Article

The Russian Blues Reveal Effects of Language on Color Discrimination

Department of Brain and Cognitive Sciences, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, MA 02139-4307, USA.
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences (Impact Factor: 9.67). 06/2007; 104(19):7780-5. DOI: 10.1073/pnas.0701644104
Source: PubMed

ABSTRACT

English and Russian color terms divide the color spectrum differently. Unlike English, Russian makes an obligatory distinction between lighter blues ("goluboy") and darker blues ("siniy"). We investigated whether this linguistic difference leads to differences in color discrimination. We tested English and Russian speakers in a speeded color discrimination task using blue stimuli that spanned the siniy/goluboy border. We found that Russian speakers were faster to discriminate two colors when they fell into different linguistic categories in Russian (one siniy and the other goluboy) than when they were from the same linguistic category (both siniy or both goluboy). Moreover, this category advantage was eliminated by a verbal, but not a spatial, dual task. These effects were stronger for difficult discriminations (i.e., when the colors were perceptually close) than for easy discriminations (i.e., when the colors were further apart). English speakers tested on the identical stimuli did not show a category advantage in any of the conditions. These results demonstrate that (i) categories in language affect performance on simple perceptual color tasks and (ii) the effect of language is online (and can be disrupted by verbal interference).

Download full-text

Full-text

Available from: Lisa Wulund, Feb 04, 2014
    • "Evidence comes mainly from research concerning links between color perception and color concepts (e.g. Thierry et al. 2009; Winawer et al. 2007; Daoutis et al. 2006). One experiment by Daoutis et al.'s (2006) involved 4–7 year old children from either England or Kwanyama (Namibia). "
    [Show abstract] [Hide abstract]
    ABSTRACT: Enactivists often defend the following two claims: (a.) Successful interactions are not driven and explained by the interactors’ ability to mindread (i.e. the ability to attribute beliefs and desires to other agents). And (b.) the mechanisms enabling 2n d personal social cognition and those enabling 3r d personal social cognition are distinct. In this paper, I argue that both of these claims are false. With regard to (a.) I argue that enactivists fail to provide a plausible alternative to traditional accounts of social cognition in interaction. I examine and reject Hanne De Jaegher’s view according to which interaction is “constitutive” for social interaction. Furthermore, I critically discuss Shaun Gallagher’s and Daniel Hutto’s views according to which social interactions are exclusively driven by low level cognitive mechanisms such as “gaze following” and “emotion detection”. Concerning (b.), I rely on data from so called “spontaneous response” false belief tasks to show that interactive and observational paradigms require the same “social-cognitive” interpretation.
    No preview · Article · Jan 2016
  • Source
    • "This difference is reflected in perceptual tasks: while native Russian speakers discriminate light blue colors from dark blue colors faster than two colors from the same category (e.g. when both stimuli belong to the light blue category), the performance of English speakers remains the same across both conditions. This means that the learnt color terms ''can affect performance of basic perceptual color discrimination tasks'' (Winawer et al. 2007, 7783). Furthermore, the authors conclude that their results do not support an interpretation based on perceptual learning and that only two explanatory options remain open. "
    [Show abstract] [Hide abstract]
    ABSTRACT: The cognitive penetrability of perceptual experiences has been a long-standing topic of disagreement among philosophers and psychologists. Although the notion of cognitive penetrability itself has also been under dispute, the debate has mainly focused on the cases in which cognitive states allegedly penetrate perceptual experiences. This paper concerns the plausibility of two prominent cases. The first one originates from Susanna Siegel’s claim that perceptual experiences can represent natural kind properties. If this is true, then the concepts we possess change the way things appear to us. The second candidate for cognitive penetration is Fiona Macpherson’s claim that, in addition to concepts, our beliefs can penetrate perceptual experiences. It is argued that neither candidate is a case of cognitive penetration. In doing so, I provide an explanation to both that is based on perceptual learning, a non-cognitive phenomenon where relatively slow and long-lasting modifications to an organism’s perceptual system bring about changes in perception. This explanation is theoretically more plausible and remains closer to the empirical data than the explanations based on cognitive penetration.
    Full-text · Article · Nov 2015 · Erkenntnis
  • Source
    • "Massey, & Gleitman, 2002). Several studies have found meaningful differences between speakers of different languages; however, these differences often diminish or disappear when people are prevented from explicitly using language (e.g.,Frank, Fedorenko, Lai, Saxe, & Gibson, 2012;Trueswell & Papafragou, 2010;Winawer et al., 2007). Furthermore , preventing access to language during only encoding or both encoding and retrieval has been found to impact cognitive performance to a greater extent compared to preventing access to language during only retrieval (Frank et al., 2012). "
    [Show abstract] [Hide abstract]
    ABSTRACT: When monitoring the origins of their memories, people tend to mistakenly attribute memories generated from internal processes (e.g., imagination, visualization) to perception. Here, we ask whether speaking a language that obligatorily encodes the source of information might help prevent such errors. We compare speakers of English to speakers of Turkish, a language that obligatorily encodes information source (direct/perceptual vs. indirect/hearsay or inference) for past events. In our experiments, participants reported having seen events that they had only inferred from post-event visual evidence. In general, error rates were higher when visual evidence that gave rise to inferences was relatively close to direct visual evidence. Furthermore, errors persisted even when participants were asked to report the specific sources of their memories. Crucially, these error patterns were equivalent across language groups, suggesting that speaking a language that obligatorily encodes source of information does not increase sensitivity to the distinction between perception and inference in event memory.
    Full-text · Article · Nov 2015 · Journal of Memory and Language
Show more