Content uploaded by Terrance McConnell
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Terrance McConnell on Sep 19, 2017
Content may be subject to copyright.
Conducting Research Related to Treatment of Alzheimer’s Disease: Ethical Issues
Mary Ann Sevick, ScD, RN, Terrance McConnell, PhD, and Melissa Muender, MA
Sevick, Mary Ann, McConnell, Terrance, Muender, Melissa. “Conducting Research Related to Treatment of
Alzheimer’s Disease: Ethical Issues,” Journal of Gerontological Nursing 29(2) (February 2003), pp. 6-12.
Made available courtesy of Slack, Inc. http://www.slackinc.com/journals.asp
The original publication can be found at http://www.jognonline.com/
***Reprinted with permission. No further reproduction is authorized without written permission from
Slack, Inc. This version of the document is not the version of record. Figures and/or pictures may be
missing from this format of the document.***
Abstract:
Researchers are obligated to protect the rights of study participants. Protecting the rights of patients with
Alzheimer’s disease (AD) is particularly complicated because of the special needs of this patient population, and
the characteristics of developing treatments and technologies. Respecting autonomy and the right to self-
determination are complicated by difficulties associated with assuring competence, understanding, and
voluntariness in the informed consent process. Protecting patients with AD from harm may be complicated
because new treatments have subtle side effects that may be difficult to detect in patients experiencing
communication difficulties. Harm to patients with AD also may occur from withholding proven treatments in
placebo-controlled trials, and in the use of genetic testing. Issues of justice in the allocation of research dollars
and the ability of patients with AD to participate in research are also discussed. By recognizing potential pitfalls,
researchers involved in testing new treatments for patients with AD can take proper steps to assure ethical
treatment of study participants.
Article:
Alzheimer’s disease (AD) is a condition characterized by progressive neurologic degeneration, resulting in
gradual deterioration of memory, language, judgment, and affect. Alzheimer’s disease usually begins around age
60, but onset may occur as early as age 40. The disease currently is estimated to affect more than 4 million
Americans, with 250,000 new cases diagnosed each year. Because of longer life expectancy and the aging of the
“baby boomer” population, 14 million Americans are expected to have AD by the year 2050—an immense social
and economic burden for the next generation (American Health Assistance Foundation, 2000).
There is hope that recent advances in basic and pharmacologic sciences will result in effective treatments for AD.
The National Institutes of Health and the pharmaceutical industry have invested significant resources in
developing new chemical compounds to treat the symptoms or slow the progress of AD, and genetic research
may result in treatments to prevent the disease altogether. The need for testing these products has and will
continue to produce a great demand for clinical trial participants.
The participants in medical research are vulnerable in a number of ways. First, medicine is a very complex field,
which is not easily understood by the average person. Study participants often have neither sufficient knowledge
to determine the best course of action for treating or preventing a disease, nor sufficient knowledge to ascertain
whether participating in research is unduly dangerous. They are dependent on clinician researchers to advise them
correctly.
A second source of vulnerability is a function of the fact that study participants are often patients who have a
problem for which they are seeking treatment. These participants place their lives in the hands of clinician
researchers, trusting they will act in the participants’ best interests. Third, because clinical research often takes
place in a health care setting, researchers are able to obtain sensitive information that may place study
participants at social or economic risk, such as the presence of diseases that could affect productivity and, hence,
employability and insurability. Fourth, clinician researchers, by virtue of their expertise and socioeconomic
status, may be intimidating to patients. Patients may hesitate to exercise their autonomy and, consequently,
acquiesce to all that is requested of them—even when it may not be in their best interests.
Because of these and other recognized vulnerabilities, several codes of ethical standards have been developed
related to the appropriate treatment of human participants in research. These include the Nuremberg Code, the
Declaration of Helsinki (World Medical Organization, 1996), and the Belmont Report (Harrison, 1993; Lurie &
Wolfe, 1999; Shuster, 1998). These codes outline the rights of human participants of research, which can be
summarized into the following three ethical principles:
• Respect for persons.
• Beneficence.
• Justice.
These rights, in turn, imply responsibilities on the part of researchers. The researcher’s job of protecting the rights
of participants who have AD is complicated by the complexity of the disease, that AD results in progressive
neurologic deterioration, and the nature of available diagnostic tools and treatments. This article focuses, in
depth, on the particular responsibilities and challenges faced by investigators in protecting the rights of study
participants with AD.
RESPECTING RESEARCH PARTICIPANTS
Respect for the person requires the researcher to acknowledge the dignity and autonomy of individuals. It also
requires that individuals with diminished autonomy or those who may not be able to speak for themselves (e.g.,
live human fetuses, children, prisoners, the mentally disabled, and those with severe illnesses) receive extra
attention to be sure their rights are protected. The principal way the dignity and autonomy of participants in
research is honored is through the use of full informed consent. There are five basic elements of full informed
consent (Faden & Beauchamp, 1986):
• Disclosure of information.
• Comprehension.
• Voluntariness.
• Competence.
• The decision to participate or not participate.
Disclosure and Comprehension
Disclosure means participants must receive adequate information about the nature of the study, what they will
experience, the risks associated with the experimental treatment, and whether or not they can expect to
experience any benefits as a result of the study. Participants also have the right to know what treatments are
available to them if they do not participate in the study. Comprehension means the researcher has an obligation to
ensure, to the greatest degree possible, participants understand what is disclosed. Voluntariness means
participants have been told they have the right to refuse to participate, or to withdraw from the study at any point
without fear of retribution. The decision to participate or not participate involves the actual authorization to
include the patient in the study.
The informed consent process can be complicated with patients with dementia. In the early stages of AD,
neuronal damage primarily affects the hippocampus of the brain. The hippocampus function in the acquisition of
information stored in long-term memory, and is responsible for transferring recent experiences into long-term
memory. In recruiting a patient with early AD into a study, the investigator may find that the patient appears to
comprehend disclosure of the various aspects of the study. However, they may quickly forget what was
discussed, including that they consented to the study. The researcher must also remember that informed consent
is an ongoing process in which the investigator re-evaluates, over time, the willingness of participants to continue
with a study. However, as discussed in more detail below, ongoing consent in AD patients is complicated by the
progressive mental deterioration that occurs with the disease. In patients who are gradually becoming
incompetent, it is not clear how changing preferences should be honored.
Voluntariness
With informed consent, investigators have an obligation to assure that participation is voluntary. Various
approaches exist to obtain consent to participate in a study. To convince, by providing facts and permitting the
patient to decide based on those facts, is referred to as persuasion. Persuasion is acceptable as long as it is clear to
the participant that they have a right to refuse. Coercion, manipulation, deception, indoctrination, and seduction
may result in patient decisions not consistent with the patient’s considered judgments. These behaviors are
considered unethical (Faden & Beauchamp, 1986).
Because the competence of AD patients is often questioned, researchers may choose not to approach the
participant for consent. Instead, they may proceed directly to a family member or other legal guardian for
authorization to include the patient in the study. Evidence suggests, despite the disease process, people with AD
still have personal values that investigators should respect. Researchers should refrain from “talking around” the
patient as if they do not exist. Such conduct precludes voluntariness, and is demoralizing to patients struggling to
maintain their autonomy.
According to the Ethical Guidelines established by the Alzheimer Society of Canada, “while still capable, the
individual should be given choices and the opportunity to make decisions” (Fisk et al., 1998, p. 244). These
guidelines suggest techniques that can be used to make the decision-making process simpler for patients with
AD, including reducing the number of options presented and reducing more complex decisions into a series of
simple decisions with step-by-step guidance through the stages (Fisk et al., 1998, p. 244).
Competence
Competence usually refers to a legal definition of whether the person has the legal right to make important
decisions. Children younger than 18 are not of legal age to sign an informed consent. Individuals who have
mental illness or significant cognitive disorders (e.g., AD) may be determined incompetent in formal legal
proceedings. If a person is deemed legally incompetent, the researcher is obligated to obtain legal consent from
the next of kin (e.g., spouse, parent, children, siblings), or a legally designated proxy. The proxy participates in
the consent process, and should be guided by their beliefs regarding what the patient would want if competent to
provide consent. Although the proxy may legally provide the consent, the researcher is ultimately responsible for
assuring that decisions made by the third party are contrary neither to the patient’s wishes, nor to the patient’s
best interests (Fisk et al., 1998).
Decision to Participate
In discussing the actual decision to participate or not participate in a clinical study, some ethicists argue that the
researcher has an obligation to be certain that the decision is “authentic” (Faden & Beauchamp, 1986).
Authenticity is a difficult term to define and, perhaps, is best illustrated by providing an example of a behavior
that is not authentic. The following is a hypothetical example of a consent.
Mr. Z is asked to participate in a study to test a new therapy for AD. The new treatment involves gene therapy.
The researcher describes the study protocol, risks, benefits, and alternative therapies to Mr. Z and his daughter.
Mr. Z agrees to participate. He appears to be acting intentionally and to clearly understand the nature of the study.
No coercion is involved. However, Mr. Z’s daughter advises the researcher that Mr. Z had always expressed
strong moral concerns related to genetic manipulation and his religious beliefs precluded such therapies. Mr. Z’s
consent was not consistent with his prior expressed values.
Authenticity is particularly problematic when questioning patients with AD. The type of progressive deterioration
occurring with the disease eventually renders patients unable to possess reflectively held values. Thus, it is quite
common for patients with AD to behave in a manner that is “out-of-character.” Some have suggested using
advanced directives, completed while competent, to determine if individuals may be used as participants in
dementia research. However, serious problems have been raised with this proposal (Berghmans, 1998).
Ethicists disagree about what researchers should do in situations such as these. According to Dworkin (1993), the
best method of respecting Mr. Z’s autonomy is to adhere strictly to his earlier wishes, expressed when he was still
competent. By doing so his personhood is respected as it was, when still intact. However, Dresser
(Dresser, 1986) asserts that decisions affecting a demented person at a given time must speak to the person’s
current point of view. Dresser would argue that Mr. Z has a right to change his preferences. Jaworska (1999)
seeks a middle ground between these two positions—stating that, despite cognitive deterioration, it may be
possible with some patients to assess the extent to which new and seemingly inconsistent preferences are actually
newly formed preferences. Careful questioning of Mr. Z by his daughter may determine the reason for his change
in values. The consistency of expressed preferences may also provide some clues regarding the extent to which
they reflect internally held values. If Mr. Z changes his mind frequently about his willingness to accept gene
therapy, the researcher may be able to assume with some certainty the best way to respect Mr. Z’s wishes is to
honor his preferences expressed when he was still competent.
Some clinician researchers advocate that, when completing advanced directives, patients indicate their
willingness to participate in research protocols and identify a proxy who can make such decisions for them in the
event that their competency is diminished (Sachs, Rhymes, & Cassel, 1993). Proxy or caregiver involvement is
also important from the perspective of adherence. As the disease progresses, researchers will increasingly rely on
others to be certain that the experimental protocol is followed (Fisk et al., 1998).
BENEFICENCE
Researchers are required to protect the welfare of participants. This directive usually takes the form of two moral
principles. The principle of nonmaleficence instructs agents not to cause harm to others. Precepts against killing
and assault are based on this principle. The principle of beneficence counsels agents to promote the welfare of
others. Others’ welfare can be promoted by preventing evil or harm, removing existing evil or harm, and
positively promoting the welfare of others (Faden & Beauchamp, 1986). Four areas in which beneficence is a
particular issue in AD research are:
• When research is not expected to provide direct health benefits for the participants (i.e., nontherapeutic).
• Risks associated with new pharmaceutical treatments.
• Use of placebos in clinical trials.
• Use of genetic tests to screen for risk of AD.
Direct Health Benefits for the Participants
Because researchers handle experimental drugs or treatments, they are often unaware of all of the risks involved.
Thus, by administering experimental treatments, researchers may cause unforeseen harm. Researchers are
obligated to guard against potential harm by making their best efforts to identify possible adverse events, and
determine the probability that participants will encounter such events. This is conducted through Phase I studies,
when available, or through careful review of the literature and consultation with clinicians and scientists who
have knowledge about the drug or treatment under investigation. The researcher must then make a judgment
regarding the extent to which the research goals sought justify the identified risks. In biomedical ethics literature,
this is referred to as the “benefit–risk ratio” in which the investigator must weigh and balance probable risks and
benefits to be gained from the research.
According to Faden and Beauchamp (1986), the researcher’s obligation to “do no harm” is not a pledge never to
cause harm to study participants, but rather to be certain the potential benefits to be gained by the research
outweigh the risks involved. For all known and anticipated risks identified, the researcher is obligated to guard
against potential problems. A research protocol should be developed including:
• Screening criteria eliminating individuals for whom the intervention would not be advised.
• Monitoring procedures for adverse events or side effects among study participants for as long as
participants are deemed at-risk.
• Specific strategies for handling adverse events or side effects, such as criteria for dropping participants
from a study or treatment plans for handling problems that arise.
Some institutions carry insurance to reimburse participants for adverse health events resulting from clinical
investigations. Depending on the type of study, a Data Safety Monitoring Board (DSMB) may be formed. The
DSMB consists of researchers and clinicians not affiliated with the clinical study. They provide oversight to the
statistical, medical, and ethical aspects of the study through periodic review of interim data on trial performance,
treatment safety, and treatment efficacy (Hawkins, 1991; Wittes, 1993).
Risks Associated with New Drugs
According to Whitehouse (1996), in considering the development of new drugs for AD it is helpful to think in
terms of short-, intermediate-, and long-term approaches. The first category consists of drugs currently on the
market for symptomatic treatment of AD. These include cholinesterase inhibitors such as tacrine, donepezil, and
rivastigmine (Lemiere, Van Gool, & Dom, 1999; Rosler et al., 1999; Whitehouse, 1996). The intermediate
category consists of compounds which delay the progression of the disease, including such drugs as selegiline,
vitamin E, estrogen, and nonsteroidal antiinflammatory drugs (National Institute on Aging, 1997; Whitehouse,
1996). The long-term approaches include treatments to prevent or cure the disease, which may result from future
discoveries pertaining to genetics and the molecular pathogenesis of AD (Whitehouse, 1996).
One of the primary ethical concerns pertaining to use of experimental drugs and treatments with patients with AD
is the potential inability of patients with more advanced disease to inform researchers about adverse reactions or
side effects they are experiencing. Many of the AD drugs currently used or being tested for treatment of AD have
subtle side effects (e.g., headache, nausea, abdominal pain, muscle pain, hot flashes, breast tenderness) that may
be difficult to detect. Side effects or adverse events are likely to be more difficult to detect in participants with
significant communication problems.
Another potential problem associated with drugs for symptomatic treatment of AD was recently discussed in a
letter to the editor of the Journal of the American Geriatrics Society (Bianchetti & Trabucchi, 1999). In this letter,
Bianchetti and Trabucchi present the case of a 53-year-old woman with AD being treated with donepezil.
Although the medication resulted in substantial improvements in intelligence and memory, the patient became
distressed because she regained awareness of her declining physical and mental state. The authors were
successfully able to treat the patient with antidepressants. However, this example demonstrates that current
treatments may result in patients re-living the distress associated with AD-related decline, and careful attention
must be paid assure that the patient’s quality of life is not compromised.
Use of Placebos
Placebo-controlled trials are common in testing new drugs (Burstein & Swiontkowski, 2001). However, there is
current debate about the ethics of using placebos in treatment studies where proven therapies exist for treating the
disease under study (Macklin, 1999; Rothnan & Michels, 1994). The original wording of the Declaration of
Helsinki states:
in any medical study, every patient—including those of a control group, if any—should be assured of the
best proven diagnostic and therapeutic method. This does not exclude the use of inert placebo in studies
where no proven diagnostic or therapeutic method exists (World Medical Organization, 1996).
However, revisions to the Helsinki document have been proposed pertaining to the use of placebos. Article 18 of
the revision permits the use of a placebo in cases where it is “justified by a scientifically and ethically sound
research protocol.” The proposed revisions further state that “when the outcome measures are neither death nor
disability, placebo or other no-treatment controls may be justified on the basis of their efficiency” (Brennan,
1999, p. 529). Levine argues in favor of the revised language, stating that the original Helsinki document
precludes the development of all new treatments, except for those diseases for which there are no proven
therapies, and use of placebos is justified on the grounds of efficiency (i.e., that requiring active treatment in
control groups would substantially increase the expense of conducting studies on new therapies). He states that
the use of placebos is justified in cases where the adverse effects of withholding an agent are merely symptomatic
and rapidly reversible. He further argues that another justification for use of placebos is they are responsive to the
patient’s right to self-determination (i.e., that normal volunteers have the right to assume risks that they perceive
to be reasonable in the pursuit of science) (Levine, 1999).
Although such arguments may work for studies testing new treatments for the common cold, arthritic symptoms,
or mild hypertension, in the future these arguments may not be useful in justifying research pertaining to AD
treatments. Cholinesterase inhibitors provide only symptomatic relief and, thus, it may be justifiable to withhold
these for the duration of a clinical trial. However, some of the intermediate drugs such as selegiline, vitamin E,
nonsteroidal anti-inflammatory agents, and estrogen may delay disability. Alzheimer’s disease results in
progressive decline. As evidence mounts that these drugs alter the course of the disease it will become more
difficult to justify withholding them, even under the proposed Helsinki revisions. This issue raises three
questions:
• How much evidence is required questioning the use of placebos?
• What degree of societal benefit must be expected to justify the continued use of placebos?
• How should researchers balance to the harm done to individuals from whom proven treatments were
withheld against the potential benefits to be realized from society?
Unfortunately, no clear answers to these questions exist.
In response to the argument that normal volunteers have the right to assume risks they perceive to be reasonable
in the pursuit of science, it is important to note that patients with AD are not “normal volunteers.” As stated
previously, patient self-determination needs to be preserved and, in cases where proxy consent is legally required,
assent should be obtained from the patient. Even if assent is obtained, it is doubtful that proxies have a right to
volunteer vulnerable participants for studies contrary to their best interests. In placebo controlled trials, those
participants randomized to the control group may be worse off than they would have been by not participating in
the study—at least when a treatment with some known efficacy is available.
Genetic Testing
Genetic information pertaining to the risk of developing AD is another area of concern related to beneficence.
The field of genetics is progressing rapidly, permitting early identification of risk for certain diseases, as well as
the possibility of future gene-based therapies. In October 1993, a research group from Duke University reported
the discovery of a genetic risk factor for susceptibility to AD. Shortly after this announcement, physicians were
deluged with requests for the “Alzheimer test.” One biotechnology firm (Genica, San Diego, CA) quickly
produced marketing materials about the test, suggesting it could be used for early identification of patients who
could benefit from early treatment or patients who could participate in clinical trials of new AD drugs (Quaid,
Dinwiddie, Conneally, & Nurnberger, 1996).
According to Post et al. (1997), five professional groups have developed consensus statements related to genetic
testing for susceptibility to AD. All agree that predictive testing in individuals who are asymptomatic is not
recommended at this time, but differ on use of the test for diagnosis of symptomatic individuals. Regardless of
how it is used, there are several ethical issues researchers must consider before using such a test. With the current
state of knowledge, it is not possible to determine, definitively, whether or not an individual will develop the
disease.
Being identified as at risk can have tremendous negative implications for individuals. There is currently no cure,
and it is not clear if anything can be done to reduce the test recipient’s risk of developing AD. Anticipation of
developing AD can diminish subsequent quality of life, and even result in suicidal behavior. A positive test can
also negatively influence employability and insurability Thus, it is not clear that the benefits of genetic testing
outweigh the risks involved (Fisk et al., 1998). Genetic testing of individuals who have a family member with
AD is appropriate if requested, and if it is accompanied by pre- and post-test counseling (Post et al., 1997).
JUSTICE
The principle of justice refers to whether or not a person has been treated according to what is fair, due, or owed
(Faden & Beauchamp, 1986). Justice demands the burdens and benefits of research to be distributed fairly among
all in society. Thus, no group should be unduly deprived of the benefits of scientific research, nor should any
group be disproportionately burdened. Patients with dementia are frequently excluded from research out of
concern for exploiting vulnerable participants. However, according to Post et al. (1997), to deny access of
patients with AD to participation in clinical research is to avoid rather than accept and practice ethical
responsibility. If extra attention is paid to issues of respect and beneficence, these vulnerable participants can and
should be recruited into clinical studies. To do otherwise would greatly impair society’s progress in treating AD.
Research is very expensive. These expenses are undertaken because of expected societal benefits. However, the
manner in which research dollar allocations are made often has very little to do with the extent to which a
particular health problem is a pressing societal issue. Rather, the amount of money spent on a disease is often a
function of the biases of policymakers, and also the need for policymakers to respond to the will of their voting
constituents.
For example, certain diseases seem to trigger more of an emotional response on the part of the public. Heart
disease is the number one killer in the United States, but because cancer is more feared, far more money is spent
on cancer research than on cardiovascular research. Some claim the voting power of an aging population is
pressuring Congress to invest in AD research and, as a result, the National Institute on Aging is providing
disproportionate research support in this area (Adelman, 1998; Wadman, 1998). However, given the tremendous
economic burden of AD and the aging of the “baby boomers,” health care expenditures related to the disease are
likely to increase greatly as this group peaks in number in the next 20 to 30 years. Recent estimates suggest new
drug developments have the potential to offer cost savings for many patients, and suggest continued investment
in AD research may be worthwhile (Knapp, Wilkinson, & Wigglesworth, 1998).
SUMMARY
Nurses are often involved in AD research as investigators, study coordinators, or data collectors. In these various
roles, nurses have a responsibility to assure that patients receive the respect they are due, that patients are not
harmed, and that the benefits and burdens of research are distributed in an equitable manner. As discussed in this
article, protecting the rights of patients with AD who participate in research is particularly complicated because
of the special needs of this patient population, and the characteristics of developing treatments and technologies.
By recognizing potential pitfalls, nurses involved in AD research can take proper steps to assure ethical treatment
of study participants.
REFERENCES
Adelman, R.C. (1998). The Alzheimerization of aging: A brief update. Experimental Gerontology, 33, 155-157.
American Health Assistance Foundation. (2000). Facts on Alzheimer’s disease. Retrieved December 16, 2002,
from http://www.ahaf.org/!alzfax.htm
Berghmans, R.L. (1998). Advance directives for non-therapeutic dementia research: Some ethical and policy
considerations. Journal of Medical Ethics, 24, 32-37.
Bianchetti, A., & Trabucchi, M. (1999). Ethical problems in the use of antidementia drugs [letter; comment].
Journal of the American Geriatric Society, 47, 913.
Brennan, T.A. (1999). Proposed revisions to the Declaration of Helsinki—Will they weaken the ethical principles
underlying human research? New England Journal of Medicine, 341, 527-530.
Burstein, A.H., & Swiontkowski, M.F. (2001). Update on human rights issues in clinical research. The Journal of
Bone and Joint Surgery, 83, 161-163.
Dresser, R. (1986). Life, death, and incompetent patients: Conceptual infirmities and hidden values in the law.
Arizona Law Review, 28, 373-405.
Dworkin, R. (1993). Life’s dominion. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
Faden, R.R., & Beauchamp, T.L. (1986). A history and theory of informed consent. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Fisk, J.D., Sadovnick, A.D., Cohen, C.A., Gauthier, S., Dossetor, J., Eberhart, A., & LeDuc, L. (1998). Ethical
guidelines of the Alzheimer Society of Canada. Canadian Journal of Neurological Science, 25, 242-248.
Harrison, L. (1993). Issues related to the protection of human research participants. Journal Neuroscience
Nursing, 25, 187-193.
Hawkins, B.S. (1991). Data monitoring committees for multicenter clinical trials sponsored by the National
Institutes of Health I. Roles and membership of data monitoring committees for trials sponsored by the
National Eye Institute. Controlled Clinical Trials, 12, 424-437.
Jaworska, A. (1999). Respecting the margins of agency: Alzheimer’s patients and the capacity to value.
Philosophy and Public Affairs, 28, 105-138.
Knapp, M., Wilkinson, D., & Wigglesworth, R. (1998). The economic consequences of Alzheimer’s disease in
the context of new drug developments. International Journal of Geriatric Psychiatry, 13, 531-543.
Lemiere, J., Van Gool, D., & Dom, R. (1999). Treatment of Alzheimer’s disease: An evaluation of the
cholinergic approach. Acta Neurologica Belgica, 99, 96-106.
Levine, R.J. (1999). The need to revise the Declaration of Helsinki. New England Journal of Medicine, 341, 531-
534.
Lurie, P., & Wolfe, S.M. (1999). Proposed revisions to the Declaration of Helsinki: Paving the way for
globalization in research. Western Journal of Medicine, 171(1), 6.
Macklin, R. (1999). The ethical problems with sham surgery in clinical research. New England Journal of
Medicine, 341, 992-996.
National Institute on Aging. (1997). New drug therapies delay effects of Alzheimer’s disease. Retrieved
December 16, 2002, from http://www.alzheimers.org/adear
Post, S.G., Whitehouse, P.J., Binstock, R.H., Bird, T.D., Eckert, S.K., Farrer, L.A., Fleck, L.M., Gaines, A.D.,
Juengst, E.T., Karlinsky, H., Miles, S., Murray, T.H., Quaid, K.A., Relkin, N.R., Roses, A.D., St. George-
Hyslop, P.H., Sachs, G.A., Steinbock, B., Truschke, E.F., & Zinn, A.B. (1997). The clinical introduction
of genetic testing for Alzheimer disease: An ethical perspective. Journal of the American Medical
Association, 277, 832-836.
Quaid, K.A., Dinwiddie, S.H., Conneally, P.M., & Nurnberger, J.I. (1996). Issues in genetic testing for
susceptibility to alcoholism: Lessons from Alzheimer’s disease and Huntington’s disease. Alcoholism:
Clinical and Experimental Research, 20, 1430-1437.
Rosler, M., Anand, R., Cicin-Sain, A., Gauthier, S., Agid, Y., Dal-Bianco, P., Stahelin, H.B., Hartman, R., &
Gharabawi, M. (1999). Efficacy and safety of rivastigmine in patients with Alzheimer’s disease:
International randomised controlled trial. BMJ, 318, 633-638.
Rothnan, K.J., & Michels, K.B. (1994). The continuing unethical use of placebo controls. New England Journal
of Medicine, 331, 394-398.
Sachs, G.A., Rhymes, J., & Cassel, C.K. (1993). Biomedical and behavioral research in nursing homes:
Guidelines for ethical investigations. Journal of the American Geriatric Society, 41, 771-777.
Shuster, E. (1998). The Nuremberg Code: Hippocratic ethics and human rights. Lancet, 35, 974-977.
Wadman, M. (1998). Aging population of voters backs Alzheimer’s funding. Nature, 392, 428.
Whitehouse, P.J. (1996). Future prospects for Alzheimer’s disease therapy: Ethical and policy issues for the
international community. Acta Neurologica Scandinavica, 165, 145-149.
Wittes, J. (1993). Behind closed doors: The data monitoring board in randomized clinical trials. Statistics in
Medicine, 12, 419-424.
World Medical Organization. (1996). Declaration of Helsinki. British Medical Journal, 313, 1448-1449.