Jennifer Ryan Lockhart’s research while affiliated with Auburn University and other places

What is this page?


This page lists works of an author who doesn't have a ResearchGate profile or hasn't added the works to their profile yet. It is automatically generated from public (personal) data to further our legitimate goal of comprehensive and accurate scientific recordkeeping. If you are this author and want this page removed, please let us know.

Publications (7)


Are life forms real? Aristotelian naturalism and biological science
  • Article
  • Full-text available

February 2024

·

34 Reads

Synthese

Jennifer Ryan Lockhart

·

Micah Lott

Aristotelian naturalism (AN) holds that the norms governing the human will are special instances of a broader type of normativity that is also found in other living things: natural goodness and natural defect. Both critics and defenders of AN have tended to focus on the thorny issues that are specific to human beings. But some philosophers claim that AN faces other difficulties, arguing that its broader conception of natural normativity is incompatible with current biological science. This paper has three aims. First, we consider a distinctive and nuanced critique of AN’s general understanding of natural normativity put forward by Tim Lewens. Second, after giving a defense of AN, we explore and evaluate Lewens’ proposed alternative view—Kantian projectivism about life forms. We present a problem for Kantian projectivism and suggest reasons for thinking that AN is, after all, the superior position. Finally, we clarify and explain how AN’s claims about life forms and our knowledge of them, relate to empirical observation and to contemporary biological science.

Download

Constitutivism and cognitivism

August 2022

·

78 Reads

·

2 Citations

Philosophical Studies

Constitutivism holds that an account of what a thing is yields those normative standards to which that thing is by nature subject. We articulate a minimal form of constitutivism that we call formal, non-epistemological constitutivism which diverges from orthodox versions of constitutivism in two main respects. First: whereas orthodox versions of constitutivism hold that those ethical norms to which people are by nature subject are sui generis because of their special capacity to motivate action and legitimate criticism, we argue that these features are compatible with treating these norms as of a piece with those ‘formal’ natural-historical norms which can be used to assess living things. Second: unlike orthodox versions of constitutivism, our version does not seek to use a non-normative account of that kind of being which we are as a means of identifying those normative claims to which we are are by nature subject. We then indicate how our position can afford us the resources to address some of the familiar difficulties that face cognitivism in ethics.


Clinical reasoning as midwifery: A Socratic model for shared decision making in person‐centred care

April 2022

·

10 Reads

·

3 Citations

Nursing Philosophy

Shared decision making has become the standard of care, yet there remains no consensus about how it should be conducted. Most accounts are concerned with threats to patient autonomy, and they address the dangers of a power imbalance by foregrounding the patient as a person whose complex preferences it is the practitioner's task to support. Other corrective models fear that this level of mutuality risks abdicating the practitioner's responsibilities as an expert, and they address that concern by recovering a nuanced but genuinely directive clinical role. Cribb and Entwistle helpfully categorize models of shared decision making as ‘narrower’ and ‘broader’ and praise the latter's ‘open‐ended and fully dialogical ways of relating’. However, they stop short of providing a philosophical account of how that dialogue works. In this paper, a nurse–midwife and a philosopher collaborate to argue that the Socratic model of dialogue offers a solution to the practitioner–patient dilemma. In the Theaetetus, Socrates compares dialogical reasoning to ‘midwifery with all its standard features’. By means of a three‐way analogy, elements of midwifery practice are used to illuminate features of Socrates' claim that his dialogue is like midwifery; those features are then translated into an approach to shared decision making as the ‘midwifery of good thinking’ which both midwives and physicians would do well to adopt. A key concept that emerges is the need for practitioners to make a risk‐confidence assessment of the particular content of any decision to appropriately modulate their role in the practice of shared decision making.



Moral Luck and the Possibility of Agential Disjunctivism

March 2017

·

13 Reads

·

5 Citations

European Journal of Philosophy

Most presentations of the problem of moral luck invoke the notion of control, but little has been said about what control amounts to. We propose a necessary condition on an agent's having been in control of performing an action: that the agent's effort to perform the action ensured that the agent performed the action. The difficulty of satisfying this condition (or one like it) leads many on both sides of the moral luck debate to conclude that much of what we do is not within our control, and, at the limit, underpins agential skepticism, the view that no one has ever been in control of having performed an action in the external world. We propose a response to the agential skeptic modeled on the epistemological disjunctivist's response to the skeptic about perceptual experience. According to agential disjunctivism, the necessary condition on control can be met, thus undermining agential skepticism and one motivation for the problem of moral luck. Our view can be understood as resisting moral luck not by shrinking the domain of robust moral evaluation but by refusing to contract the realm of robust control.


Kant on the motive of (imperfect) duty

January 2017

·

64 Reads

·

3 Citations

This paper argues that Kantians face a little discussed problem in accounting for how actions that fulfill imperfect duties can be morally motivated. It is widely agreed that actions that are performed from the motive of duty are performed through a recognition of the objective necessity of the action. It is also generally held that the objective necessity of an action consists in its rational non-optionality. Many actions that fulfill imperfect duties, however, are rationally optional. Given these constraints, it is impossible that such rationally optional actions (including, for instance, many acts of benevolence) could be performed from the motive of duty. After presenting the problem as one that Kantians should find genuinely pressing, this paper offers a solution by advancing an alternative to the conception of rational necessity widely shared by Kantians. On the alternative view presented here, an action is rationally necessary if and only if the justifying reasons that speak in favor of performing the action do not depend on any empirical and therefore contingent motivational source on the part of an agent. Such actions may well be rationally optional. Moral motivation is therefore possible even in the case of rationally optional actions. Abbreviations: The following abbreviations are used for Kant’s works. All translations are from Practical Philosophy, ed. Mary J. Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999). Citations are given by the abbreviation, the volume, and the page number from Kant’s Gesammelte Schriften, edited by the Royal Prussian Academy of Sciences (Berlin: Georg Reimer, later Walter deGruyter & Co., 1900–). G. Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten (Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals). KpV Kritik der praktischen Vernunft (Critique of Practical Reason). MS Die Metaphysik der Sitten (The Metaphysics of Morals).


Kant and Kierkegaard on Inwardness and Moral Luck

March 2015

·

29 Reads

·

3 Citations

Philosophical Investigations

The traditional understanding of Kant and Kierkegaard is that their views on the good will and inwardness, respectively, commit them to denying moral luck in an attempt to isolate an omnipotent moral subject from involvement with the external world. This leaves them vulnerable to the criticism that their ethical thought unrealistically insulates morality from anything that happens in the world. On the interpretation offered here, inwardness and the good will are not contrasted with worldly happenings, but are instead a matter of worldly happenings that exhibit a particular temporal structure. Kant and Kierkegaard should not be understood as denying moral luck.

Citations (5)


... In particular, I will argue that these two questions can be best answered by taking a 1 Admittedly, there are some versions of constitutivism which do not face the aforementioned dilemma with regard to the authority and content questions. In particular, constitutivists influenced by Aristotle, such as Lavin (2017), Fix (2021), and Lockhart & Lockhart (2022), reject the 'minimum conception of agency' restriction. While their versions of constitutivism are interesting on their own, they are not relevant for the main focus of this paper, which is to answer the authority and content questions together. ...

Reference:

The Authority and Content of Morality: A Dilemma for Constitutivism and a Coherentist Approach to Normativity
Constitutivism and cognitivism

Philosophical Studies

... The reasons for this might be that nurses and midwives approach patient data holistically, spend more time with patients and monitor and further assess their condition, engage in problem solving at the bedside by carrying out countless orders regarding care, ensuring its quality, and, above all, anticipate the risk of emergencies. Furthermore, nurses' and midwives' practice is focused on providing patient-centered care [51,52]. ...

Clinical reasoning as midwifery: A Socratic model for shared decision making in person‐centred care
  • Citing Article
  • April 2022

Nursing Philosophy

... Thanks to an anonymous referee for encouraging me to clarify this point. 3 Reath 1989 has offered the most well-known version of the epiphenomenal or intellectualist interpretation, but numerous others have subscribed to a similar view, including: Allison 1990, Guyer 2008, Herman 1993, Lockhart 2017, MacBeath 1973, O'Neill 2013, Walker 1989, and Wolff 1973 states from playing a positive role in Kant's account of moral motivation.6 Due to the earlier dominance of the intellectualist interpretation, however, for quite some time scholars were focused on showing that feeling was involved in moral motivation rather than explaining how this works.7 The task for more recent scholarship has been to explain how exactly the feeling of respect might play a positive role in action motivated by the moral law alone. ...

Kant on the motive of (imperfect) duty
  • Citing Article
  • January 2017

... But the former are too sketchy (contrast them with Refl, AA 19: 213.4-6 where Kant seems to suggest that although certainty about moral laws is necessary, figuring out which laws apply in a given case might be a matter of probability), and it might be argued that interpreting the latter in this way rests on a faulty account of agency (Lockhart 2015). In any case, retrospective luck will have to wait for another occasion. ...

Kant and Kierkegaard on Inwardness and Moral Luck
  • Citing Article
  • March 2015

Philosophical Investigations