Daniel M. Wegner’s research while affiliated with Cambridge and other places

What is this page?


This page lists works of an author who doesn't have a ResearchGate profile or hasn't added the works to their profile yet. It is automatically generated from public (personal) data to further our legitimate goal of comprehensive and accurate scientific recordkeeping. If you are this author and want this page removed, please let us know.

Publications (142)


Das Google-Gedächtnis
  • Chapter

March 2017

·

40 Reads

Daniel M. Wegner

·

Adrian F. Ward

Früher haben wir Freunde und Bekannte gefragt, wenn wir Rat oder Informationen brauchten. Heute suchen wir rasch im Internet und finden Antworten auf so ziemlich alle Lebensfragen. Dieser Kulturwandel wirkt sich auf unser Gedächtnis uns Selbstbild aus.



Does the Robot Have a Mind? Mind Perception and Attitudes Towards Robots Predict Use of an Eldercare Robot
  • Article
  • Full-text available

January 2014

·

432 Reads

·

186 Citations

International Journal of Social Robotics

·

·

·

[...]

·

Robots are starting to be developed for aged care populations and some of these have been made into commercial products that have been well received. However, little is known about the psychological factors that promote acceptance or rejection of robots by older people. Finding out more about these psychological determinants of robot uptake and acceptance is the primary focus of the study described in this paper. A healthcare robot feasibility study was conducted in a retirement village. Older people (n=25) were invited to use a prototype robot with healthcare functions over a two week period. Questionnaires were completed before and after the period. It was found that residents who held significantly more positive attitudes towards robots, and perceived robot minds to have less agency (ability to do things) were more likely to use the robot. It was also found that attitudes towards robots improved over time in robot-users. Our results suggest that the cognitions older people hold about robots may influence their decisions to use robots. The study results also validate participants’ subjective self-reports of attitudes towards robots and perceptions of robot mind, against the objective measure of robot use. Interventions to foster adaptive cognitions could be developed and applied in the design, deployment and marketing of robots to promote their use and acceptance.

Download


Figure 1: Relationship between mind-blanking, mind-wandering, and reading comprehension, under both self-paced and auto-scrolling conditions in Experiment 2c.
Figure 2: Average incidence of mind-blanking, mind-wandering, and focusing on external stimuli in Experiment 1.
Table 3 | Means and SDs of conscious states in Experiment 2a.
Table 4 | Experimental design of Experiments 3a, 3b, and 3c.
Mind-blanking: When the mind goes away

September 2013

·

2,338 Reads

·

100 Citations

People often feel like their minds and their bodies are in different places. Far from an exotic experience, this phenomenon seems to be a ubiquitous facet of human life (e.g., Killingsworth and Gilbert, 2010). Many times, people's minds seem to go "somewhere else"-attention becomes disconnected from perception, and people's minds wander to times and places removed from the current environment (e.g., Schooler et al., 2004). At other times, however, people's minds may seem to go nowhere at all-they simply disappear. This mental state-mind-blanking-may represent an extreme decoupling of perception and attention, one in which attention fails to bring any stimuli into conscious awareness. In the present research, we outline the properties of mind-blanking, differentiating this mental state from other mental states in terms of phenomenological experience, behavioral outcomes, and underlying cognitive processes. Seven experiments suggest that when the mind seems to disappear, there are times when we have simply failed to monitor its whereabouts-and there are times when it is actually gone.


Six Guidelines for Interesting Research

September 2013

·

2,734 Reads

·

32 Citations

Perspectives on Psychological Science

There are many guides on proper psychology, but far fewer on interesting psychology. This article presents six guidelines for interesting research. The first three-Phenomena First, Be Surprising, and Grandmothers, Not Scientists-suggest how to choose your research question; the last three-Be The Participant, Simple Statistics, and Powerful Beginnings-suggest how to answer your research question and offer perspectives on experimental design, statistical analysis, and effective communication. These guidelines serve as reminders that replicability is necessary but not sufficient for compelling psychological science. Interesting research considers subjective experience; it listens to the music of the human condition. © The Author(s) 2013.


Robots with Display Screens: A Robot with a More Humanlike Face Display Is Perceived To Have More Mind and a Better Personality

August 2013

·

1,824 Reads

·

236 Citations

It is important for robot designers to know how to make robots that interact effectively with humans. One key dimension is robot appearance and in particular how humanlike the robot should be. Uncanny Valley theory suggests that robots look uncanny when their appearance approaches, but is not absolutely, human. An underlying mechanism may be that appearance affects users' perceptions of the robot's personality and mind. This study aimed to investigate how robot facial appearance affected perceptions of the robot's mind, personality and eeriness. A repeated measures experiment was conducted. 30 participants (14 females and 16 males, mean age 22.5 years) interacted with a Peoplebot healthcare robot under three conditions in a randomized order: the robot had either a humanlike face, silver face, or no-face on its display screen. Each time, the robot assisted the participant to take his/her blood pressure. Participants rated the robot's mind, personality, and eeriness in each condition. The robot with the humanlike face display was most preferred, rated as having most mind, being most humanlike, alive, sociable and amiable. The robot with the silver face display was least preferred, rated most eerie, moderate in mind, humanlikeness and amiability. The robot with the no-face display was rated least sociable and amiable. There was no difference in blood pressure readings between the robots with different face displays. Higher ratings of eeriness were related to impressions of the robot with the humanlike face display being less amiable, less sociable and less trustworthy. These results suggest that the more humanlike a healthcare robot's face display is, the more people attribute mind and positive personality characteristics to it. Eeriness was related to negative impressions of the robot's personality. Designers should be aware that the face on a robot's display screen can affect both the perceived mind and personality of the robot.


The Harm-Made Mind: Observing Victimization Augments Attribution of Minds to Vegetative Patients, Robots, and the Dead

June 2013

·

182 Reads

·

85 Citations

Psychological Science

People often think that something must have a mind to be part of a moral interaction. However, the present research suggests that minds do not create morality but that morality creates minds. In four experiments, we found that observing intentional harm to an unconscious entity-a vegetative patient, a robot, or a corpse-leads to augmented attribution of mind to that entity. A fifth experiment reconciled these results with extant research on dehumanization by showing that observing the victimization of conscious entities leads to reduced attribution of mind to those entities. Taken together, these experiments suggest that the effects of victimization vary according to victims' preexisting mental status and that people often make an intuitive cognitive error when unconscious entities are placed in harm's way. People assume that if apparent moral harm occurs, then there must be someone there to experience that harm-a harm-made mind. These findings have implications for political policies concerning right-to-life issues.


Feeling Robots and Human Zombies: Mind Perception and the Uncanny Valley

July 2012

·

1,255 Reads

·

675 Citations

Cognition

The uncanny valley-the unnerving nature of humanlike robots-is an intriguing idea, but both its existence and its underlying cause are debated. We propose that humanlike robots are not only unnerving, but are so because their appearance prompts attributions of mind. In particular, we suggest that machines become unnerving when people ascribe to them experience (the capacity to feel and sense), rather than agency (the capacity to act and do). Experiment 1 examined whether a machine's humanlike appearance prompts both ascriptions of experience and feelings of unease. Experiment 2 tested whether a machine capable of experience remains unnerving, even without a humanlike appearance. Experiment 3 investigated whether the perceived lack of experience can also help explain the creepiness of unfeeling humans and philosophical zombies. These experiments demonstrate that feelings of uncanniness are tied to perceptions of experience, and also suggest that experience-but not agency-is seen as fundamental to humans, and fundamentally lacking in machines.


Action Identification Theory

January 2012

·

14,481 Reads

·

200 Citations

R o b i n R . V a l l a c h e r a n d D a n i e l M . W e g n e r ABSTRACT The theory of action identification is a system of three principles explaining how people's thoughts of what they are doing relate to what they do. In a sense, the principles suggest an "operating system" for a human being – a program linking thought to action. The principles suggest simply that people do what they think they are doing, that when they can think of doing something more, they do that – but that when they can't do what they were thinking of doing, they think of doing less. Stated this way, the principles may seem perhaps too simple, but their interaction and ramifications are remarkably complex and predictive of a rich array of phenomena. The theory has things to say about how people can conceptualize their actions optimally, it offers insights into how people regulate actions through thinking, it provides a template for understanding how action connects to emotion and to self-concept, and it suggests how social influence occurs by changing how actions are understood. These consequences of the theory were discovered early on, but have recently been supplemented by extensions to encompass the dynamics of action and the role of action identification in the understanding of own and others' minds.


Citations (96)


... Similar to our results, Demanet et al. (2013) found that participants experienced stronger temporal action (and effect) binding when participants exerted greater physical effort (stretching a strong elastic band) compared to less effort (stretching a weaker band) during an operant task where they could produce an auditory effect with a button press. While this physical effort may not be directly comparable to the cognitive effort required for anti-saccades, some researchers propose that effort arises from an abstract sense that integrates signals from different modalities (Preston & Wegner, 2009). These authors reason 'that the experience of effort gives intentional actions their unique phenomenological signature and thus reinforces the subjective experience of being in control' (Demanet et al., 2013, p. 576). ...

Reference:

The impact of the degree of action voluntariness on sense of agency in saccades
Elbow Grease: When Action Feels Like Work
  • Citing Chapter
  • October 2008

... This theory states that negative (self)beliefs are partly suppressed into the subconscious (55). Addressing beliefs for instance through measurement with stereotypical statements has the potential to increase individuals' awareness of them and hence can result in higher scores over time (56). An explanation for why this effect did not appear in the other subscales (Awareness and Agreement) is that the latter two scales measure 'general' beliefs, the subscale "Agreement" aims to measure the agreement with commonly held stereotypes about individuals with mental health problems and the subscale of Awareness measures the knowledge of common mental health stereotypes in society. ...

Covering Up What Can't Be Seen: Concealable Stigma and Mental Control

Journal of Personality and Social Psychology

... Besides this predictive component of the SoA Schwarz et al., 2018Schwarz et al., , 2022, agents can also experience SoA for outcomes they did not predict (e.g., Ramachandran & Rogers- Ramachandran, 1997), and this may foster the acquisition of novel action-effect contingencies. Thus, there is likely also a postdictive component to the SoA, such that agents employ explicit reasoning processes to determine whether their action caused an effect in the environment (Liesner et al., 2020;Synofzik et al., 2008;Wegner, 2003;Wegner & Wheatley, 1999). Postdictive SoA experience is shaped by various factors. ...

Apparent Mental Causation

American Psychologist

... Last, passive monitoring is a passive strategy that involves monitoring thought occurrences in mind with minimized volitional control and can serve as a neutral control condition for the active strategies (Lavy & van den Hout, 1990). Wegner and Smart (1997) suggested that acceptance should be more effective than suppression in controlling UITs. In a deep activation hypothesis of suppression, a suppressed UIT is argued to become consciously absent but subconsciously primed in mind. ...

Deep Cognitive Activation: A New Approach to the Unconscious

Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology

... The languaging perspective enables one to treat embodied, historical and verbal aspects of languaging as equally necessary and irreducible to each other. The perspective is inseparable from knowing as the latter emerges mainly from people's linguistic activities through interlocking the actions of the other, which Wegner and Sparrow (2007) call 'coaction'. In their understanding, coaction occurs when 'one agent's action is influenced by or occurs in the context of another agent's action' (18). ...

The Puzzle of Coaction
  • Citing Chapter
  • July 2007

... Taken together, our study informs current theorizing on the underlying mechanisms and effects of action-outcome learning in individual and joint action settings and provides novel evidence that co-actors tend to form group-level representations of their joint actions if afforded by given task constraints. 10 Notably, this idea would be in line with Vallacher and Wegner's (1985, 1987 theory of action identification which formulates basic principles of how people conceptualize their actions. The theory assumes that people can conceptualize their actions at different hierarchical levels of abstractions, ranging from lower-level interpretations related to specific movements they perform to higher-level interpretations related to more distal ends of their actions. ...

A Theory of Action Identification
  • Citing Book
  • April 2014

... Based on past work arguing morality is inherently social [48,49] and moral judgment is highly sensitive to the situation, context, and social consensus [18,19,25,26], we hypothesized that FoMO and social setting would influence moral judgments by decreasing the severity. Supporting that prediction, we observed that higher FoMO predicted less severe judgments-judgments shifted closer to neutral. ...

Morality takes two: Dyadic morality and mind perception.
  • Citing Chapter
  • January 2012

... Multiple perspectives suggest that concealment can trigger distressing self-reflections and rumination over an extended period (Kelly 2002). Secret-keepers might find themselves caught in a self-sustaining cycle of obsessive preoccupation, even when not actively engaging in concealment behaviors (Wegner and Lane 1995). Concealment also entails restraining one's behaviors, thoughts, and feelings, which could act as cumulative stressors (Pennebaker 1989) and consume The duration between two consecutive waves was 2 weeks. ...

From secrecy to psychopathology.
  • Citing Chapter
  • January 1995

... While in a depressive state, individuals fail to find pleasure or happiness from their surrounding environment (American Psychiatric Association, 2013); they even struggle with recalling memories in which they were happy (Lloyd and Lishman, 1975). Prompting them to shift from self-blame to happiness is unlikely to be successful, in fact, in most cases, it would result in a deterioration of mood (Wegner et al., 1993). However, we hypothesized that shifting from self-blame to sadness and later to longing might be, not only more intuitive, as these feelings are all shades of negative emotions, but also beneficial. ...

Ironic Processes in the Mental Control of Mood and Mood-Related Thought

Journal of Personality and Social Psychology

... Interestingly, perceived premeditation may stem from any anticipation-like mental content (such as foresight, effortful forethought, wishful thinking, and the consideration of multiple possible outcomes of action). Therefore, such actions would lead people to feel responsible for those outcomes and to think that they are under personal control [64]. This counterfeit perception of self-responsibility and personal control may occur despite the obvious irrelevance of premeditation and overt behaviors, and despite the absence of any causal relationship between premeditation and observed outcomes [64]. ...

Perish the Forethought: Premeditation Engenders Misperceptions of Personal Control

SSRN Electronic Journal