David Pesetsky’s research while affiliated with Massachusetts Institute of Technology and other places

What is this page?


This page lists works of an author who doesn't have a ResearchGate profile or hasn't added the works to their profile yet. It is automatically generated from public (personal) data to further our legitimate goal of comprehensive and accurate scientific recordkeeping. If you are this author and want this page removed, please let us know.

Publications (37)


Wh-which relatives and the existence of pied-piping
  • Article
  • Full-text available

September 2023

·

90 Reads

Glossa a journal of general linguistics

David Pesetsky

·

Kanoe Evile

This paper describes and offers an analysis of a kind of relative clause acceptable to some English speakers that we call a wh-which relative, e.g. the snowmen whom (of) which the children loved. We propose that these relatives involve the movement of a phrase headed by an element that we call R, analogous to the Q posited by Cable (2010a, 2010b) for interrogatives — the optional of in the example above being an overt form of a special variant of R. The syntax of this variant resembles particularly closely the variant of Q proposed by Coon (2009) for Ch’ol interrogatives in triggering movement to its specifier — but with a puzzle that has a parallel in Finnish, for which we propose a tentative solution. The analysis thus supports the overall explanatory landscape for pied-piping phenomena proposed by Cable, but presents a challenge to his broader claim that all pied-piping phenomena can be explained in this way. If correct, it provides yet one more instance of the "unity in diversity" of syntactic structures across the world’s languages.

Download

Complementizer-Trace Effects

November 2017

·

136 Reads

·

37 Citations

Perlmutter observed that English wh ‐movement obeys a puzzling constraint: an asymmetry between subject extraction and non‐subject extraction that interacts with the complementizer system. While wh ‐extraction of a non‐subject from a finite embedded clause is compatible with the presence or absence of the word that introducing the clause, extraction of the subject is possible only when that is omitted: a. ✓ Who do you think that Sue met ____?/ ✓ Who do you think Sue met ____? b. * Who do you think that ____ met Sue?/ ✓ Who do you think ____ met Sue? The effect has come to be known as the “ that‐ trace effect,” a member of a family of possibly broader sets of phenomena, all called “complementizer‐trace effects.” A strong poverty of the stimulus argument makes it clear that these phenomena are rooted in innate properties of human language. The discovery of these effects in multiple diverse and unrelated languages reinforces this conclusion, especially when coupled with the availability of independently supported explanations for the absence of similar effects in other specific languages. On the other hand, quite distinct accounts have been offered for complementizer‐trace effects, and there is no consensus yet as to which of these approaches is most likely to prove correct. Linear accounts have been proposed that specifically bar extraction from positions right‐adjacent to elements of the complementizer system; these accounts are supported by claimed interactions with the presence/absence of prosodic boundaries between the two. Alternative structure‐based accounts that have proved influential include structural locality requirements on extraction sites that occupy particular syntactic positions – as well as proposals that take an opposite approach, banning movement that is too local. Thus, although the importance of complementizer‐trace effects for linguistic theory is clear, the deeper source of these effects remains a matter of controversy.



Recursive misrepresentations: A reply to Levinson (2013)

June 2014

·

87 Reads

·

13 Citations

Language

Levinson 2013 (L13) argues against the idea that ‘recursion, and especially recursive center-embedding, might be the core domain-specific property of language’ (p. 159), citing crosslinguistic grammatical data and specific corpus studies. L13 offers an alternative: language inherits its recursive properties ‘from the action domain’ (p. 159). We argue that L13’s claims are at best un-warranted and can in many instances be shown to be false. L13’s reasoning is similarly flawed— in particular, the presumption that center-embedding can stand proxy for embedding (and clausal embedding can stand proxy for recursion). Thus, no support remains for its conclusions. Furthermore, though these conclusions are pitched as relevant to specific claims that have been published about the role of syntactic recursion, L13 misrepresents these claims. Consequently, even an empirically supported, better-reasoned version of L13 would not bear on the questions it claims to address.


Verb-stranding Verb Phrase ellipsis and the structure of the Russian verbal complex

April 2011

·

503 Reads

·

81 Citations

Natural Language & Linguistic Theory

This paper investigates novel evidence from Russian Verb-Stranding Verb Phrase Ellipsis (VVPE), and argues for its use as a probe into the syntactic structure of morphophonologically inseparable but morphosyntactically complex verbs. The first step is to distinguish internal argument drop from VVPE, because they appear identical on the surface. I present novel evidence that Russian internal argument drop is illicit in syntactic islands, while VVPE is licit. Once this bifurcation established, it allows us to explain previously obscured differences in the syntactic licensing of subject vs. internal argument drop in Russian. The second step uses the verb matching requirement on the stranded verb in Russian VVPE to establish which parts of the verbal complex originate inside the domain of ellipsis, and which parts orig-inate outside. A surprising finding is that the verb matching properties of the Russian VVPE construction do not align with what has been demonstrated to hold of other languages in which VVPE is available. Unlike the strict matching requirement of Hebrew (Goldberg, 2005a,b) or Irish (McCloskey, to appear) VVPE, the matching requirement in Russian VVPE appears to be sensitive to discourse factors, at least for certain speakers. This last discovery results in a significant contribution to our understanding of the nature of the identity requirement in ellipsis licensing. Keywords: verb phrase ellipsis & verb-stranding & Russian & verb movement & argument drop & clause structure * This project has a long history, originating as part of my dissertation and evolving very significantly as a result of extensive input from some very generous people. I am deeply grateful to Jim McCloskey, Jorge Hankamer, Sandy Chung, and Maria Polinsky especially for their mentorship and extensive comments. I am thankful for the very constructive comments of Marcel den Dikken and two anonymous NLLT reviewers. Thanks to for discussion of the Russian data. All errors are my own.



Against Taking Linguistic Diversity at "Face Value"

October 2009

·

44 Reads

·

9 Citations

Behavioral and Brain Sciences

Evans & Levinson (E&L)advocate taking linguistic diversity at "face value". Their argument consists of a list of diverse phenomena, and the assertion that no non-vacuous theory could possibly uncover a meaningful unity underlying them. I argue, with evidence from Tlingit and Warlpiri, that E&L's list itself should not be taken at face value — and that the actual research record already demonstrates unity amidst diversity.



Pirahã Exceptionality: A Reassessment

April 2007

·

4,571 Reads

·

216 Citations

Language

Everett (2005) has claimed that the grammar of Pirahã is exceptional in displaying 'inexplicable gaps', that these gaps follow from a cultural principle restricting communication to 'immediate experience', and that this principle has 'severe' consequences for work on universal grammar. We argue against each of these claims. Relying on the available documentation and descriptions of the language, especially the rich material in Everett 1986, 1987b, we argue that many of the exceptional grammatical 'gaps' supposedly characteristic of Pirahã are misanalyzed by Everett (2005) and are neither gaps nor exceptional among the world's languages. We find no evidence, for example, that Pirahã lacks embedded clauses, and in fact find strong syntactic and semantic evidence in favor of their existence in Pirahã Likewise, we find no evidence that Pirahã lacks quantifiers, as claimed by Everett (2005). Furthermore, most of the actual properties of the Pirahã constructions discussed by Everett (for example, the ban on prenominal possessor recursion and the behavior of WH-constructions) are familiar from languages whose speakers lack the cultural restrictions attributed to the Pirahã. Finally, following mostly Gonçalves (1993, 2000, 2001), we also question some of the empirical claims about Pirahã culture advanced by Everett in primary support of the 'immediate experience' restriction. We conclude that there is no evidence from Pirahã for the particular causal relation between culture and grammatical structure suggested by Everett. Linguistics Version of Record


Property Delay (Remarks on “Phase Extension” by Marcel den Dikken)

January 2007

·

25 Reads

·

6 Citations

Theoretical Linguistics

1. Truth in unpackaging In his paper, den Dikken argues that several syntactic and semantic phenomena provide evidence for a package of proposals that includes the following four claims: (1) Phase Extension “Syntactic movement of the head H of a phase α up to the head X of the node β dominating α extends the phase up from α to β; α loses its phasehood in the process, and any constituent on the edge of α ends up in the domain of the derived phase β as a result of Phase Extension”. (den Dikken's (3)) (2) Phase Impenetrability Condition as in Chomsky (2000, passim) [PIC] “[I]n phase α with head H, the domain [of H] is not accessible to operations outside α, only H and its edge are accessible to such operations”. (den Dikken's (1)) (3) Adjunction Prohibition “[A]djunction to meaningless categories is disallowed.” (den Dikken's (18)) (4) Inherent Phase “[A]n inherent phase is a predication (subject–predicate structure).” (den Dikken's (2))


Citations (34)


... However, in the Minimalist Program, theta-roles are interpreted from the unambiguous configurations of vP-layer by the conceptual-intentional system after spell-out (Chomsky 2007;Gallego 2007;Hale and Keyser 1993). This assumption in the Minimalist Program has been made not only because of the 2 This paper assumes that case features are uninterpretable tense/aspect features contained in nominals (Pesetsky and Torrego 2001;Svenonius 2001). ...

Reference:

Paiwan ''Nominative'' and A-Topic Operator
T-to-C Movement: Causes and Consequences
  • Citing Chapter
  • April 2001

... However, only one can receive structural case from Voice. We assume nominative and accusative case are assigned by T and Voice respectively, and that, updating Burzio's generalization (1986), Voice only assigns case if it has an unvalued D feature (Pesetsky & Torrego 2004). This means that only verbs whose subject is introduced syntactically in the specifier of Voice will be able to have accusative-marked vP-internal arguments. ...

Tense, Case, and the Nature of Syntactic Categories
  • Citing Chapter
  • May 2004

... These findings within the segmentation literature stand in contrast to studies that have examined the influence of context speech rate on the perception of individual segments. Although it has long been understood that the perception of segments-for example, the perception of the distinction between [b] and [w] [28], between [b] and [p] [28], or between [ʃ] and [tʃ] [29]-can be influenced by the perception of the duration of immediately adjacent segments, support for the idea that segments further away can affect the perception of individual segments is equivocal at best. Distal rate effects from context more than a syllable remote from a point of segmental ambiguity are rare and often weak [30], with some authors proposing that long-distance rate normalization is unnecessary [31] or qualitatively different from the rate adaptation that occurs due to proximal information [20,21]. ...

Perceptual integration of acoustic cues for stop, fricative, and affricate manner

... Although such evidence for rapid learning of speech-specific structure was initially cited as evidence for the existence of a domain-specific "speech acquisition device" (Mehler et al. 1988), recent demonstrations of rapid statistical induction in 7-8-month-old infants (e.g. Marcus et al. l999, Saffran et al. 1996), including results with nonspeech stimuli (Haith 1994, Saffran et al. 1997, have led some theorists to conclude that the infant brain is a powerful learning device that is capable of rapid learning from arbitrarily sequenced materials in any modality (e.g. , Elman & Bates 1997. Hence the acquisition of speech contrasts in the first year of life may be a language-specific manifestation of domain-general learning mechanisms (Kuhl 1985). ...

Acquiring language [1] (multiple letters)
  • Citing Article
  • January 1997

Science

... The error which we are mainly concerned with is the subject relative pronoun deletion from a relative clause which modifies an indefinite noun of a post-verbal noun phrase (NP) even though the same structure is termed Determiner Phrase (DP) or (AgrP, in more recent works) in a sentence like "Jack is a student Ø doesn't come late" committed in the written work by Arabic speakers of English as a foreign language. This error, in addition to other types of errors in English relative clauses, has been observed in many earlier works, some for pedagogical purposes such as that of Yorkey (1977), Scott and Tucker (1974), Schachter (1974), Hamdallah and Tushyeh (1995), while others such as Lambrecht (1988), Chomsky (1995), Duffield (2009), Fox (2003, and Collins (2015), deal with various theoretical aspects of the relative clause since it is a global structure subject to various processes and/or constraints. Our main concern in this work will concentrate on both the contrastive analyses and the theoretical aspects of the relative clause as they pertain to the problem which our students face, namely the absence of the relative clause subject from English sentences when the relative clause describes an indefinite noun in the post-verbal position of the matrix sentence. ...

50 years later: Reflections on Chomsky's Aspects

... In his recent response to Sun's (2021) bipartite analysis of the zhǐyǒu…Ø EXCL construction, Hole (2023) effectively upholds the Spec-Head analysis on the ScalP. Moreover, he introduces a featural account within the framework of Pesetsky and Torrego (2007). This framework allows features to exhibit four possible combinations along the dimensions of valued-unvalued and interpretable-uninterpretable. ...

The syntax of valuation and the interpretability of features
  • Citing Chapter
  • January 2007

... Unfortunately, many Japanese individuals struggle with English after years of study. One important reason is the difficulty in distinguishing speech sounds that are not part of the Japanese language (e.g., /l/ and /r/) [1][2][3][4][5]. This ability is very important for speech perception and for improving English proficiency. ...

Brain mechanisms of speech perception: A preliminary report

... Before moving to the proposal, I want to outline some of the ancillary assumptions that I will be adopting. First, I assume that all syntactic operations-Agree and Merge (both internal and external)-are feature driven (Svenonius 1994;Adger 2003;Lechner 2004;Pesetsky and Torrego 2006;Heck and Müller 2007;Müller 2010, a.o.). In particular, following Heck and Müller (2007) and Müller (2010), I assume that features come into two classes depending on the operations that they trigger: structure building features responsible for Merge, and probe features that participate in Agree operations. ...

Probes, goals and syntactic categories
  • Citing Article
  • January 2006

... The existence of some form of music faculty has support across a number of disciplines, such as neuroimaging (e.g., Griffiths & Frackowiak, 1998;Patterson et al., 2002;Zatorre et al., 2002;Tavalage et al., 2004;Yost, 2009;Oxenham, 2012;Nunes-Silva & Hasse, 2013;Norman-Haignere et al., 2015), neuropsychology (e.g., Peretz & Coltheart, 2003;Peretz & Zatorre, 2005;Peretz, 2006Peretz, , 2009, and philosophy (e.g., Fodor, 1983;Schneider 2011). In music theory and cognitive science, Patel (2008), Katz and Pesetsky (2011) and Lerdahl (2013) invoke weak forms of music faculty, which comprise shared capacities or shared neural structure between music and natural language systems, and possibly other perceptual or cognitive systems. However, concept assembly in music using MC involves dissimilar entities and processes from those of natural language, so the extent of shared neural circuitry for these activities may be questioned prima facie, even if some operations are broadly parallel (Rawbone, 2021). ...

The Identity Thesis for Language and Music