindu, budista e jainista, oferece um poderoso relato explicativo das grandes questões humanas e, em particular, do sofrimento humano aparentemente imerecido. Whitley R. P. Kaufman (2005) tem razão em apontar que em alguns pontos, como o sofrimento de crianças, a ocorrência de desastres naturais e a possibilidade de salvação universal, a teoria do carma parece, pelo menos inicialmente, muito mais satisfatória do que a tentativas feitas para resolver o problema perene do mal por escritores que trabalham dentro das tradições teístas principais do judaísmo, cristianismo e islamismo. Kaufman, pensamos, também está correto ao destacar a falta de análise crítica dada pelos filósofos da religião contemporâneos (analíticos ou anglo-americanos) à teoria do carma, pelo menos em comparação com o volumoso corpo de trabalhos produzidos nos últimos anos sobre o problema teísta do mal. O recente artigo de Kaufman nesta revista, portanto, é bem-vindo como um passo para corrigir esse desequilíbrio na literatura, e no processo que contribui para remover o viés teísta ocidental de grande parte da filosofia da religião contemporânea. Por outro lado, pensamos que Kaufman infelizmente fez pouco para promover o entendimento geral da doutrina do carma e a maneira como essa doutrina é apresentada como uma resposta ao problema do mal. Kaufman oferece seis objeções à teoria do carma. Acreditamos não apenas que todas essas objeções falham em seu objetivo declarado, mas que a forma de proceder de Kaufman, sua metodologia, ajuda a explicar por que suas críticas à teoria do carma não são bem-sucedidas.

Download



Theodicy: The Solution to the Problem of Evil, or Part of the Problem?

July 2008

·

914 Reads

·

23 Citations

Sophia

Theodicy, the enterprise of searching for greater goods that might plausibly justify God’s permission of evil, is often criticized on the grounds that the project has systematically failed to unearth any such goods. But theodicists also face a deeper challenge, one that places under question the very attempt to look for any morally sufficient reasons God might have for creating a world littered with evil. This ‘anti-theodical’ view argues that theists (and non-theists) ought to reject, primarily for moral reasons, the project of ‘justifying the ways of God to men’. Unfortunately, this view has not received the serious attention it deserves, particularly in analytic philosophy of religion. Taking my cues from such anti-theodicists as Kenneth Surin, D.Z. Phillips and Dostoyevsky’s Ivan Karamazov, I defend several reasons for holding that the way of thinking about God and evil enshrined in theodical discourse can only add to the world’s evils, not remove or illuminate them.


Karma and the Problem of Evil: A Response to Kaufman

October 2007

·

1,066 Reads

·

19 Citations

Philosophy East and West

2007 by University of Hawai‘i Press 533 religions, but it clearly has no place within nontheistic religions. That is why Barry Whitney’s comprehensive bibliography on theodicy has so few entries relating to the doctrine of karma (Whitney 1993).3 Kaufman is not unaware of this problem, but states in response that ‘‘it would be a great mistake to insist on an unnecessarily narrow formulation of the problem of evil, in particular one that assumes an ethical monotheist religion’’ (p. 17). However, this is to confuse the project of offering a theodicy with the much broader project of offering a response to the problem of evil. Although a theodicy can be offered as a solution to the theistic problem of evil, it may be of little or no use in relation to other varieties of the problem of evil. It would be more appropriate, therefore, to speak of karma as an explanatory account of the existence of evil and suffering, rather than as a theodicy or a moral justification for the actions of a benevolent God.4 Second, Kaufman conceives of the doctrine of karma not only as a theodicy, but also as a ‘theory’ in the sense of a fully developed philosophical account of the presence of evil, or, as he puts it, ‘‘a complete, systematic theory of the origins and explanation...


An epistemically distant God? A critique of John Hick's response to the problem of divine hiddenness

March 2007

·

408 Reads

·

11 Citations

The Heythrop Journal

God is thought of as hidden in at least two ways. Firstly, God's reasons for permitting evil, particularly instances of horrendous evil, are often thought to be inscrutable or beyond our ken. Secondly, and perhaps more problematically, God's very existence and love or concern for us is often thought to be hidden from us (or, at least, from many of us on many occasions). But if we assume, as seems most plausible, that God's reasons for permitting evil will (in many, if not most, instances) be impossible for us to comprehend, would we not expect a loving God to at least make his existence or love sufficiently clear to us so that we would know that there is some good, albeit inscrutable, reason why we (or others) are permitted to suffer? In this paper I examine John Hick's influential response to this question, a response predicated on the notion of ‘epistemic distance’: God must remain epistemically distant and hence hidden from us so as to preserve our free will. Commentators of Hick's work, however, disagree as to whether the kind of free will that is thought to be made possible by epistemic distance is the freedom to believe that God exists, or the freedom to choose between good and evil, or the freedom to enter into a personal relationship with God. I argue that it is only the last of these three varieties of free will that Hick has in mind. But this kind of freedom, I go on to argue, does not necessitate an epistemically distant God, and so the problem of divine hiddenness remains unsolved.


Confronting the horror of natural evil: An exchange between Peter Coghlan and Nick Trakakis

October 2006

·

24 Reads

·

1 Citation

Sophia

In this exchange, Peter Coghlan and Nick Trakakis discuss the problem of natural evil in the light of the recent Asian tsunami disaster. The exchange begins with an extract from a newspaper article written by Coghlan on the tsunami, followed by three rounds of replies and counter-replies, and ending with some final comments from Trakakis. While critical of any attempt to show that human life is good overall despite its natural evils, Coghlan argues that instances of natural evil, even horrific ones, can be justified as the unavoidable by-product of a natural system on which human life and culture depends. Trakakis, however, rejects this view, counselling instead a degree of skepticism about our ability to construct a plausible theodicy for horrific evil.


A third (meta-)critique

October 2006

·

11 Reads

·

1 Citation

Sophia

I begin my third reply by answering some of the criticisms raised by Tierno against theodical attempts to account for the pervasiveness of moral evil. I then take the discussion to a meta-philosophical level, where I question the very way of thinking about God and evil implicit in Tierno’s critique and in much contemporary philosophy of religion.


Rowe’s new evidential argument from evil: Problems and prospects

May 2006

·

14 Reads

Sophia

This paper examines an evidential argument from evil recently defended by William Rowe, one that differs significantly from the kind of evidential argument Rowe has become renowned for defending. After providing a brief outline of Rowe’s new argument, I contest its seemingly uncontestable premise that our world is not the best world God could have created. I then engage in a lengthier discussion of the other key premise in Rowe’s argument, viz., the Leibnizian premise that any world created by God must be the best world God can create. In particular, I discuss the criticisms raised against this premise by William Wainwright as well as Rowe’s attempt to meet these criticisms. The Wainwright-Rowe exchange, I argue, highlights some insuperable difficulties in Rowe’s challenge to theism.



Citations (4)


... We respond that we should distinguish between a metaphysical claim and an epistemic claimthe efficacy of karmic causality is not dependent on our knowledge of its existence, any more than gravity did not operate in the times of the ancient Romans, who could not articulate the concept of gravitational attraction. The analogy with gravity raises, of course, the vexed question whether reincarnation is a real process that can be experientially verified or whether reincarnation is only a theoretical postulate that explains some present-day circumstances (Pasricha (1990); Chadha & Trakakis (2007)). However, it is beyond the scope of this article to address this question (for an extended discussion of this point, see Barua (2015)). ...

Reference:

The alchemy of suffering in the laboratory of the world: Vedāntic Hindu engagements with the affliction of animals
Karma and the Problem of Evil: A Response to Kaufman

Philosophy East and West

... Third, even though such doxastically wayward religious persons would certainly come to believe that the Anselmian God exists and would come to have correct soteriological beliefs, they would still be free to decide whether to enter into personal relationship with God or not. (Trakakis, 2007). Their liberty would still be preserved. ...

An epistemically distant God? A critique of John Hick's response to the problem of divine hiddenness
  • Citing Article
  • March 2007

The Heythrop Journal

... The POE literature distinguishes between natural evils and moral evils. Natural evils are sufferings which do not arise from the deliberate actions of humans (see, for example , Hick 1966;Inwagen 1988;Trakakis 2005), including the destruction of cities, towns, and villages caused by severe storms or earthquakes; famines as caused by draughts; or any number of other naturally occurring phenomena. Call individual instances of natural evil first-order natural evils. ...

Is theism capable of accounting for any natural evil at all?
  • Citing Article
  • February 2005

International Journal for Philosophy of Religion

... The term theodicy comes from the combination of two Ancient Greek terms: θεóς which means 'god', and δίκη, which means justice, thus arguing for the justification or vindication of God, as it were. In the context of religion, theodicy is a theory that considers evil and suffering in humans within the framework of the ideal divine, transcending the frameworks of faith-based existing systems (Rouzati 2018;Trakakis 2008). This term appears to have been first used in 1710 by the German philosopher Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz in his French essay often shortened to 'Théodicée', which examined the origins of evil, man's freedom, and God's goodness (Sleigh 1996, pp. ...

Theodicy: The Solution to the Problem of Evil, or Part of the Problem?
  • Citing Article
  • July 2008

Sophia