October 2014
·
6 Reads
Mind
This page lists works of an author who doesn't have a ResearchGate profile or hasn't added the works to their profile yet. It is automatically generated from public (personal) data to further our legitimate goal of comprehensive and accurate scientific recordkeeping. If you are this author and want this page removed, please let us know.
October 2014
·
6 Reads
Mind
July 2014
·
101 Reads
·
2 Citations
Criminal Law and Philosophy
We discuss and respond to the contributions of Tatjana Hörnle, John Kleinig, and John Stanton-Ife, and clarify some aspects of the arguments made in Crimes, Harms, and Wrongs.
March 2014
·
87 Reads
·
1 Citation
The Cambridge Law Journal
January 2014
·
39 Reads
·
2 Citations
Criminal Law and Philosophy
This paper responds to Antje du-Bois Pedain’s discussion of the wrongfulness constraint on the criminal law. Du-Bois Pedain argues that the constraint is best interpreted as stating that φing is legitimately criminalised only if φing is wrongful for other-regarding reasons. We take issue with du-Bois Pedain’s arguments. In our view, it is neither a necessary nor sufficient condition of legitimate criminalisation that φing is wrongful in du-Bois Pedain’s sense. Rather, it is a necessary (albeit insufficient) condition of legitimate criminalisation that φing is what we call bare wrongful—that is, that the reasons in favour of φing are defeated by the reasons against. Though du-Bois Pedain is critical of this view, we argue that her criticisms do not convince.
January 2013
·
51 Reads
·
5 Citations
This chapter addresses the differences between justifications and excuses, their respective characters and basic structures. It argues that justifications and 'rationale-based' excuses such as duress are fundamentally similar, and that their differences have relatively few implications for the criminal law. It is often claimed that justifications are 'about the act' and excuses 'about the actor': but they are about both - and equally so. Both rationalebased excuses and justifications are personal, and impersonal, alike to the actor. While their differences track a categorical moral distinction about the normative status of an agent's conduct, the main driver of that difference is whether the agent's rationale for acting was, or was not, what Raz calls an 'excluded' reason. If not excluded, a justification may well lie. Even if excluded, it may ground an excuse. So there are key differences in how, morally speaking, the defendant's rationale is relevant to her exculpation. But that same rationale leads in either case to blameless acquittal. The starting point is the same. The end point is the same. There are some idiosyncratic stop signs, but basically the difference is the routes. It is argued that there is no fundamental difference of output in the criminal law, at least for individual defendants. Rather, from the perspective of the law, the main differential consequence regards actions by the state. State action may be justifiable, but it is inexcusable.
January 2013
·
52 Reads
·
7 Citations
Many criminal theorists agree that conviction of a criminal offence, or at least of a stigmatic criminal offence, should not normally occur unless the accused is culpable with respect to that offence. Not everyone thinks this. Some writers, for example, hold that once an offender goes through a ‘gateway’ of wrongdoing, she may legitimately be held criminally liable for consequences that flow from her initial wrongful action, without being culpable specifically for those further consequences. Indeed, similar thinking lies behind traditional doctrines of felony-murder. But even those writers generally accept that the offender should in principle be culpable with respect to the initial action. There must, they agree, be some culpability, somewhere, to legitimate conviction for a serious criminal offence. My concern in this chapter is with the underlying question: when is a person culpable? Conventionally, the ascription of culpability or blame is thought to rest upon findings of mens rea. And it is certainly true that mens rea elements have a role to play in establishing culpability. Yet how they do so remains obscure. Part of the problem is that many existing accounts seek a comprehensive but false unity. They tend not to separate positive from negative criteria; responsibility from culpability; capacity-based from circumstance-based exculpations; and, most importantly of all, choice-based accounts from other explanations of blame. As we shall see, a less integrated approach, with two alternative bases of culpability, may be more perspicuous.
July 2012
·
33 Reads
·
1 Citation
Just as in the Indian Penal Code, the intoxication provisions contained in ss. 85 and 86 of the Singaporean and Malaysian Penal Codes are described as ‘General Exceptions’, suggesting that they operate as affirmative (or ‘supervening’) substantive-law defences to criminal liability. It is argued in this article, however, that the primary function of these provisions is not to create a distinct legal defence. Rather, it is to enable the courts to convict persons who do not satisfy the mens rea requireents of a crime, when their lack of mens rea is because of intoxication. The sections permit us to treat such defendants as having mens rea when in fact they do not. As such, the provisions are mainly inculpatory, not exculpatory. They assist the prosecution, not the defendant. This claim will be defended both in principle and in terms of statutory interpretation. This article also discusses certain exceptions, where intoxication does operate as a true supervening defence.
March 2012
·
3 Reads
The Cambridge Law Journal
January 2012
·
600 Reads
·
5 Citations
This article reviews the offence of causing death by driving while uninsured, unlicensed or disqualified and challenges the courts' approach to causation in interpreting the offence. © 2012 Thomson Reuters (Professional) UK Limited and Contributors.
July 2011
·
600 Reads
·
27 Citations
The Cambridge Law Journal
Everyone agrees that mens rea is relevant to fault. The maxim actus non fit reus nisi mens sit rea has been around for centuries.1 According to foundational principles of the criminal law, it is normally not enough to support a conviction that D perpetrates the actus reus. Neither should it be. Causing harm to another person may be unfortunate, but the moral turpitude associated with a criminal conviction requires some element of fault. And to show that, we need mens rea.
... While some states have reported positive results from reduced arrests and a shift to tax-based regulation, others face challenges such as continued racial disparities in enforcement and the fact that marijuana is still illegal under federal law. In December 2013, Uruguay became the first country to legalize the sale, cultivation, and distribution of recreational marijuana, a move that has brought it to the forefront of the list of countries and states in the United States that have liberalized marijuana laws in recent years (Simester, A.P. 2016 services. Each jurisdiction's unique legal framework and societal values strongly influence these outcomes. ...
January 2010
... 172 This was also one of Griew's objections to Ghosh: 'Robin Hood must be a thief even if he thinks the whole of the right-thinking world is on his side.' 173 Yet is this actually the case? If theft is rationalised by reference to a broad conception of the harm principle operating as a mechanism for protecting a property right regime, 174 On the other hand, there is considerable strength in Steel's thesis that such an approach overstates the importance of regime protection, and understates the necessity of some sort of felonious thought on the part of the thief, ie dishonesty. 176 On this foundation a Robin Hood defence becomes intelligible, if not actually legitimate. ...
Reference:
Do freegans commit theft?
August 2005
... I believe there are several reasons for defending a utilitarian principle of criminalization. First, although some philosophers, such as Bentham (1781), Hart (1968) 10 and Simester and Sulivan (2000), 11 have accepted something like UPC, none, to my knowledge, has devoted much time to the defense of UPC. Either, like Bentham, they have focused primarily on describing UPC and its applications within the criminal law; or, like Simester and Sullivan, they flag their adherence to something like the UPC without discussing possible objections to it. ...
August 2007
... In this context, the harm caused is not accidental or 'unlucky' but rather a product of a person's conscious choice to engage in risky conduct for which they must take responsibility (Bindon 2006: 176). By committing an offence, their 'normative position' has changed, altering their moral standing and exposing them to liability for any consequence, whether contemplated or not (Sullivan and Simester 2012;Horder 1995: 764). ...
January 2012
... In order to address a similar criticism, proponents of Strict Liability have pointed out that a distinction ought to be made between stigmatising and non-stigmatising offences. If no stigmatisation is attached to causing harm without fault, attributing remedial duties to those who caused harm might be much less problematic (Simester 2005). 15 Similarly, one might point out that the attribution of duties on the basis of benefitting from injustice should not be seen as an attempt to stigmatise the beneficiaries. ...
April 2005
... Simester (2013) 'Getting Drunk in Singapore and Malaysia', Thailand Law Journal 1/16. http://www. ...
July 2012
... 8 This replacement need not be a wholesale revision of the control requirement for all legal wrongs. For an example of a partial revision, see A. P.Simester (2013), and for an example of skepticism about partial revision, seeKing (2009). Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. ...
Reference:
Minding Negligence
January 2013
... 40 For this reason it is perfectly normal to say, in a somewhat abbreviated manner, and as Marcia Baron recently does, that an excuse " is called for only if one has done something wrong " (cf. Baron 2005, 390). Kent Greenawalt 1984, 1898, n. 6 equally mentions that the " natural priority of justification " need not be absolutely observed in the iter of applying the law. ...
January 2013
... But the use of the term "defence" here is imprecise, and to the extent that it implies a supervening defence, it is misleading. 82 In reality, whenever D denies the elements of a crime, she is simply denying the prosecution case against her: she is denying the essential elements of inculpation. Thus, where intoxication rules apply to find liability despite the successful denial of offence elements, this is not about the denial of a defence, this is logically about the construction of a crime. ...
January 2009
Criminal law review (London, England)
... We say, for example, that the United States invaded Iraq in 2004 because it intended to depose Saddam Hussein, and it acted on the belief that Iraq had weapons of mass destruction (e.g. Cryer and Simester 2005). Open any newspaper or history book, and you find claims about what 'Britain', 'the Ministry of Health', or other political institutions want, intend and desire. ...
Reference:
Political Anti-Intentionalism
January 2005
Theoretical Inquiries in Law