Dan Priel’s research while affiliated with The Graduate Center, CUNY and other places

What is this page?


This page lists works of an author who doesn't have a ResearchGate profile or hasn't added the works to their profile yet. It is automatically generated from public (personal) data to further our legitimate goal of comprehensive and accurate scientific recordkeeping. If you are this author and want this page removed, please let us know.

Publications (31)


Jurisprudence and Psychology
  • Chapter

January 2011

·

611 Reads

·

1 Citation

Dan Priel

Psychology, the study of the mind, was until late in the nineteenth century considered part of philosophy. An important catalyst in it gaining independence was when researchers in the field began adopting the experimental methods of the natural sciences. Fairly quickly, a gulf was created between the psychologists, who increasingly turned to ‘external’ means of enquiry, and the philosophers who continued to rely on introspection.1 These methods soon led to opposed substantive paradigms to the explanation of human nature: in psychology, behaviourism was the leading theory of the day; in philosophy it was theories that emphasised ‘understanding’, the examination of the workings of human reason as understood from ‘within’.


Jurisprudence and Psychology

November 2010

·

143 Reads

·

2 Citations

SSRN Electronic Journal

I argue that much of the work in analytic jurisprudence has been concerned with two questions that have not been adequately distinguished: (a) an inquiry about the concept of law, and (b) an explanation of the important features of the practice of law. It is often assumed that the two inquiries are the same. In this essay I distinguish the two and argue that work in psychology provides important insights about both. With regard to the first, I argue that much jurisprudential conceptual analysis is challenged by psychological work on concepts. With regard to the second, I argue that legal theorists would benefit from greater attention to what people’s ‘internal’ attitudes about law are by looking at psychological research on the matter. But psychology is not merely a challenge to contemporary jurisprudence: following the critique I suggest various ways psychological work can assist us in thinking on old jurisprudential questions like the dispute between positivism and natural law or the question of law’s normativity.


Description and Evaluation in Jurisprudence

November 2010

·

126 Reads

·

10 Citations

Law and Philosophy

In the last three decades or so a prominent view among legal philosophers has been that while legal theory is evaluative because it requires making judgments of importance, it can remain morally neutral. This view, which I call the ‘orthodox view’, was first articulated by Joseph Raz and has since been supported by many other prominent legal philosophers. In this essay I examine it, and argue that it is indefensible. I begin by examining the terms ‘description’ and ‘evaluation’, and show that they are ambiguous in a way that most current discussion does not realize. I then rely on this analysis to develop several arguments against the orthodox view. I argue that defenders of the orthodox view have considered only one such argument, and that even with regard to this one their response is unsuccessful.


The Scientific Model of Jurisprudence

September 2010

·

21 Reads

·

9 Citations

SSRN Electronic Journal

I argue in this essay that the popular “descriptive” approach to jurisprudence can be modeled after attempts at explaining natural phenomena by scientists. I present four assumptions that are underlying this approach to jurisprudence, which are similar to those of natural scientists. I then argue, however, that in the case of jurisprudence (and unlike the natural sciences) these assumptions contradict each other. After presenting my case I respond to several potential replies to my argument. If my arguments are correct, this shows that jurisprudential descriptivism is not just, as some have argued, unimportant, but rather that it is impossible. The suggests that those who claim to offer an account of the “nature” of law are in fact doing something else.


A Public Role for the Intentional Torts

September 2010

·

147 Reads

·

4 Citations

King's law journal: KLJ

The recent litigation that ended in the House of Lords’ decision in Ashley v. Chief Constable of Sussex Police has brought the intentional torts back to the focus of judicial attention. Most commentary on this decision has focused on a few dicta that purport to support a reading the decision as concerned with private vindication of rights. In this article I examine this decision against a broad shift that has been taking place within tort law, and in particular the tort of negligence, away from ‘private law’ concern with the particular individuals involved in the litigation and towards broader ‘public’ concerns. After describing this shift in the case of negligence, I consider three possible private law interpretations of the role of the intentional torts. I argue that they are all deficient. I then highlight an aspect of Ashley that has been ignored by other commentators and which fits the public interpretation of tort law. I argue that this aspect provides a more convincing explanation for the decision, and one that aligns the intentional torts with the rest of tort law.


British Politics, the Welfare State, and Tort Liability of Public Authorities

July 2010

·

19 Reads

SSRN Electronic Journal

There has been a notable shift in the scope of negligence liability of public authorities in the Post War period. Notably there was a trend toward restriction of liability in the 1980s. This essay tries to explain why this happened not by focusing on changing legal formulas but by examining the political context of the law in this area. I begin the essay by demonstrating how changes in the attitudes toward the role of the state have led to the changes in the law in this area. I then go on to examine the impact of Thatcher’s ascent to power. Some commentators have suggested that the restriction in liability that took place during the years of her premiership was the result of the impact of Thatcherite ideology on the courts. I consider why such an ideology might be used (and has been used) to justify restriction of liability on public authorities, but argue that such arguments are quite different from those actually found in court decisions at the time. Though founded on ideas that may also be called broadly ‘conservative’, they do not reflect the distrust of state institutions typical in New Right writings, but are rather based on great respect for them, a view that reflects a different strand of conservatism. I demonstrate this attitude from the cases and offer some explanations for its possible adoption by the courts.


Jurisprudence Between Science and the Humanities

March 2010

·

152 Reads

·

7 Citations

SSRN Electronic Journal

For a long time philosophy has been unique among the humanities for seeking closer alliance with the sciences. In this essay I examine the place of science in the context of jurisprudential debates, in particular in the context of the idea known as legal positivism. I argue that historically legal positivism has been advanced by theorists who were also positivists in the sense the term is used in the philosophy of social science, i.e. they were committed to the idea that the explanation of social phenomena should be conducted using similar methods to those used in the natural sciences. I then argue that around the 1960’s jurisprudence and in particular legal positivism have undergone change towards anti-positivism. Central to this trend was the idea that proper jurisprudential inquiry must be conducted from the “internal point of view.” What this view amounted to was an attempt combine a scientific-like aim of neutral description with a humanistic method of inquiry. It thus did not entirely abandon its links with scientific inquiry, but has radically changed their nature. I show that this stance had a negative impact of narrowing down the range of issues discussed and of the kind of method considered appropriate for discussing these questions, I then argue that to counter current these isolationist trends jurisprudence would benefit from reorientation of its midway position between science and the humanities in the opposite direction: its aims should be those traditionally associated with the humanities but its methodology should be much closer to that of the sciences.


The Place of Legitimacy in Legal Theory

March 2010

·

26 Reads

·

14 Citations

McGill Law Journal

In this essay I argue that to understand debates in jurisprudence one needs to distinguish clearly between four concepts: validity, content, normativity, and legitimacy. More specifically I show that debates between legal positivists and Dworkin should be understood not, as it is often said, as debates on the conditions of validity, but rather as debates on the right way of understanding the relationship between these four concepts. After presenting the two different ways in which legal positivists and Dworkin understand this relationship, I argue that the Dworkinian approach is superior to the positivist one. The positivist account begins with an attempt to explain the conditions of validity and to leave the question of assessment of valid legal norms to the second stage of inquiry. But though appealing, I argue that the notion of validity cannot be given sense outside a preliminary consideration of legitimacy.


Forty Years On

February 2008

·

18 Reads

SSRN Electronic Journal

Since the 1960's Ronald Dworkin has been arguing for a particular account of law that he believed was both explanatorily superior to the one offered by competing theories, and also the basis for normative arguments for producing right answers to legal questions. Justice in Robes collects Dworkin's most recent essays on this subject and thus provides the appropriate opportunity for assessing the legal theory of one of the more influential legal philosophers. In this Review I seek to offer a clearer account than appears in the book itself of Dworkin's project, and in this way offer a measured assessment of his work. My argument shows that there has been significant misunderstanding of Dworkin's project and that once it is cleared we can see that Dworkin's questions are not so far apart from those of other legal theorists. This approach has another benefit, as it ties together Dworkin's disparate discussions in Justice in Robes into a more coherent whole. Once the structure of Dworkin's argument is clarified, I move on to examine the details of his argument. Here, I argue, his arguments are often less convincing. Nevertheless, I argue, this need not lead us to wholesale rejection of his theory. I show how his ideas make more sense within a broader account of law that shows the limited but undeniable sense in which his arguments are correct, and inform our understanding of legal practice.


Free-Floating from Reality

February 2008

·

25 Reads

·

1 Citation

SSRN Electronic Journal

The paper considers Matthew Kramer's notion of free-floating norms as a way of defending inclusive legal positivism. I argue first that there are numerous counterexamples to Kramer's approach. I then go on to argue that Kramer's approach represents a prevalent, yet mistaken, approach in contemporary legal philosophy of trying to answer empirical questions by conceptual arguments. I conclude that this approach should be abandoned.


Citations (10)


... Literary writers try to decipher the concept of freedom from philosophical perspectives, legal, social, and psychological perspectives (Saliba, 1991). Freedom can be established as a relationship between one and the other with constraints, 'free to' versus 'freedom from' (Priel, 2013;Callister, 2017). Current freedom ideations are separated into positive and negative angles. ...

Reference:

Cognitive Transcendence
Lon Fuller's Political Jurisprudence of Freedom
  • Citing Article
  • December 2014

Jerusalem Review of Legal Studies

... 177 Juristic commentary since Anns v Merton London Borough Council 178 reveals unease at a tort attempting to define the relationship between public authority and individuals. 179 Furthermore, judicial treatment of the tort also underwent significant shifts in approach that mirrored changes in dominant political ideologies. 180 It is unsurprising the tort is often labelled unprincipled and incoherent. ...

The Indirect Influence of Politics on Tort Liability of Public Authorities in English Law
  • Citing Article
  • March 2013

Law & Society Review

... After a century of legal scholarship, the public/private distinction remains key to organising law school curriculums; there is also evidence of a recent move by some legal scholars towards the contention that such a divide is somehow fundamental to English law (Priel, 2013). Hopefully, the addition of this empirically rich and historically adept work to the canon of legal critiques of the public/private divide would go some way towards disturbing its resilience. ...

The Political Origins of English Private Law
  • Citing Article
  • April 2013

Journal of Law and Society

... In other words, this thesis does not need to make an argument as to whether it is possible to identify necessarily true features of law or adequate explanations of its nature, 1048 or whether we ought to use the standard of truth to evaluate the results of 1048 For a useful overview of this literature, see Priel 2007. jurisprudential inquiries. ...

Jurisprudence and Necessity
  • Citing Article
  • June 2007

Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence

... This has been tied to the management reforms (Hirvonen 2014), but it also could be argued that it links back to the idea and ideals of public servantry and to legal liberal epistemologies (Mik-Meyer 2017). The law in this framework of understanding is understood as disembodied, abstract, and neutral (Fineman 2013;Kearns and Sarat 1998;Priel 2012;Hirvonen, 2014), and social workers are expected to adhere to the political goals and values of the state and the municipality even when these values are not in congruence with professional ethics and personal values (Larsen, 2011 ...

The Scientific Model of Jurisprudence
  • Citing Article
  • September 2010

SSRN Electronic Journal

... Its opponents-the number of whom grew progressively from the mid-nineteenth century-saw the deplorable effect of the legal positivism in the narrowness of a purely normative analysis that stripped legal science of many important insights and dimensions which could help better explain the machinery of the law. This perspective proved to be disadvantageous not only for legal scholars, who could easily find historical or anthropological examples refuting this positivist paradigm, but also for legal practitioners who faced many aspects of social life which were regulated legally but not by the state law. 4 These disadvantages of the legal positivism unsurprisingly suggested the need to work out new, more flexible perspectives of legal thinking based on interdisciplinary approaches (Priel 2015). ...

Towards Classical Legal Positivism
  • Citing Article
  • July 2011

SSRN Electronic Journal

... The mechanism of the civil trial may also provide an outlet for the anger and frustration of victims, particularly in the face of denials of liability by defendants, 26 and allow for a public dissection of the wrongful conduct. 27 While the realities of the litigation process often diminish the force of such arguments, notably the fact that most tort cases are settled before trial, 28 an award of compensation, even if based on a settlement, is likely to have significance to a victim of abuse beyond the monetary. As Case has observed: a compensation award does more than provide financial recompense for the economic disadvantages which abuse and psychiatric injury have inflicted, it also performs a subset of functions; damages have symbolic force as, inter alia, an expression of the wrong done to the claimant and a vindication of the claimant's character. ...

A Public Role for the Intentional Torts
  • Citing Article
  • September 2010

King's law journal: KLJ

... Referring back to Table 1 and Fig. 1, empiricism instead best captures the epistemological position of legal positivism. Legal positivists prioritise empirical data exclusively, often (at least in the earlier days) of natural science genre (Priel 2012). For the reasons already made about the convergent epistemologies, empiricism also commits to other philosophies. ...

Jurisprudence Between Science and the Humanities
  • Citing Article
  • March 2010

SSRN Electronic Journal

... [35] Counteracting the gender legality of heteronormative male dominance on the monopoly of force, the legitimacy of LGBTQIA + justice hence universality of legitimacy is the fundamental being. [36] [37] Competitive machoism is key to the dictatorial psychology. In a fortiori nationalism, gender a priori syntaxes of the LGBTQIA + population is effective in overwriting the machoism psychopathy in ontological intersubjectivity. ...

The Place of Legitimacy in Legal Theory
  • Citing Article
  • March 2010

McGill Law Journal

... In applying this idea, however, the two authors seem to take a different route. The former quotation, written by a psychologist, comes from a book that put 23 Criticised in Priel (2007a Priel ( , 2010). 24 I do not claim that Robinson and Leiter's respective ideas are identical; there is considerable difference in focus between the two books, and the seventy-odd years between them clearly show their mark. ...

Description and Evaluation in Jurisprudence
  • Citing Article
  • November 2010

Law and Philosophy