Douglas Lavin’s research while affiliated with University College London and other places

What is this page?


This page lists works of an author who doesn't have a ResearchGate profile or hasn't added the works to their profile yet. It is automatically generated from public (personal) data to further our legitimate goal of comprehensive and accurate scientific recordkeeping. If you are this author and want this page removed, please let us know.

Publications (10)


Forms of Rational Agency
  • Article

July 2017

·

37 Reads

·

18 Citations

Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement

Douglas Lavin

A measure of good and bad is internal to something falling under it when that thing falls under the measure in virtue of what it is . The concept of an internal standard has broad application. Compare the external breed standards arbitrarily imposed at a dog show with the internal standards of health at work in the veterinarian's office. This paper is about practical standards, measures of acting well and badly, and so measures deployed in deliberation and choice. More specifically, it is about the attempt to explain the unconditional validity of certain norms (say, of justice and prudence) by showing them to be internal to our agency and the causality it involves. This is constitutivism . Its most prominent incarnations share a set of assumptions about the nature of agency and our knowledge of it: conceptualism , formalism and absolutism . This essay investigates the merits and viability of rejecting all of them while still seeking the ground of practical normativity in what we are, in our fundamental activity.


Action as a form of temporal unity: On Anscombes Intention

November 2015

·

35 Reads

·

21 Citations

Canadian Journal of Philosophy

The aim of this paper is to display an alternative to the familiar decompositional approach in action theory, one that resists the demand for an explanation of action in non-agential terms, while not simply treating the notion of intentional agency as an unexplained primitive. On this Anscombean alternative, action is not a worldly event with certain psychological causes, but a distinctive form of material process, one that is not simply caused by an exercise of reason but is itself a productive exercise of reason. I argue that to comprehend the proposed alternative requires an account of the temporality of events in general. An event does not simply have a position in time, but is itself temporally structured. With the inner temporality of events in view, the Anscombean conception of action as a specifically self-conscious form of temporal unity is made available for critical reflection.


Other wills: The second-person in ethics

September 2014

·

22 Reads

·

9 Citations

Philosophical Explorations

This paper is about the interest of the second-person to ethics. The focus of recent discussion has been the explanatory power of the second-person, rather than its careful description or the very possibility of what is described. This paper is something of a corrective. Its aim is to get the claim that the second-person matters to ethics into a clearer focus with a view to raising further questions and puzzles.


Über das Problem des Handelns

September 2013

·

7 Reads

·

3 Citations

Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie

“On the Problem of Action” contrasts two conceptions of the task of action theory: the dominant conception, which I call the decompositional approach, and an alternative, non-decompositional approach that is implicit in the tradition of action theory descending from Aristotle. Decompositionalists seek to characterize intentional action as a composite of something inward and something outward, bound together by some generic kind of causal relation. I show that this approach is committed to characterizing action in terms that treat the agent’s own standpoint on her action as a separable factor, not integral to the worldly happening that constitutes her action proper, and I argue that this commitment leads decompositionalists to focus their theorizing not on actions-in-progress, but on cases of completed action. I then show how the neo-Aristotelian approach to understanding action contrasts with the decompositional approach in each of these respects: it seeks, not to explain what intentional action is by decomposing action into several not-intrinsically-agential factors, but rather to characterize the understanding of what it is to act implicit in the agent’s knowledge of her own action-in-progress. The main aim of this paper is simply to show that there is an alternative to the decompositional project, one that resists the demand for an explanation of action in non-agential terms, while not simply treating the notion of intentional agency as an unexplained primitive. To see the possibility of this sort of understanding of action is, I argue, to see how action could turn out to be, not a worldly event with certain psychological causes, but a distinctive form of material process, one that is not simply caused by an exercise of reason but is itself a (productive) exercise of reason, it is itself the exercise of a power of practical cognition.


Must There Be Basic Action? *

June 2013

·

57 Reads

·

63 Citations

Nous

Dependence, mediacy, and complexity are abstract concepts, as are their complementary opposites, independence, immediacy, and simplicity. The determinate conception we have to do with here is of an instrumentally or teleologically basic action: very roughly, an action is basic in this sense when no means are taken in its execution, or equally, when it is not the end of any other action. The concept figures in the description of the structure of getting something done, specifically of getting something done on purpose or intentionally, and thus also in the description of the agent's point of view on the structure of his own efficacy. The agent so depicted understands himself as doing whatever he does through the performance of basic actions, with all the rest derived from these. Means-end rationality expands our sphere of influence and massively extends our reach—there are flags on the moon and at the bottom of the sea!—but it is precisely at the inner limit of this teleological order that a rational agent's power to make a dent in things is genuinely displayed. Where means-end rationality comes to a close, efficacy genuinely begins: this is where the conceptual rubber is supposed to hit the material road, in the things one does without thought about how they get done. Sometimes it is said there is a spark of the divine in this. My own view is the opposite, that there is at best only a shadow of the brute.2



Goodness and Desire

July 2010

·

31 Reads

·

40 Citations

The chapter is a defense of the thesis that rational agents must desire and act sub specie boni or under the guise of the good. Our thought is that what underlies the guise of the good thesis is a more general point about the explanation of any self-movement, a point that applies, in different forms, to the explanation of behavior in nonrational animals, and even to the explanation of the nutrition, growth, and reproduction of nonsentient living things. What these various kinds of explanation have in common, we suggest, is that they all have a teleological structure; and we argue that, in general, this sort of explanation works by connecting what a creature is doing with what is good for creatures of its kind. The special feature of the application of this explanatory structure to rational creatures is that such creatures belong to a kind in which this connection between action and goodness becomes self-conscious: They are creatures whose action is expressive of and explained by their conception of their own good. This, we argue, is why rational self movers must act under the guise of the good.




Citations (7)


... SeeKant (1793); compareEngstrom (2009).21 CompareThompson (2003),Millgram (2010) andLavin (2017).22 Compare e.g.Wiggins (1975).Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. ...

Reference:

Metaethical constructivism and the capacity of practical reason
Forms of Rational Agency
  • Citing Article
  • July 2017

Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement

... 21 Perhaps it even attributes too little; see Schwitzgebel (2012). 22 Here I follow Setiya (2007) and Boyle and Lavin (2010) in their conclusion of a "stalemate" with respect to particular examples-though I doubt they would agree that there is a stalemate with respect to views as ambitious as the Normative Belief Requirement. ...

Goodness and Desire
  • Citing Chapter
  • July 2010

... That is, for the raising of an arm (to use a rather famous example) to constitute an action, a person, typically the one whose arm is in question, must intend to raise her arm. For recent research developing rather different perspectives in the philosophy of action, all the while accepting that intention is necessary for action, see Lavin (2015); Amaya (2018); Shepherd (2019). The latter distinguishes between two very different kinds of thinking about actions, and intentions to act, namely Wittgensteinian and Anscombian. ...

Action as a form of temporal unity: On Anscombes Intention
  • Citing Article
  • November 2015

Canadian Journal of Philosophy

... A general question that is increasingly asked, both in the psychological and philosophical literature, is how the capacity to know and understand oneself and others is related to various forms of human sociality (e.g. Heal 2003;Reddy 2008;Schilbach et al. 2013;Lavin 2014;Avramides 2015;Satne and Roepstorff 2015;Satne 2021). A common theme in some recent work on knowledge of other minds is that understanding the nature of such knowledge may require discarding the traditional view that our perspective on the mental lives of others is fundamentally spectatorialgrounded on, in Reid's (1764Reid's ( /1997 terms, 'solitary operations of the mind', such as inferring the causes of observed behavior or direct observation. ...

Other wills: The second-person in ethics
  • Citing Article
  • September 2014

Philosophical Explorations

... The notion "normativity" should briefly be defined, since it might be conceived from multiple perspectives. According to Pavlakos (2011), there are two main approaches of normativity, the first concerning an ideal aspect of human beings' lives and the second related to standards of judging, acting and feeling deriving from reflective activities or actions. ...

Discussion: Three Comments on Joseph Raz's Conception of Normativity
  • Citing Article
  • December 2011

Jurisprudence