Drazen Prelec’s research while affiliated with Massachusetts Institute of Technology and other places

What is this page?


This page lists works of an author who doesn't have a ResearchGate profile or hasn't added the works to their profile yet. It is automatically generated from public (personal) data to further our legitimate goal of comprehensive and accurate scientific recordkeeping. If you are this author and want this page removed, please let us know.

Publications (24)


General identifiability of possible world models for crowd wisdom
  • Preprint

February 2022

·

7 Reads

Drazen Prelec

·

John McCoy

Prelec, Seung and McCoy (2017) proposed a crowd wisdom model where ideal Bayesian observers receive discrete i.i.d. signals si ∈ {s1,...,sn} conditional on an unknown ‘state,’ i.e., a possible world aj ∈ {a1,...,am}. Signals and worlds are presumed drawn from a distribution p(si,aj) known to observers, but unknown to the analyst. The paper asserted via an example but without formal proof that if ideal observers specify a belief matrix as conditional distributions p(aj|si), and a meta-knowledge matrix (beliefs about other observers’ signals) as p(si|sk) = ∑j p(si|aj)p(aj|sk), then the analyst can, in the large sample limit, derive p(si,aj) and identify the actual signal-generating world. Here we provide a proof based on computing the signal prior as the stationary distribution of the meta-knowledge matrix.




(Dis)honesty detection statistics.
Information use statistics.
Information use descriptive.
Do Not Tell Me More; You Are Honest: A Preconceived Honesty Bias
  • Article
  • Full-text available

August 2021

·

103 Reads

·

3 Citations

According to the previous literature, only a few papers found better accuracy than a chance to detect dishonesty, even when more information and verbal cues (VCs) improve precision in detecting dishonesty. A new classification of dishonesty profiles has recently been published, allowing us to study if this low success rate happens for all people or if some people have higher predictive ability. This paper aims to examine if (dis)honest people can detect better/worse (un)ethical behavior of others. With this in mind, we designed one experiment using videos from one of the most popular TV shows in the UK where contestants make a (dis)honesty decision upon gaining or sharing a certain amount of money. Our participants from an online MTurk sample ( N = 1,582) had to determine under different conditions whether the contestants would act in an (dis)honest way. Three significant results emerged from these two experiments. First, accuracy in detecting (dis)honesty is not different than chance, but submaximizers (compared to maximizers) and radical dishonest people (compare to non-radicals) are better at detecting honesty, while there is no difference in detecting dishonesty. Second, more information and VCs improve precision in detecting dishonesty, but honesty is better detected using only non-verbal cues (NVCs). Finally, a preconceived honesty bias improves specificity (honesty detection accuracy) and worsens sensitivity (dishonesty detection accuracy).

Download


What makes dynamic strategic problems difficult? Evidence from an experimental study

November 2020

·

75 Reads

·

17 Citations

Strategic Management Journal

Research Summary Managers regularly deal with dynamic tasks, where decisions impact immediate payoffs as well as long‐term capabilities. Research shows that people do poorly in dynamic tasks, but the underlying mechanisms are unclear. These may range from unsystematic problem‐solving to rational learning in complex environments. In a series of experiments, we tease apart alternative explanations, showing that poor performance is due to behavioral difficulties. Remarkably, we find that people do poorly even if provided with complete information about the payoff function, thus, eliminating any need for learning. They unsystematically search among possible solutions and end up with inefficient heuristics. The results show that differences in thinking through a dynamic problem may lead to substantial variation in performance, even if common sources of complexity and ambiguity are excluded. Managerial Summary Why do people, including managers, have difficulty managing systems where taking action today impacts future outcomes? Difficulty of learning in a complex environment has been proposed as the key challenge. Using experiments, we show that people find such tasks difficult even when all relevant information is provided to them and there is nothing to learn. Using trial and error most participants learn satisfactory, but inferior, heuristics. Those who systematically think through tradeoffs over time significantly outperform others even in a simple task, suggesting such thinking adds value in realistic managerial settings as well.


Figure 1. Percentage of coins outcome reported both for Lab and virtual M-Turk samples.
Figure 3. Declared vs. Real die outcome (Lab vs. Mturk). Asterisk above the bars mean significant differences between the declared and real outcomes. Asterisks over the black dashed lines mean significant differences between lab and Mturk samples. *** p<0.01; ** p<0.05; * p<0.1
Binomial test (í µí¼‹) comparing actual outcomes with uniform distribution. Also, the Chi-squared test (χ2) comparing the differences between Lab and Mturk samples for each outcome.
Cheaters, Liars, or Both? A New Classification of Dishonesty Profiles

August 2020

·

2,497 Reads

·

27 Citations

Psychological Science

Experimental studies of dishonesty usually rely on population-level analyses, which compare the distribution of claimed rewards in an unsupervised, self-administered lottery (e.g., tossing a coin) with the expected lottery statistics (e.g., 50/50 chance of winning). Here, we provide a paradigm that measures dishonesty at the individual level and identifies new dishonesty profiles with specific theoretical interpretations. We found that among dishonest participants, (a) some did not bother implementing the lottery at all, (b) some implemented but lied about the lottery outcome, and (c) some violated instructions by repeating the lottery multiple times until obtaining an outcome they felt was acceptable. These results held both in the lab and with online participants. In Experiment 1 ( N = 178), the lottery was a coin toss, which permitted only a binary honest/dishonest response; Experiment 2 ( N = 172) employed a six-sided-die roll, which permitted gradations in dishonesty. We replicated some previous results and also provide a new, richer classification of dishonest behavior.


Incentive-Compatible Surveys via Posterior Probabilities

August 2020

·

24 Reads

Theory of Probability and Its Applications

by SIAM. We consider the problem of eliciting truthful responses to a survey question when the respondents share a common prior that the survey planner is agnostic about. The planner would therefore like to have a “universal” mechanism, which would induce honest answers for all possible priors. If the planner also requires a locality condition that ensures that the mechanism payoffs are determined by the respondents’ posterior probabilities of the true state of nature, we prove that, under additional smoothness and sensitivity conditions, the payoff in the truth-telling equilibrium must be a logarithmic function of those posterior probabilities. Moreover, the respondents are necessarily ranked according to those probabilities. Finally, we discuss implementation issues.


К вопросу о стимульно-согласованных исследованиях с использованием апостериорных вероятностейIncentive compatible surveys via posterior probabilities

April 2020

·

17 Reads

Теория вероятностей и ее применения

·

Drazen Prelec

·

·

[...]

·

Hrvoje &Ccaron;ikic

Рассматривается проблема выявления правдивых ответов на вопросы некоторого исследования в случае, когда респонденты имеют общее априорное распределение, не интересующее составителя опроса. В такой постановке составителю опроса желательно иметь универсальное правило, стимулирующее респондентов отвечать правдиво при любом априорном распределении. Если дополнительно выполняются условие локальности (которое гарантирует, что платежные функции правил определяются апостериорными вероятностями фактического состояния системы) и условие достаточной гладкости, мы доказываем, что равновесная платежная функция в случае правдивых ответов респондентов является логарифмической функцией апостериорных вероятностей. Более того, респонденты должны быть упорядочены в соответствии с этими вероятностями. В заключение обсуждаются вопросы применения полученных результатов.


Incentive-Compatible Surveys via Posterior Probabilities

January 2020

·

22 Reads

We consider the problem of eliciting truthful responses to a survey question when the respondents share a common prior that the survey planner is agnostic about. The planner would therefore like to have a "universal” mechanism, which would induce honest answers for all possible priors. If the planner also requires a locality condition that ensures that the mechanism payoffs are determined by the respondents' posterior probabilities of the true state of nature, we prove that, under additional smoothness and sensitivity conditions, the payoff in the truth-telling equilibrium must be a logarithmic function of those posterior probabilities. Moreover, the respondents are necessarily ranked according to those probabilities. Finally, we discuss implementation issues.


Citations (15)


... Pascual-Ezama et al. [9] developed a new online version of the "die-under-the-cup" task, which enables individual tracking of dishonest behavior, unlike the aggregated results of previous studies. Results from this study, as well as others replicating the findings [4,88], are critical to studying dishonesty and understanding its potential variability at different levels and scales. By taking an individual approach, researchers can uncover a diverse set of dishonest profiles based on different strategies, allowing us to differentiate between the nature and gradient of dishonesty (e.g., cheating, lying, full-extent dishonesty, etc.). ...

Reference:

The Role of Cognition in Dishonest Behavior
Do Not Tell Me More; You Are Honest: A Preconceived Honesty Bias

... Also, we conduct this study in the Indian demographic, where such a study has been missing from the system dynamics literature. Most of the prior studies evaluating stock-flow principles have been conducted in the Western countries, especially the United States of America (Sweeney and Sterman, 2000;Sterman andSweeney, 2002, 2007;Cronin et al., 2009;Sterman, 2010;Harvey et al., 2019;Tadesse and Davidsen, 2019;Rahmandad et al., 2021). ...

What makes dynamic strategic problems difficult? Evidence from an experimental study
  • Citing Article
  • November 2020

Strategic Management Journal

... This line of reasoning suggests that increased ability may put people in a better position to resolve ambiguity present in the task. In support of this prediction, Pascual-Ezama et al. (2020) show that participants who simply skip rolling a die, when instead they were supposed to, go on to cheat the most. Similarly, Gross and De Dreu (2021) also found that participants who do not follow task rules go on to cheat more when given the chance. ...

Cheaters, Liars, or Both? A New Classification of Dishonesty Profiles

Psychological Science

... Plenty of other studies try to repurpose the BTS for forecast combination providing mixed evidence of its effectiveness. Radas and Prelec (2019) ask subjects from MTurk to state their willingness to pay for new gadgets. They find in successive randomized trials that combining predictions via the BTS reduces error in reported willingness to pay. ...

Whose data can we trust: How meta-predictions can be used to uncover credible respondents in survey data

... The paper [14] developed an informational theoretic paradigm for designing incentive mechanisms, which included, as special cases, many established mechanisms, including BTS, and showed that the properties of BTS could be proved in a simpler way by using a connection to Shannon mutual information. For a different connection between BTS and information theory, see [7]. Liu and Chen [16] designed a "uniform dominant" truth serum when there was a noisy signal of the ground truth and there were sufficiently many agents and tasks. ...

Game of Duels: Information-Theoretic Axiomatization of Scoring Rules
  • Citing Article
  • August 2018

IEEE Transactions on Information Theory

... A hierarchical logistic regression predicting purchase decisions yielded parameters on price (b = − 0.334, se = 0.116, p = 0.004), payment method (b = − 0.036, se = 0.099, p = 0.715) and their interaction (b = 0.251, se = 0.120, p = 0.037) in the anticipated direction. This interaction follows predictions based on a prior test conducted in a similar context 35 . Consistent with previous empirical studies 7,8 , participants were more willing to purchase higher-price items with credit rather than with cash, and thus they spent more overall when using credit card (average basket = $87.41, ...

Committing to Plastic: The Effect of Credit Cards on Purchase Intention
  • Citing Article
  • January 2013

SSRN Electronic Journal

... The extremised MPW algorithm allows decision-makers to generate accurate probabilistic predictions even when the forecasters' past performance is unavailable. The extremised MPW algorithm is also computationally simple, which may be appealing to decision-makers that are unfamiliar with more-sophisticated aggregation approaches that require structural estimation of latent parameters [20]. While previous research have demonstrated how meta-predictions can be used to correct for crowd biases [7], or used to identify the structure and extent of shared information in the crowd [13], no studies to date have shown that forecasters' meta-predictions can be used to derive weights that quantify latent expertise. ...

A statistical model for aggregating judgments by incorporating peer predictions
  • Citing Article
  • March 2017

... Despite its usefulness and ease of application, using consensus as the sole arbiter for evaluating the validity of a judgment has limitations. For example, in certain occasions the majority opinion has been shown to be systematically wrong (Galesic et al., 2018;Prelec et al., 2017). It has also been argued that disagreement can be a catalyst for enhancing knowledge. ...

A solution to the single-question crowd wisdom problem
  • Citing Article
  • January 2017

Nature