ArticlePDF Available

The rational cure for prereproductive stress syndrome revisited

Authors:

Abstract

If it is irrational to allow the worst outcome of our actions, and if it is immoral to cause suffering, then it is irrational and immoral to have children.
.......................................................................................
The rational cure for prereproductive
stress syndrome revisited
MHa¨yry
...................................................................................
If it is irrational to allow the worst outcome of our actions, and if it
is immoral to cause suffering, then it is irrational and immoral to
have children.
Irecently published in this journal a
paper, entitled A rational cure for
prereproductive stress syndrome, and was
happy to see that three colleagues—
Rebecca Bennett, Søren Holm, and
Sahin Aksoy—had taken the time to
critically examine it. This gave me an
opportunity to briefly revisit the topic,
and to clarify some of the arguments I
put forward.
THE IRRATIONALITY OF HAVING
CHILDREN
In my paper, A rational cure for prerepro-
ductive stress syndrome,
1
I claimed that it is
irrational to have children,
Nif (a) it is irrational to deliberately
allow the worst outcome of our
actions in a given situation,
Nand if (b) to have children allows this.
I argued that having children allows
the worst outcome of our reproductive
choices (the creation of a possibly bad
life, where the alternative is no life),
Nif (c) it makes good sense to restrict
the analysis to the comparative value
of life versus non-existence of possi-
ble future individuals, as experienced
by themselves,
Nand if (d) there are individuals who
genuinely would prefer non-exis-
tence to their own life.
My practical conclusion in the paper
was modest: (e) ‘‘Possible parents could
be told that, according to at least one
philosopher, it would be all right for
them not to reproduce at all.’’
1
This was
my suggested ‘‘rational cure for prere-
productive stress syndrome’’.
‘‘NOT STRONGLY IRRATIONAL’’
Holm argues against (a) that it is not
irrational to deliberately allow a low
probability of the worst outcome.
2
He
starts from the premise that to make
my argument work I would need to
regard the maximin rule—the rule
specified in claim (a)—as the only
criterion of rationality. If I do so,
however, I should never, in fear of
micro-organisms, eat food that has
not been fully sterilised in an
autoclave—something that Holm seems
to think would be ludicrous. On the
other hand, if I do not regard the
maximin rule as the only criterion of
rationality, I cannot defend directive
counselling against having children.
I have a very simple countercomment
to this. I do not regard the maximin rule
as the only definition of rationality. Nor
do I need to do so, because I do not
advocate directive counselling—a choice
I hoped would be clear from the
cautious formulation of conclusion (e).
My apologies, if I have expressed myself
in unclear terms.
‘‘LIFE CANNOT BE THE WORST
OUTCOME’’
Aksoy argues against (b) that having
children cannot bring about the worst
outcome, because the worst possible
outcome of reproductive choices is
always non-existence.
3
He refers to his
own previously formulated view,
4
according to which existence ‘‘is essen-
tial and prerequisite to everything good
or bad, and deserves to be protected and
respected’’.
3
He also quotes Spinoza,
who in his work published in 1677
wrote: ‘‘No one can desire to be happy,
to act well and live well, who does not at
the same time desire to be, to act, and to
live, that is to say, actually to exist’’.
3
My primary reason for not being
impressed by these statements in the
present context is that they do not
address choices before a being is or is
not brought into existence. I can fully
agree with Aksoy that human existence,
once it is ‘‘here’’, so to speak, is the basis
of all experiences. I can also agree with
Spinoza that being alive precedes desires
concerning the content of one’s life (if
this is what he meant): but I fail to see
the relevance of these statements to the
choice to reproduce or not to reproduce.
All they demonstrate is that as the
foundation of our experiences, life can
have positive instrumental value to us if
our experiences are good. By the same
token, it can have negative instrumental
value to us if our experiences are bad. It
does not, however, have any value, good
or bad, when it is not present.
‘‘IT IS RATIONAL TO HAVE
SAVIOUR SIBLINGS’’
Bennett notes against my claim (c) that
in certain circumstances it does seem
irrational to ignore the interests of a
potential child’s existing siblings.
5
A
case in point is when these siblings
suffer horribly from conditions that
could be cured or substantially alle-
viated by tissue transplants from the
new individuals. It would seem rational,
according to my adopted account, to
produce these ‘‘saviour siblings’’. By
doing so we could remove certain
suffering by allowing only a slight
possibility of suffering—surely an acc-
eptable trade off?
Well, no. In fact, such trade offs are
not in line with the maximin rule. The
remark is good from the viewpoint of
maximising expected utility, which is
another feasible way of construing what
rationality means.
67
Because, however,
the worst possible outcome of creating
‘‘saviour siblings’’ is that there will be,
in the end, two lives that those living
them would prefer not to have (instead
of just the already existing one), max-
imin rationality does not support this
choice.
THE IMMORALITY OF HAVING
CHILDREN
I also claimed in my paper that it is
immoral to have children:
Nif (f) it is immoral to bring about
avoidable suffering,
Nand if (g) having children has this
effect.
I took the first statement to be self
evidently true, and supported the sec-
ond by specifying two senses in which it
can be said to be true. Having children
brings about avoidable suffering
Nin the sense that (h) all human beings
suffer at some point in their lives,
Abstract
If it is irrational to allow the worst outcome of our actions, and if it is immoral to cause
suffering, then it is irrational and immoral to have children.
606 REPRODUCTION
www.jmedethics.com
Nand in the sense that (j) potential
parents cannot guarantee that their
child’s life would not become at some
point in time (physically, mentally, or
socially) overwhelmingly miserable.
The truth of these statements was not
contested by my critics, although their
ethical implications were.
My practical conclusion from these
premises was even more modest than
my inference from the analysis of
rationality: (k) ‘‘In principle, and in an
equal discussion between competent
participants, my moral views may enti-
tle me to reproach individuals who
decide, or have decided, to have chil-
dren. There is, however, seldom much
point in my doing so.’’
1
‘‘IT IS IN (NEARLY) EVERYBODY’S
INTEREST TO EXIST’’
Aksoy and Bennett both dispute my
claim (f)—that it is immoral to bring
about avoidable suffering—by arguing
that it would be good to all, or at least
most, individuals, to exist, and therefore
always morally acceptable to help them
in this endeavour, despite the suffering
produced.
According to Aksoy, it is right to allow
any suffering our potential children can
experience, because existence is in and
of itself valuable, and non-existence is
the paragon of evil. In his view, it is
‘‘immoral to ‘sentence’ someone to non-
existence while you have the chance to
bring them into life’’.
3
Bennett, in her
turn, argues that it is permissible to
bring about some suffering, if good
things in life depend on this. In her
words, it ‘‘is in the interest of any child
whose life will be likely worth living
overall, that he or she is brought to
birth’’.
5
My main conceptual difficulty with
these critiques is that I do not know who
Aksoy and Bennett are talking about.
Who exactly is the absent someone who
is sentenced to non-existence; and who
precisely is the unborn child whose
interests would be served by bringing
her to birth? How can we attribute
experiences and interests to beings
who have not existed in the past, do
not exist now, and will possibly never
exist in the future?
Apart from this metaphysical pro-
blem, there are a couple of normative
issues that I would like to raise.
Aksoy seems to say that even indivi-
duals whose lives would be utterly
miserable—filled with suffering and
nothing else—must be brought into
existence, when we have that chance.
If this is his message, I disagree and so
do many others.
589
I think that it would
be inhumane to force suffering human
beings to live. Aksoy’s view also implies
that we should spend our entire lives
trying to make babies. Women should
aim to be with child all the time, and
men should probably focus on perfect-
ing the techniques of ectogenesis and
male pregnancy. This is not an impos-
sible idea, of course, but it is not one
that is likely to have wide popularity,
either.
Bennett, on the other hand, resorts to
the language of ‘‘worthwhile lives’’ (an
expression, by the way, which is not
used in my original paper). This is
undoubtedly a good move in that it
helps her to avoid the criticism levelled
at Aksoy’s more stringent view. It is not
easy, however, to draw the line between
‘‘worthwhile’’ and ‘‘unworthwhile’’
lives in a universally acknowledged, or
even widely accepted, way.
So although Aksoy can be accused of
committing himself to an absurdly stern
view, Bennett defends a position that
seems to require further specifications.
SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS
I have argued in this response to my
critics that if it is irrational to allow the
worst outcome of our actions, and if it is
immoral to cause suffering, then it is
irrational and immoral to have children.
I have also spelled out the premises of
my argument, and claimed that they
remain intact against the main objec-
tions presented by my critics.
I have not argued—either here or in
the original paper—that the accounts of
rationality and morality I have evoked
are the only ones. All I have said is that
it makes good sense to apply the
maximin rule to reproductive choices,
in which we can actually refrain from
creating beings that we can harm
merely by creating them. Nor have I
argued—here or originally—that would
be parents should be given directive
antinatal counselling. All I have implied,
by arguing that abstinence is a rational
and moral choice, is that would be
parents should probably not be given
directive pronatal counselling, either.
In the light of these observations, I
still believe it would be all right for
people not to reproduce: and I still think
that people would not be horribly
manipulated if someone told them this.
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
This article was produced as a part of
the project Ethical and Social Aspects of
Bioinformatics (ESABI), financed between
2004 and 2007 by the Academy of Finland
(SA 105139). My thanks are due to the
academy for its support, to Dr Tuija Takala
for her helpful comments, and to Peter
Herissone-Kelly for checking my English.
J Med Ethics 2005;31:606–607.
doi: 10.1136/jme.2005.011684
Correspondence to: M Ha¨yry, Centre for Social
Ethics and Policy, Institute of Medicine, Law and
Bioethics, School of Law, University of
Manchester, Williamson Building, Oxford
Road, Manchester, M13 9PL, UK; matti.hayry@
manchester.ac.uk
REFERENCES
1Ha¨ yry M. A rational cure for prereproductive
stress syndrome. J Med Ethics 2004;30:377–8.
2Holm S. Why it is not strongly irrational to have
children. J Med Ethics 2004;30:381.
3Aksoy S. Response to: A rational cure for
prereproductive stress syndrome. J Med Ethics
2004;30:382–3.
4Aksoy S. To value life and existence.
Eubios J Asian Int Bioethics 1997;7:102–4.
5Bennett R. Human reproduction: irrational but in
most cases morally defensible. J Med Ethics
2004;30:379–80.
6Savulescu J. Procreative beneficence: why we
should select the best children. Bioethics
2001;15:413–26.
7Ha¨ yry M. If you must make babies, then at least
make the best babies you can?Hum Fertil (Camb)
2004;7:105–12.
8Bennett R, Harris J. Are there lives not worth
living?When is it morally wrong to reproduce?In,
Dickenson D, ed. Ethical issues in maternal-fetal
medicine. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2002:321–34.
9Archard A. Wrongful life. Philosophy
2004;79:403–20.
REPRODUCTION 607
www.jmedethics.com
... Those are replete in the extant literature. 4,5,6,7,8,9,10,11,12,13,14,15,16,17,18,19,20 This is a conceptual exploration showing how close to the surface antinatalist premises have been for at least four decades, even in seminal works such as Parfit's. ...
Article
Full-text available
Derek Parfit famously opined that causing a person to exist with a life barely worth living can be wrong, although it is not wrong for that person. This conundrum is known as the nonidentity problem. Parfit also held that persons can, in a morally relevant sense, be caused to exist in the distant future by actions that make the agent a necessary condition for a person’s existence. When these views are combined, which he did, and applied explicitly to persons with a life not worth living, which he did not, an interesting conditional conclusion can be drawn. If every family line eventually produces a person with a life not worth living, and if causing that person to exist cannot be justified by the benefits befalling others in the family line, it is always wrong to have children. Parfit did not draw this antinatalist conclusion, but an analysis of his introduction of the nonidentity problem shows that he could have. Since Parfit’s other views on population ethics continue to be discussed with relative respect, it stands to reason that the antinatalist position should be no exception. Right or wrong, it has its legitimate place in considerations concerning the future of reproduction.
... Antinatalism is most commonly associated with South African philosopher David Benatar [14], although somewhat similar positions have been argued for by Peter Wessel Zapffe [15], Arthur Schopenhauer, Matti Häyry [16][17], Stuart Rachels [18] and, more recently, Blake Hereth and Anthony Ferrucci [19]. ...
Article
Full-text available
Ethical vegans and vegetarians believe that it is seriously immoral to bring into existence animals whose lives would be miserable. In this paper, I will discuss whether such a belief also leads to the conclusion that it is seriously immoral to bring human beings into existence. I will argue that vegans should abstain from having children since they believe that unnecessary suffering should be avoided. After all, humans will suffer in life, and having children is not necessary for a good life. Thus vegans, and probably vegetarians as well, should not have children. I will consider several objections against this controversial claim, show why the objections fail and conclude that it would be best for ethical vegans to abstain from procreation.
... This principle is in line with Häyry's antinatalist view: not having children is both rational and ethical. 2,3 Some see this sort of antinatalist conclusion as repugnant or implausible itself, 4 while others endorse similar conclusions for somewhat different reasons. 5,6 I am not sure whether it is wrong to have children. ...
Article
Full-text available
The aim of this commentary is to critically examine Matti Häyry’s article ‘Just Better Utilitarianism’, where he argues that liberal utilitarianism can offer a basis for moral and political choices in bioethics and thus could be helpful in decision-making. This commentary, while generally sympathetic to Häyry’s perspective, argues that Häyry should expand on who belongs to our moral community because, to solve practical ethical issues, we need to determine who (and what) deserves our moral consideration. Challenging Häyry’s principle of actual or prospective existence, this commentary suggests that – at least sometimes – the quality of life of those who will never come into existence matters. In a similar vein, this commentary aims to show that determining how to treat mindless humans such as fetuses might pose difficulties for liberal utilitarianism unless the issue of the boundaries of the moral community is addressed.
... In a causal sense, they are, but legally and morally, this is not much to go by (although it raises interesting questions about parental responsibility). 103,104,105,106 The test can spread responsibility too widely, and we should augment it with other criteria. Mirroring this, an assailant can argue that while the assault may have contributed to the harm, we can identify many other agents who did, too, making it difficult to say whose deed was decisive. ...
Article
Full-text available
Moral and political philosophers no longer condemn harm inflicted on nonhuman animals as self-evidently as they did when animal welfare and animal rights advocacy was at the forefront in the 1980s, and sentience, suffering, species-typical behavior, and personhood were the basic concepts of the discussion. The article shows this by comparing the determination with which societies seek responsibility for human harm to the relative indifference with which law and morality react to nonhuman harm. When harm is inflicted on humans, policies concerning negligence and duty of care and principles such as the ‘but for’ rule and the doctrine of double effect are easily introduced. When harm is inflicted on nonhumans, this does not happen, at least not any more. As an explanation for the changed situation, the article offers a shift in discussion and its basic terminology. Simple ethical considerations supported the case for nonhuman animals, but many philosophers moved on to debate different views on political justice instead. This allowed the creation of many conflicting views that are justifiable on their own presuppositions. In the absence of a shared foundation, this fragments the discussion, focuses it on humans, and ignores or marginalizes nonhuman animals.
... In the light of these observations, one would think that the right question is, "Should anyone have children" rather than, "Should everyone have them?" [16,17,18] Since the Breeders' Pact can be thought of as a contract, and since contracts are in political theory often applied to parties against their will, it is useful to examine the conditions on which the extension could be legitimate. I will not consider this from the viewpoint of purely hypothetical agreements, though. ...
Chapter
Full-text available
Two questions precede any considerations of reproductive genetics and gender. They are “Should people have children to begin with?” and “Who is responsible for children and why?” If it is irrational or immoral to produce offspring, as I have suggested elsewhere [1–3], reproductive genetics turns out to be a waste of time and gendered family roles obsolete. Tom Buller examines critically my views on this in Chapter 11. If, again, some people are more responsible for children than others, this should be made visible in the allocation of child-related burdens in society. In what follows, I offer some general comments regarding this second question for further discussion.
Article
Full-text available
Antinatalism assigns reproduction a negative value. There should be fewer or no births. Those who say that there should be fewer births have been called conditional antinatalists. A better name for their view would be selective pronatalism. Those who say that there should be no births face two challenges. They must define the scope of their no-birth policy. Does it apply only to human or sentient beings or can it also be extended to all organic life, perhaps even to machine consciousness? And whatever the scope, they have to justify the eventual extinction of humankind or other life forms, an inevitable consequence of unconditional antinatalism. Different axiologies and moral theories produce different responses to these challenges. It is argued that a two-value conflict-sensitive negative utilitarianism would produce a kind and reasonable justification for ending at least human and factory-animal reproduction. The conclusion is purely moral and supports only voluntary extinction for humankind.
Article
Full-text available
I present a qualified new defense of antinatalism. It is intended to empower potential parents who worry about their possible children's life quality in a world threatened by environmental degradation, climate change, and the like. The main elements of the defense are an understanding of antinatalism's historical nature and contemporary varieties, a positional theory of value based on Epicurean hedonism and Schopenhauerian pessimism, and a sensitive guide for reproductive decision-making in the light of different views on life's value and risk-taking. My conclusion, main message, to the concerned would-be parents is threefold. If they believe that life's ordinary frustrations can make it not worth living, they should not have children. If they believe that a noticeably low life quality makes it not worth living and that such life quality can be reasonably expected, they should not have children, either. If they believe that a noticeably low life quality is not reasonably to be expected or that the risk is worth taking, they can, in the light of their own values and beliefs, have children. The conclusion is supported by a combination of the extant arguments for reproductive abstinence, namely the arguments from consent, moral asymmetry, life quality, and risk.
Article
Should we make people healthier, smarter, and longer-lived if genetic and medical advances enable us to do so? Matti Häyry asks this question in the context of genetic testing and selection, cloning and stem cell research, gene therapies and enhancements. The ethical questions explored include parental responsibility, the use of people as means, the role of hope and fear in risk assessment, and the dignity and meaning of life. Taking as a starting point the arguments presented by Jonathan Glover, John Harris, Ronald M. Green, Jürgen Habermas, Michael J. Sandel, and Leon R. Kass, who defend a particular normative view as the only rational or moral answer, Matti Häyry argues that many coherent rationalities and moralities exist in the field, and that to claim otherwise is mistaken.
Article
My recently published book Rationality and the Genetic Challenge: Making People Better? analyzes different philosophical responses to developments in genetics.1 In the last two issues of the Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 14 scholars have presented critical comments on my work, and this article is my response to them.
Article
In this article, I will show what is respected most in human reproduction and parenting is not a right to reproduce in the way in which this right is explicitly proposed. The only way in which people can become, and function as, parents without having to submit themselves to anyone else's judgements and decisions, is by having reproductive sex. Whatever one's intentions, social status, standard of living, income, etc., so long as assistance is not required, that person's reproductive decisions will not be interfered with in any way, at least not until neglect or abuse of their offspring becomes known. Moreover, none of the features that are said to back the right to reproduce (such as bodily integrity or personal autonomy) can justify one's unquestioned access to the relationship with another unable to consent (the child). This indicates that the discourse in terms of the right to reproduce as is currently used so as to justify non-interference with natural reproduction and parenting coupled with the regulation of assisted forms of reproduction and parenting, is at best self-deluding and that all it protects is people's freedom to have reproductive sex and handle the consequences.
Article
Full-text available
This article provides an overview of the reasons why people should or should not have children, and of two attempts to define what we can do to make sure that the lives of the children we have are as good as they can be. It is suggested that the answers to these questions are more complex than we tend to think, and that rational arguments can be found to support many mutually conflicting reproductive policies.
Article
Full-text available
While I am inclined to agree that in most cases a choice to become pregnant and bring to birth a child is an irrational choice, unlike Professor Hayry,1 I believe that choosing to do so is far from being necessarily immoral. In fact I will argue that it is often these irrational (but morally defensible) choices which make human life the valuable commodity many of us believe it is. Hayry argues that not only is the choice to have children always an irrational choice, but also it is necessarily an immoral choice. Thus, for Hayry “human reproduction is fundamentally immoral”.1 He claims it is important to point out to prospective parents that their urge to have children is irrational. From this, he argues, it follows that once this is accepted the use of advance technologies to assist conception should be reassessed, and furthermore, the irrationality and immorality of having children should become a legitimate part of guidance given to those expressing a wish to have children. According to Hayry the reason it is irrational and immoral to choose to bring to birth a child is that “having a child can always realistically lead to the worse possible outcome, when the alternative is not having a child”.1 He argues that when people consider having children they are faced with the choice between deciding not to have children and thus harming or benefiting no-one (this, it is argued has a value of zero), or having children where this life may be good or bad, and thus the value of this choice can be …
Article
Full-text available
Since human reproduction is arguably both irrational and immoral, those who seek help before conceiving could be advised it is all right not to have children.
Article
Full-text available
I argue that it is wrong deliberately to bring into existence an individual whose life we can reasonably expect will be of very poor quality. The individual's life would on balance be worth living but would nevertheless fall below a certain threshold. Additionally the prospective parents are unable to have any other child who would enjoy a better existence. Against the claims of John Harris and John Robertson I argue that deliberately to conceive such a child would not be to exercise the right to procreate. For this right is internally constrained by the requirement that any resultant child has the reasonable prospect of a minimally decent life.
Article
Eugenic selection of embryos is now possible by employing in vitro fertilization (IVF) and preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD). While PGD is currently being employed for the purposes of detecting chromosomal abnormalities or inherited genetic abnormalities, it could in principle be used to test any genetic trait such as hair colour or eye colour. Genetic research is rapidly progressing into the genetic basis of complex traits like intelligence and a gene has been identified for criminal behaviour in one family. Once the decision to have IVF is made, PGD has few ‘costs’ to couples, and people would be more inclined to use it to select less serious medical traits, such as a lower risk of developing Alzheimer Disease, or even for non-medical traits. PGD has already been used to select embryos of a desired gender in the absence of any history of sex-linked genetic disease. I will argue that: (1) some non-disease genes affect the likelihood of us leading the best life; (2) we have a reason to use information which is available about such genes in our reproductive decision-making; (3) couples should select embryos or fetuses which are most likely to have the best life, based on available genetic information, including information about non-disease genes. I will also argue that we should allow selection for non-disease genes even if this maintains or increases social inequality. I will focus on genes for intelligence and sex selection. I will defend a principle which I call Procreative Beneficence: couples (or single reproducers) should select the child, of the possible children they could have, who is expected to have the best life, or at least as good a life as the others, based on the relevant, available information.
Article
Eugenic selection of embryos is now possible by employing in vitro fertilization (IVF) and preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD). While PGD is currently being employed for the purposes of detecting chromosomal abnormalities or inherited genetic abnormalities, it could in principle be used to test any genetic trait such as hair colour or eye colour. Genetic research is rapidly progressing into the genetic basis of complex traits like intelligence and a gene has been identified for criminal behaviour in one family. Once the decision to have IVF is made, PGD has few 'costs' to couples, and people would be more inclined to use it to select less serious medical traits, such as a lower risk of developing Alzheimer Disease, or even for non-medical traits. PGD has already been used to select embryos of a desired gender in the absence of any history of sex-linked genetic disease. I will argue that: (1) some non-disease genes affect the likelihood of us leading the best life; (2) we have a reason to use information which is available about such genes in our reproductive decision-making; (3) couples should select embryos or fetuses which are most likely to have the best life, based on available genetic information, including information about non-disease genes. I will also argue that we should allow selection for non-disease genes even if this maintains or increases social inequality. I will focus on genes for intelligence and sex selection. I will defend a principle which I call Procreative Beneficence: couples (or single reproducers) should select the child, of the possible children they could have, who is expected to have the best life, or at least as good a life as the others, based on the relevant, available information.
Article
This response to "A rational cure for pre-reproductive stress syndrome" first suggests it is existence that is essential and prerequisite to everything good or bad, therefore it deserves to be protected and respected. Secondly, it argues that every life is worth living, even if it is worse than some other lives, if the only alternative is non-existence. Finally, it takes a critical view of and challenges Häyry's suggestion that in a good clinical situation, the idea of the irrationality of having children could be a legitimate part of the guidance given, since it is not the counsellor's or doctor's duty to advise a couple who wish to have children that it is irrational or even immoral to bring a child into life.
Article
Response to: A rational cure for prereproductive stress syndrome
To value life and existence
  • S Aksoy
Aksoy S. To value life and existence. Eubios J Asian Int Bioethics 1997;7:102-4.