April 2022
·
17 Reads
The Journal of Politics
This page lists works of an author who doesn't have a ResearchGate profile or hasn't added the works to their profile yet. It is automatically generated from public (personal) data to further our legitimate goal of comprehensive and accurate scientific recordkeeping. If you are this author and want this page removed, please let us know.
April 2022
·
17 Reads
The Journal of Politics
April 2022
·
14 Reads
·
1 Citation
Philosophia
A common objection to political liberalism is that since reasonable citizens agree that some ways of life are worse than others – for instance that the life of a drug addict is less worthwhile than the life of a person who spends her time with family and philosophy – political liberals must concede that the state can sometimes permissibly use perfectionist reasons. I argue in this paper that this challenge is mistaken, because the comparison only tells us something about relative, not absolute, value. And because the real question concerns what the right justificatory constituency looks like, not what counts as reasonable in some other sense, the implication is that perfectionists and political liberals could construct equally plausible idealised constituencies. This stalemate gives us reason to develop arguments in favour of our preferred justificatory constituency. We cannot view local comparative judgements in isolation.
March 2022
·
12 Reads
·
1 Citation
European Journal of Political Theory
Social norms regulating carework and social reproduction tend to be inegalitarian. At the same time, such norms often play a crucial role when we plan our lives. How can we criticise objectionable practices while ensuring that people can organise their lives around meaningful and predictable rules? Gerald Gaus argues that only ‘publicly justified’ rules, rules that everyone would prefer over ‘blameless liberty,’ should be followed. In this paper, we uncover the inegalitarian implications of this feature of Gaus's framework. We show that because a society without clear social norms for how social reproduction and care work ought to be organised would be so unattractive, inegalitarian rules would pass Gaus's test They would pass this test since they would nevertheless be better than ‘blameless liberty.’ Those who are disproportionately burdened by a rule are faced with the daunting task of showing that they would be better off under no rule, instead of merely having to show that they would be better off with a different rule.
January 2022
·
4 Reads
·
1 Citation
Canadian Journal of Philosophy
Kevin Vallier has recently argued that the ideals of public justification and public deliberation should be separated. The link between the two, Vallier suggests, has been assumed without being properly defended. Once examined, the connection falls apart. In this paper, I argue that there is, in fact, a clear and convincing story available for why the two ideals should be treated as mutually reinforcing. Drawing on recent empirical evidence, I argue that the deliberative behaviour of citizens can have a clear and positive impact on the behaviour and policy choices of public officials.
October 2021
·
9 Reads
·
13 Citations
Journal of Medical Ethics
A wide range of non-pharmaceutical interventions (NPIs) have been introduced to stop or slow down the COVID-19 pandemic. Examples include school closures, environmental cleaning and disinfection, mask mandates, restrictions on freedom of assembly and lockdowns. These NPIs depend on coercion for their effectiveness, either directly or indirectly. A widely held view is that coercive policies need to be publicly justified-justified to each citizen-to be legitimate. Standardly, this is thought to entail that there is a scientific consensus on the factual propositions that are used to support the policies. In this paper, we argue that such a consensus has been lacking on the factual propositions justifying most NPIs. Consequently, they would on the standard view be illegitimate. This is regrettable since there are good reasons for granting the state the legitimate authority to enact NPIs under conditions of uncertainty. The upshot of our argument is that it is impossible to have both the standard interpretation of the permissibility of empirical claims in public justification and an effective pandemic response. We provide an alternative view that allows the state sufficient room for action while precluding the possibility of it acting without empirical support.
March 2021
·
32 Reads
·
3 Citations
Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy
Many democratic theorists hold that when a decision is collectively made in the right kind of way, in accordance with the right procedure, it is permissible to enforce it. They deny that there are further requirements on the type of reasons that can permissibly be used to justify laws and policies. In this paper, I argue that democratic theorists are mistaken about this. So-called public reason requirements follow from commitments that most of them already hold. Drawing on the democratic ideal of civic equality, I show that it can successfully explain why political decision-making must have the right sort of procedure-independent justification. However, contra standard accounts of public reason, I argue that laws and policies need to be justified with convergence accessible, not shared, reasons. Public reasons are those that are accessible in light of evaluative standards shared by all, or in light of every citizen’s private evaluative standards. Since this will make the set of public reasons wider, it makes the theory more palatable to sceptics while retaining the framework’s justificatory potential.
February 2021
·
10 Reads
·
4 Citations
Economics and Philosophy
Most political liberals argue that only rules, policies and institutions that are part of society’s basic structure need to be justified with so-called public reasons. Laws enacted outside this set are legitimate if and when public reasons can justify the procedure that selects them. I argue that this view is susceptible to known problems from social choice theory. However, there are resources within political liberalism that could address them. If the scope of public reason is extended beyond the basic structure it could order people’s preferences in a way that circumvents the identified issues.
June 2020
·
26 Reads
·
3 Citations
Journal of Social Philosophy
March 2020
·
1 Read
·
1 Citation
Jurisprudence
... A study conducted before the COVID-19 pandemic found a highly significant positive association between the percentage of people in a country who voted for populist parties and who believe that vaccines are not effective. (39)(40)(41)(42) In this sense, making scientific evidence available is a key task of Public Health professionals to support truly informed and evidence-based decision making (43,44), eventually determining barriers and drivers to vaccination, and using the insight to design evidence-based interventions for improving vaccination uptake, as recommended by the World Health Organization is the author/funder, who has granted medRxiv a license to display the preprint in (which was not certified by peer review) preprint ...
October 2021
Journal of Medical Ethics
... 12. For other criticisms of moderate perfectionism, see, e.g., Billingham (2017), Kugelberg (2022), and Li (2020). ...
Reference:
Perfectionism
April 2022
Philosophia
... Some theorists have appealed to similar ideas without using civic friendship as the grounding for RAP, so do not fall within the ambit of our critique. SeeNeufeld (2019) andKugelberg (2021). ...
March 2021
Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy
... It should be first acknowledged that there is of course no guarantee that the relevant kind of restrictions will obtain for social preferences over decision rules. Notably, as Kugelberg (2022) rightfully argues, it seems to be difficult to identify a salient dimension along which (democratic) decision rules could be unanimously arranged by the members of the public -a necessary condition for the singled-peak restriction for preferences over decision rules to obtain. More generally, even though we may expect members of the public to have more structured social preferences than those corresponding to individuals' conceptions of the good -if only because everyone agrees that the social alternatives in the subset X* must be ranked above those in the complementary subset -it is far from guaranteeing that the single-peak restriction obtains. ...
February 2021
Economics and Philosophy
... Public reason liberals who answer "yes" believe in symmetry, those who answer "no" believe in asymmetry. Henrik D. Kugelberg argues in favor of the latter (Kugelberg, 2020). According to Kugelberg, some choices in life are paradigmatically fundamental, such as whether to believe in religious teachings (p. ...
Reference:
Constructing the Abstract Individual
June 2020
Journal of Social Philosophy
... However, this connection is not inevitable. For instance, as a review of In the Shadow of Justice aptly points out, the success of the welfare state in Scandinavian countries is not solely linked to the economic growth of the two decades following the war (Kugelberg, 2020). In theory, 1 and 2 are separable. ...
March 2020
Jurisprudence