ChapterPDF Available
Democracy,
Accountability,
and
Representation
Edited by
Adam Przeworski
New York University
Susan C. Stokes
University of Chicago
Bernard Manin
New York University
PUBLISHED BY THE PRESS SYNDICATE OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE
The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS
The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 2RU, UK www.cup.cam.ac.uk
40 West 20th Street, New York, NY 10011-4211, USA www.cup.org
10 Stamford Road, Oakleigh, Melbourne 3166, Australia
Ruiz de Alarcón 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain
© Adam Przeworski Susan C. Stokes Bernard Manin 1999
This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception
and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements,
no reproduction of any part may take place without
the written permission of Cambridge University Press.
First published 1999
Printed in the United States of America
Typeface Centennial 10/13 pt. System QuarkXPress®[BTS]
A catalog record for this book is available from
the British Library.
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication data
Democracy, accountability, and representation / edited by
Adam Przeworski, Susan C. Stokes, Bernard Manin.
p. cm. – (Cambridge studies in the theory of democracy)
ISBN 0-521-64153-5 (hc.). – ISBN 0-521-64616-2 (pbk.)
1. Democracy. 2. Elections. 3. Representative government and
representation. 4. Responsibility. I. Przeworski, Adam. II. Stokes,
Susan Carol. III. Manin, Bernard. IV. Series.
JC423.D43946 1999
321.8 – dc21 98-50663
CIP
ISBN 0 521 64153 5 hardback
ISBN 0 521 64616 2 paperback
Contents
vii
List of Contributors page ix
Introduction 1
Bernard Manin, Adam Przeworski,
and Susan C. Stokes
Part One: Elections, Accountability, and
Representation 27
1Elections and Representation 29
Bernard Manin, Adam Przeworski, and Susan C. Stokes
2Electoral Accountability and the Control of
Politicians: Selecting Good Types versus
Sanctioning Poor Performance 55
James D. Fearon
3What Do Policy Switches Tell Us about Democracy? 98
Susan C. Stokes
4Accountability and Authority: Toward a Theory of
Political Accountability 131
John Ferejohn
5Accountability and Manipulation 154
José María Maravall
6Party Government and Responsiveness 197
James A. Stimson
7Democracy, Elections, and Accountability for
Economic Outcomes 222
José Antonio Cheibub and Adam Przeworski
Contents
viii
Part Two: The Structure of Government and
Accountability 251
8Accountability in Athenian Politics 253
Jon Elster
9Government Accountability in Parliamentary
Democracy 279
Michael Laver and Kenneth A. Shepsle
10 Mixing Elected and Nonelected Officials in
Democratic Policy Making: Fundamentals of
Accountability and Responsibility 297
Delmer D. Dunn
Part Three: Overview 327
11 Situating Democratic Political Accountability 329
John Dunn
Author Index 345
Subject Index 350
Bernard Manin, Adam Przeworski,
and Susan C. Stokes
Chapter One
Elections and
Representation
29
The claim connecting democracy and representation is that
under democracy governments are representative because they
are elected: if elections are freely contested, if participation is
widespread, and if citizens enjoy political liberties, then gov-
ernments will act in the best interest of the people. In one – the
“mandate” – view, elections serve to select good policies or policy-
bearing politicians. Parties or candidates make policy proposals
during campaigns and explain how these policies would affect
citizens’ welfare; citizens decide which of these proposals they
want implemented and which politicians to charge with their
implementation, and governments do implement them. Thus,
elections emulate a direct assembly and the winning platform
becomes the “mandate” that the government pursues. In a second
– “accountability” – view, elections serve to hold governments
responsible for the results of their past actions. Because they
anticipate the judgment of voters, governments are induced to
choose policies that in their judgment will be positively evaluated
by citizens at the time of the next election.
Yet both views are problematic. Representation is an issue
because politicians have goals, interests, and values of their own,
and they know things and undertake actions that citizens cannot
observe or can monitor only at a cost. Even if once they are in
office politicians may want to do nothing but serve the public, to
get elected in the first place they may have to gratify special
interests. And once elected, they may want to pursue their private
goals or some public objectives that differ from those of citizens.
If they have such motivations, they will want to do things other
than represent the public. And voters do not know everything they
need to know, whether to decide prospectively what politicians
Manin, Przeworski, and Stokes
30
should be doing or to judge retrospectively if they did what they
should have done. And if voters know that there are some things
they do not know, they do not want to bind politicians to implement
their wishes. In turn, if citizens do not have sufficient information
to evaluate the incumbent governments, the threat of not being
reelected is insufficient to induce governments to act in the best
interest of the public.
In this chapter we analyze whether voters can enforce repre-
sentation by using their vote to choose policies and politicians,
using it to sanction the incumbent, or using their vote simul-
taneously in both ways. We then discuss institutional features that
may be conducive to inducing representation.
The Mandate Conception of Representation
In electoral campaigns parties propose policies and offer
candidates. If voters believe that politicians are not all the same,
they may attempt to secure representation by using their vote
to choose best policies or policy-bearing politicians. The questions
we need to examine are whether (1) electoral campaigns are
informative, that is, voters can justifiably expect that parties would
do what they proposed, and (2) pursuing the winning platform, the
“mandate,” is always in the best interest of voters. We will say that
“mandate-representation” occurs if the answer to both these
questions is positive, that is, parties truthfully inform voters about
their intentions and the implementation of these intentions is best
for voters under the given circumstances.
The mandate conception of representation is widespread:
scholars, journalists, and ordinary citizens rely on it as if it were
axiomatic. Keeler (1993), for example, explains the major policy
reforms introduced by Reagan, Thatcher, and Mitterand as
follows: their respective countries faced economic crises, voters
wanted change and expressed this desire at the polls, and the
respective governments implemented their mandates. This model
seems to account well for policy formation in advanced industrial
society (Klingeman, Hofferbert, and Budge 1994). As a French
politician put it, “Since the Romans, it is an old law of politics,
which we should never lose from our view: governments can last
only by the principle by which they were born” (Séguin 1997).
A rudimentary conceptual apparatus may help clarify what is
entailed. In elections, parties or candidates present themselves to
voters, informing them about their policy intentions.1Specifically,
they tell voters which policies they intend to pursue, for what
purposes, and with which consequences. Once elected, the
victorious candidates choose policies, not necessarily the same as
announced. Having observed the outcomes of the policies, voters
vote again. To introduce an example, suppose that there are
two possible platforms: S (for economic “security”) and E (for
“efficiency”) policies.2Competing parties or candidates promise to
do S or E, and once elected pursue S or E.
Politicians may care both about policies and about being
elected and reelected. Politicians have preferences over policies if
their reward from holding office or the probability of reelection
depends on the policies they adopt. One can think of the reward
from holding office in three ways: politicians may have favorite
policies and derive utility from implementing them, they may want
to advance their private interests, or they may derive satisfaction
from the honor attached to office. Politicians have some beliefs
about the promises that are more likely to make them win and the
policies that voters will in fact appreciate having experienced their
results.
Thus, the question about mandate representation is whether
(1) the policy of the incumbents will be the same as their electoral
platform, and (2) whether pursuing this platform will be best for
voters. The conditions under which mandate representation
occurs are threefold: when politicians’ and voters’ interests
coincide, when politicians are motivated by the desire to be
reelected and they think that voters will reelect them if they
pursue policies on which they campaigned, and when politicians
are concerned about the credibility of their future promises. We
discuss these situations in turn.
1. Interests of politicians coincide with those of voters.3
Citizens and governments have identical interests if govern-
ments want in their self-interest to bring about states of the
world that are most desired by citizens. If politicians and voters
Elections and Representation
31
1Candidates also extol their personal virtues, a topic we treat later.
2The terminology is Elster’s (1994).
3Obviously, the question that arises with such formulations is, Which voters? We
assume in this chapter that, whatever is the dimensionality of the issue space, a
majority rule equilibrium exists and thus there exists a “decisive voter.” For com-
plications that arise when this assumption does not hold, see Ferejohn (1986,
1995).
Manin, Przeworski, and Stokes
32
also have the same beliefs about the effects of policies on outcomes
(“technical beliefs” in the language of Austen-Smith 1990),4then
candidates get elected on the platform most preferred by voters
and as incumbents they implement this platform in their own
interest.
Almost all discussions of representation, beginning with J. S.
Mill’s Considerations on Representative Government (1991 [1861]),
assume that electing politicians who somehow mirror or reproduce
the composition of the electorate achieves representation. The
assembly is representative in this view if it is a miniature of the
electorate, a sample of it. The hypothesis underlying this conviction
is that if the assembly is descriptively representative, then it will
act to represent interests of the represented. As a consequence,
discussions of representative institutions focus almost exclusively
on electoral systems (for an example, see Rogowski 1981). The
pathbreaking, and still unduly ignored, contribution of Pitkin
(1967) was to problematize this connection: is it true that propor-
tionality is the best way to secure representation? If each repre-
sentative puts forth opinions and promotes the interests of his
constituency, will the best interest of the collectivity be served?5
And what if representatives become different from their con-
stituents by the mere fact of being representatives? What if, once
elected, they acquire knowledge the constituents do not have and
perhaps even interests of their own?
2. Politicians want to be elected and reelected.6And they
expect that voters will reelect them if they pursue the policies
4In its pure form, spatial theory of voting is logically incomplete: voters care only
about outcomes but they choose on the basis of policies. What is obviously missing
are “technical beliefs,” as defined earlier. Note that if candidates and voters have
identical interests but different technical beliefs, they will have different induced
preferences about policies.
5One difficulty with this view, manifest in Mill, is that while the assembly may
reflect interests proportionately, many decisions entailed in governing do not
permit proportional allocations. Indeed, many are dichotomous, and in those the
majority prevails while the minority loses. Hence, while proportionality allows all
voices to be heard, it does not guarantee that all interests will be proportionately
accommodated. Thus, as Pitkin points out, the activity of representing entailed
by descriptive representation consists at most of articulating views, not of making
decisions.
6This is true regardless of whether politicians also have other interests as long as
they put a high value on holding office per se.
that they offered in their election campaign. If election-seeking
politicians know the preference of the decisive voter, they offer
a platform that coincides with this preference. If they expect
that voters’ preferences will not change or that these prefer-
ences will be confirmed by observing the outcomes of imple-
menting the mandate (Harrington 1993a), then the incumbents
pursue the announced policy in quest of reelection. And if voters
know what is good for them, the outcome is best for voters, so
that voters’ threat to punish deviations from the mandate is
credible.
3. Politicians are concerned that their promises be credible
in the future. Even if voters believe that a deviation from the
mandate was beneficial for them, they discount future promises
of politicians who acquire a reputation of reneging on their
campaign promises. Hence, voters may threaten the incumbents
to vote against them if they betray their promises, regardless of
the outcomes. This threat is implemented by the rival party in
Alesina’s (1988) model, in which voters are not strategic. In
turn, it is implemented by voters in Banks’s (1990) model, where,
in turn, the credibility of this threat is assumed, rather than
derived.7Hence, this is at best an incomplete story. We return to
it later.
Note that mandate representation is a situation in which
policies adopted by incumbents follow their electoral platforms
and these policies are the best for citizens under the conditions
observed by the incumbents. The three possibilities distinguished
earlier add up to the conclusion that mandate representation
occurs when what politicians and voters want coincides or when
politicians care only about winning elections, and to win they must
promise and implement policies that are best for the public. But
short of this happy coincidence, politicians may have incentives
either to deviate from the mandate in the best interest of the public
or to stick to it at the cost of the electorate.
Elections and Representation
33
7Banks justifies this assumption referring to the multiperiod model of Austen-
Smith and Banks (1989), where the threat of punishing deviations is indeed
credible. But in Austen-Smith and Banks, governments never quite fulfill
promises: when voters expect little of governments, parties always promise
more than they deliver, even though they deliver first best; in turn, when voters
expect a lot, platforms and reelection chances are independent of what voters
want.
Manin, Przeworski, and Stokes
34
To highlight the weakness of the mandate mechanism, suppose
that politicians cannot be reelected even once.8Voters know that
once elected the incumbent will do whatever he wants. Without
the sanction of voting again, voters must guess which of the
competing parties or candidates has policy preferences that
coincide with theirs and which is impervious to the corrupting
sway of office. Yet unless the pool of candidates includes such
politicians and unless voters guess correctly who they are, the
victorious candidates will not act in the representative manner. If
they have policy preferences distinct from those of the decisive
voter, they will deviate from the announced policies; if they pursue
private benefits, they will extract rents.
Moreover, just to get elected, politicians may have to make
promises to special interests. Suppose, in the spirit of the Chicago
School of Regulation (Stigler 1975; Peltzman 1976; Becker 1958,
1983), that (1) voters are ignorant, rationally or not, about the
impact of policies on their welfare, and (2) to present themselves
to voters, politicians need to expend resources, including but not
limited to money. Politicians are concerned only with winning
elections, but to win they must raise resources. Because voters do
not care about policies that have only a small impact on their
welfare, politicians can sell to interest groups policies that inflict
only a small cost on each individual voter but which concentrate
benefits on the particular interest groups and spend on elec-
tioneering the resources contributed by interest groups in
exchange for these policies. Since policies that raise resources
from special interests are costly to voters, politicians choose
policies that make them indifferent at the margin between
increasing voters’ welfare and campaign expenditures, and the
welfare of voters is not maximized.
To take an example, suppose that politicians decide whether to
8In fact, it is enough that the number of elections in which a politician can run is
known and finite. Suppose that the politician will not be able to run after the t-
th term. Then during the (t -1)st election voters will know that in the last term
the politician will have no incentives to seek reelection and will vote against him.
But if the politician will not be reelected for the t-th term, then he will not have
incentives to behave well during the (t -1)st term and voters will not elect him.
But then the same will be true during the (t -2)nd term, . . . , all the way to the
first one. Unless politicians care about voters’ approval when they leave office
for the last time, term limits deprive voters from creating incentives for politicians
to represent them.
subsidize the sugar industry. By subsidizing the sugar industry, the
government inflicts on each individual an annual cost of $5.75 and
benefits the sugar industry to the tune of $1.5 billion. Voters will
not want to spend their resources to learn about the sugar policy
and its effects: this information costs more than $5.75. Then the
government will subsidize, get a campaign contribution from the
industry, and maximize its probability of reelection.9Indeed,
according to the Center for Responsive Policy (New York Times,
January 24, 1997, p. 3), a sugar price subsidy that adds an extra
$50 to a five-pound bag of sugar was supported by sixty-one
senators who received on the average $13,473 from the industry
political action committee, while it was opposed by thirty-five
senators who on the average got $1,461.
The fact is that just to exist and to present themselves to voters,
political parties must raise funds. When these funds come from
special interests, they are exchanged for favors. Presumably, if
Philip Morris Co. Inc. contributed in 1996 over $2.5 million to the
Republican National Committee (New York Times, January 28,
1997, p. 3), it must have expected at least $2.5 million in favors;
otherwise, its management should have been thrown out by
stockholders. Exchanges of political contributions for policy favors
are distorting through their effects on the allocation of resources.
And the social cost of such distortions is likely to be much greater
than that of outright theft, which is distorting only through its
effect on distorting taxes.
Yet situations in which either politicians deviate from their
promises in voters’ best interest or stick to them against the
interests of a majority are possible even if incumbents face
repeated elections and even if electoral campaigns are costless (or
publicly funded).
1. Conditions may change in such a way that the imple-
mentation of the mandate is no longer best for voters. Suppose
Elections and Representation
35
9This argument is subject to two criticisms. One is that if voters are only rationally
ignorant, à la Stigler (1975), governments will be constrained to limit such
policies to those that inflict a small cost on voters: hence, the aggregate loss of
welfare may not be very large. Clearly what matters is how gullible voters are,
and Becker (1983), who drops the assumption that ignorance is only rational,
offers not even an intuition about it. Second (see Arnold 1993 and our subsequent
discussion), there are several groups and most importantly the partisan
opposition that have the interest to diffuse for free information about such
policies.
Manin, Przeworski, and Stokes
36
that immediately upon assuming office an incoming government
that won the election campaigning for policy S learns something
neither it nor the voters knew at the time of the election: the
departing government, competing for reelection, hid the sad
contents of the treasury, and the electoral victors discover upon
assuming office that coffers are empty. Say that S is the better
policy when conditions are good, while E is better when they are
bad. Then the government faces the choice of deviating from the
mandate in the best interest of voters or adhering to it in spite of
the changed circumstances. In turn, voters, who would have
agreed to changing the policy had they observed what the
government observes, must decide whether to believe the
government’s message, which will appear self-serving, without
direct access to this information. And they can err, in either
direction. Hence, incumbents will deviate some of the time and
voters punish some deviations, good or bad.
Note that even changes of conditions that are endogenous to
government policy, but were unforeseen by politicians before they
reached office, may be reasons to change course in the interest
of citizens’ welfare; the 1983 switch of the French Socialist
government may be a case in point.
2. To be elected, a candidate must offer the platform preferred
by the decisive voter. Suppose a candidate believes that the
decisive voter has incorrect beliefs about the effect of policies on
outcomes. This candidate then faces a choice of offering a platform
that she thinks is better for voters and going down to defeat
(perhaps hoping to win the next time around, if the competitor
implements less effective policies) or proposing what voters want
and having at least a 50–50 chance of winning (if the other
competitor offers the same platform). If the incumbent believes
that the less popular policy is sufficiently more effective than the
one voters prefer, he or she anticipates that, having observed its
effects, voters will become persuaded that the correct policy was
chosen and will vote to reelect, so that the politician will be able
to continue the policy that is in effect better for citizens.
Two situations need to be further distinguished. In one
(Harrington 1993a: sec. 4), the two candidates have the same
beliefs about the preferences of the decisive voter but different
beliefs about the effectiveness of policies, meaning that one of
them thinks the decisive voter is wrong. Then they offer the same
platform in the electoral campaign but once elected may pursue
different policies. If the winner is the candidate who believes that
the policy preferred by the decisive voter is significantly inferior
to the alternative, the incumbent adopts the policy she prefers, in
the belief that voters will be persuaded about its superiority once
the outcomes materialize. In such situations, we should observe
candidates offering the same platform and then sometimes
deviating from the mandate.
In the second situation, the two candidates have the same
beliefs about the effectiveness of policies but differ in their beliefs
about the preference of the decisive voter. If elected, they pursue
the same policy, but to get elected they offer different platforms.
If the winner is the candidate who believed that the voters are
mistaken, the incumbent switches policies once elected. In such
situations, we should observe candidates offering different
platforms and then pursuing the same policy regardless of who is
elected.
Note that in both of these situations candidates (may) deviate
from their platforms once elected, but they deviate believing that
they are acting in the best interest of the electorate.
3. Suppose that everything is the same as just described but
the incumbent does not believe that voters will be persuaded by
the effectiveness of the better policy – either because voters are
quite certain which policy is better for them or because the policy
choice does not make a great difference. As Harrington (1993a)
shows, if voters initially believe that one policy is better than the
other, they are harder to convince ex post of the superiority of the
alternative.10 Fearing that if he proposes one platform and pursues
another he will not be reelected, the incumbent offers the inferior
platform that voters prefer and implements it, against what
he believes are citizens’ best interests. The mandate will be
implemented, but politicians will not act in a representative
manner.
To summarize: under some conditions, incumbents may either
pursue policies that enhance that welfare of voters by deviating
Elections and Representation
37
10 The intuition is the following. Suppose that voters initially believe that policy S
is better for them than E by some amount e. If they observe an outcome of
implementing E that is better than S by the amount e, their posterior belief will
be that E produces outcomes at a level between their initial expectations and
their observation, which will still be below S. To be persuaded that E is better
than S, the outcome of E would have to be better than the prior on S by more
than e.
Manin, Przeworski, and Stokes
38
from the mandate or they may adhere to the mandate even if
they think that implementing it is not best for voters. And if
implementing the mandate is not the best the government can do,
then the threat of punishing incumbents who deviate from it is not
credible. Voters may not like governments that betray promises,
but they will not punish politicians who made them sufficiently
better off by deviating from the mandate.
This impunity is mitigated by reputational considerations
(Downs 1957; Ferejohn 1995). Politicians may be concerned about
adhering to promises as an investment in credibility. Indeed, the
Polish government was said to “be forced to remind itself of the
promises of 1993 and to make some concessions to the voters,
under the penalty of losing its credibility” (Krauze 1994). If
incumbents anticipate that voters will not only look at their past
policies but also pay attention to their new promises, that is, if
their past performance in office is not fully informative, they must
be concerned about being believed, which, in turn, moderates
their temptation to deviate from the old promises. A politician
who executed a pirouette will have to rely solely on his past
performance when seeking reelection, while a politician who stuck
to promises will be more likely to be believed next time around.
In turn, voters may want to punish politicians who renege on
their promises as an investment in information. After all, voters
want their choices to have consequences; hence, they want to be
able to predict the behavior of politicians from their campaign
platforms, rhetoric, or identity. Politicians may claim that un-
foreseen circumstances are the reason they deviated from their
mandates. But they have some explaining to do, which is prima
facie evidence that they think they are expected to follow
mandates.
While such reputational mechanisms may encourage the
incumbents to adhere to electoral promises, a striking feature
of democratic institutions, highlighted by Manin (1997), is that
politicians are not legally compelled to abide by their platform in
any democratic system. In no existing democracy are repre-
sentatives subject to binding instructions. Citizens’ suits against
governments that betrayed specific campaign promises have been
rejected by courts in several countries, most recently in Poland.
No national-level democratic constitution allows for recall, and,
except for the U.S. House of Representatives, electoral terms tend
to be long – on the average, 3.7 years for legislatures and 3.9 years
for presidents (Cheibub and Przeworski, Chapter 7 in this volume).
While provisions for impeachment and procedures for with-
drawing confidence are common, they are never targeted at the
betrayal of promises.11 Binding national referenda based on
citizens’ initiative are found only in Switzerland and, in more
restrictive forms, in Italy and Argentina. Hence, once citizens elect
representatives, they have no institutional devices to force them
to adhere to promises. Voters can sanction deviations from
mandates only after their effects have been experienced.
Why then are there no institutional mechanisms to force
officeholders to be faithful to their platforms? Historically, the
main argument was that legislatures should be allowed to
deliberate. People want their representatives to learn, one from
another. Moreover, when people are uncertain about their
judgments, they may want representatives to consult experts.
Another historical argument was that voters may not trust their
own judgments. People not only may be afraid of their own
passions but, if they are rationally ignorant, they must know that
they do not know. Presumably, elections establish the calendar for
when the accounts are to be taken. Hence, citizens may want to
give the government some latitude to govern and evaluate
government’s actions at election times. O’Flaherty (1990) argues
that this is a reason to elect politicians for fixed terms; in this
way citizens can guard themselves against inconsistent time
preferences and yet exercise ex post control.
Finally, institutions must allow for changing conditions. No
electoral platform can specify ex ante what the government should
do in every contingent state of nature; governments must have
some flexibility in coping with changing circumstances. If citizens
expect that conditions may change and governments are likely to
be representative, they will not want to bind governments by their
instructions.12
Hence, there are good reasons why democratic institutions
Elections and Representation
39
11 Occasionally a deviation from mandates provides part of the impetus for
impeachment, even though deviation is not the formal justification. Two recent
presidents who abandoned their campaign promises, in Venezuela and Ecuador,
were impeached, one immediately, with no time allowed for the outcomes to
materialize.
12 Minford (1995: 105) observes in the context of monetary policy that “if voters
have little information, they may prefer to let governments have complete
discretion, regardless of the lack of credibility, rather than tie their hands.”
Manin, Przeworski, and Stokes
40
contain no mechanisms enforcing adherence to mandates. We
choose policies that represent our interests or candidates who
represent us as persons, but we want governments to be able to
govern. As a result, while we would prefer governments to stick
to their promises, democracy contains no institutional mech-
anisms that insure that our choices would be respected.
The Accountability Conception of Representation
Even if citizens are unable to control governments by obliging
them to follow mandates, citizens may be able to do so if they can
induce the incumbents to anticipate that they will have to render
accounts for their past actions. Governments are “accountable” if
voters can discern whether governments are acting in their
interest and sanction them appropriately, so that those incumbents
who act in the best interest of citizens win reelection and those
who do not lose them. Accountability representation occurs when
(1) voters vote to retain the incumbent only when the incumbent
acts in their best interest, and (2) the incumbent chooses policies
necessary to get reelected.
To understand why the problem of accountability arises, we
must consider again politicians’ objectives. Politicians may want
to do nothing that well-informed citizens would not have wanted
them to do; they may be public-spirited and dedicate themselves
fully to furthering the public interest. But they may also want
something different from and costly to citizens, whether just some
goals that citizens do not share, reelection, or private gains.
Politicians may want to pursue their own ideas even if these differ
from those of citizens.13 Some may care most about advancing
their careers against fellow politicians, within the government or
the same party. Some may seek perks (Niskanen 1971). Some may
want to get rich at the expense of citizens, while in office or after
leaving it. Some may be most concerned about recognition by
foreigners. In all these cases politicians will want something whose
pursuit is injurious to citizens. For a lack of a better term and to
keep with the standard terminology, we will refer to this something
as “rents.”
To introduce another term standard in this literature, there are
13 Suppose that in a poor country people want to consume immediately while
benevolent politicians want to develop the country by increasing investment.
different ways in which politicians can “shirk,” that is, do things
that citizens would not want them to do. They shirk if they spend
time conspiring against their rivals. They shirk if they act to
increase their own wealth. They shirk if they extend clientilistic
favors to their families and friends. But the most important way
in which they can act against the best interests of their con-
stituents is by choosing policies that advance their own interests
or the interests of some special interests to which they are
beholden.
The problem facing citizens is then to set up a trade-off for
politicians – between extracting rents and losing office or not
extracting rents and staying in office – that would induce them to
keep rents low, where keeping rents low may mean just doing
what voters want. The standard view of how the accountability
mechanism operates relies on “retrospective voting.” In this view,
citizens set some standard of performance to evaluate gov-
ernments, such as “My income must increase by at least 4 percent
during the term,” “Streets must be safe,” or even “The national
team must qualify for the World Cup.” They vote against the
incumbent unless these criteria are fulfilled. In turn, the
government, wanting to be reelected and anticipating the citizens’
decision rule, does whatever possible to satisfy these criteria.
Imagine that the conditions under which the government
makes decisions can be “good” or “bad.” Governments decide
whether to implement policy S, which is better for citizens when
conditions are good, or policy E, which is better when conditions
are bad. Suppose that the rents the incumbents obtain when they
do all they can for the public consist just of their salaries and
legally authorized perks of office, and suppose that the incumbents
value being reelected. To make this analysis less abstract, examine
a numerical example in which the legally qualified rents equal r*
=1 +e, where eis some small number, and the value of being
reelected is V =2.
Let the structure of payoffs be as follows (the first number in
each pair represents government rents, but citizens observe only
their welfare, which is the second number):
Government
Implement S Implement E
“Good” 1 +e, 5 3, 3
Conditions
“Bad” 3, 1 1 +e, 3
Elections and Representation
41
Manin, Przeworski, and Stokes
42
Suppose now that the electorate knows everything it needs to
know. Then, to induce politicians to act as well as they can under
the circumstances, voters set their reelection rule as “When
conditions are good, vote for the incumbent if the outcome is at
least 5. When conditions are bad, vote for the incumbent if the
outcome is at least 3; otherwise throw the rascals out.” A
government facing good conditions knows that by choosing S it will
get r* =1 +eand it will be certainly reelected, thus obtaining r*
+V >3, where 3 is the most it can get by choosing E and not being
reelected. In turn, a government facing bad conditions knows that
by choosing E it will get r* +V >3, which is what it would get
by adopting S. Hence, the government acts in a representative
manner and citizens get the most they can under either conditions.
Accountability induces representation (Key 1966). As Fiorina
(1981: 11) put it: “Given political actors who fervently desire to
retain their positions and who carefully anticipate public reaction
to their records as a means to that end, a retrospective voting
electorate will enforce electoral accountability, albeit in an ex post,
not an ex ante, sense.”
Yet suppose that voters do not know what the conditions are.
Politicians know these conditions, but voters may be unable to
observe them at all or they may be able to monitor them only
at a cost. Such conditions may include the negotiating posture
of foreign governments or international financial institutions
(something citizens cannot observe) or the level of demand in the
major recipients of the country’s exports (something voters can
observe only if they turn into economists). Then voters are in a
quandary. If they set the standard the incumbent must meet at 5
and conditions turn out to be bad, the incumbent cannot be
reelected whatever he does and he will seek excess rents. In turn,
if voters set the standard at 3, the incumbent will be able to extract
excess rents when the conditions happen to be good and be
reelected by giving voters less than he could have given them.
Whatever voters decide to do, politicians will sometimes escape
from their control.
One aspect of incomplete information merits particular
attention. Note that the voters who animated the previous pages
were myopic: they were concerned only with the change of their
welfare during the current term. But if voters are fully rational,
they should also care at the end of the term about the present
value of their future welfare: the legacy the incumbent leaves
for the future. If the economy grows because the government cuts
all the trees in the country, the voter will live on champagne during
the term, but there will be no trees left to cut. In turn, if the
economy declined because it underwent structural reforms, voters
will have suffered economic deprivation but may have improved
their life chances for the future. Yet all that voters observe is the
change of welfare during the term, and they have to make
inferences about the future on this basis. Say that voters observe
that their current welfare declines: should they infer that the
government is investing in their future or pursuing some
(neoliberal) chimeras of its own or just robbing them blind?
Following Stokes (1996a), note that voters can adopt one of three
postures:
1. They can extrapolate the present experience into the future. This
is the “normal” posture, insofar as this is what models of retro-
spective voting normally assume.
2. They can assume an “intertemporal” posture (Przeworski 1996),
expecting that the worse things have gotten, the better they augur
for the future.
3. They can assume an “exonerating” posture, attributing the decline
of their welfare to bad conditions, rather than to anything the
government did.
It is hard to tell what is rational for people to do under these
circumstances. Some empirical work on neoliberal reforms in new
democracies (Przeworski 1996; Stokes 1996b) suggests that
people are willing to exonerate governments for inflation and to
treat increases of wages intertemporally, as forecasting inflation,
but that they are risk-averse about unemployment and turn
against governments that generate it. Yet other studies come to
the conclusion that people are sensitive to inflation and relatively
indifferent to unemployment (Rose 1997; Weyland 1996). In any
case, there is little on which people can base these judgments.
Accountability models of elections assume typically that while
voters do not know something that they need to know to evaluate
governments, incumbents do know what they need to do in order
to be reelected. The implicit artifice on which these models rely is
that voters offer a contract to the government: “if you give us at
least this, we will vote for you; otherwise, we will not.” Yet voters
do not offer such contracts. Note that we could cast not only ballots
but also a list of our conditions for reelecting the incumbent. But
Elections and Representation
43
Manin, Przeworski, and Stokes
44
we do not, and we do not because we want governments to do all
they can for us, rather than just fulfill our minimal demands.
Indeed, Manin (1997) points out that voters can decide whether to
reelect the incumbent on any basis they want, including qualifying
for the World Cup, and that they can change their mind between
the beginning and the end of a term. At least in this way, voters
are sovereign.
Hence, a question arises about how the incumbent will act if
information is asymmetric both ways: when voters are not cer-
tain about the conditions under which policies are made but
incumbents are uncertain what would satisfy voters. It can be
shown (Cheibub and Przeworski, Chapter 7 in this volume) that
when incumbents very much care about being reelected, they will
represent, always pursuing policies appropriate to the conditions
they observe, so that voters are better off keeping their
expectations secret. When, however, incumbents care less about
being reelected and, in turn, voters expect that conditions are
likely to be good, voters are better off formulating exacting
demands and making them known to politicians. Finally, when
incumbents attach less value to being reelected and voters expect
conditions to be bad, there is nothing voters can do to prevent
incumbents from extracting excess rents when conditions happen
to be good. Hence, voters are better off if they can reveal or not
reveal their demands strategically. But to do so, they must still
know how much the incumbent cares about being reelected and
how likely it is that conditions are good.
In sum, accountability is not sufficient to induce representation
when voters have incomplete information.
Using the Vote for Two Purposes
In a pure accountability model, voters use the vote only for
one purpose, which is to sanction the incumbent, and the entire
information available to voters is revealed by the performance
of the incumbent. In a pure mandate model, voters compare
promises candidates make about the future, and use the vote only
to choose the better candidate. In Downs’s (1957; also Fiorina
1981) model, voters use the information about the past per-
formance of the incumbent and, if available, of challengers, but
this is also a mandate model in the sense that voters use the
information about the past only to choose a better government for
the future. Indeed, Sniderman, Glaser, and Griffin (1990) claim
that purely retrospective voting would be irrational: rational
people look forward. Yet this is not right: if voters can credibly
employ their vote only to sanction the incumbent, threatening to
use it this way is a perfectly rational way of inducing governments
to act well in the future.
For all we know, voters do not meditate whether to use the one
instrument they have, the vote, to choose a better government or
to structure incentives for incumbents. Fearon (Chapter 2 in this
volume) offers persuasive stories to the effect that voters want to
select good policies and politicians. Yet voting “to keep them
honest” seems also ingrained in the repertoire of the democratic
culture. The fact remains that voters have only one instrument to
reach two goals: to select better policies and politicians, and to
induce them to behave well while in office. The question then is
what happens when voters try to use the vote for both purposes.
Suppose that, believing that politicians are not all the same,
voters are swayed by the prospect of electing better governments.
Voters may believe that the challenger is more competent, having
a better understanding of the relation between policies and
outcomes, or is more honest, being willing to accept lower rents
in exchange for holding public office. An election takes place, an
incumbent is installed, both the incumbent and the electorate
observe the objective conditions, voters set their voting rule,
incumbents choose rents, and voters vote again. Having observed
what happened during the term, voters vote for a challenger with
the probability that the challenger will be better than the
incumbent (in the sense that she would have generated higher
welfare under the same conditions). Anticipating that voters will
vote for the challenger with some positive probability, the
incumbent will then require a higher level of rents. Thus the rents
that are necessary to induce the incumbent to seek reelection
when voters use the vote as a selection device are larger than in
the case when voters are only concerned about incentives for the
incumbent. Using the vote to choose a better government
prospectively is costly to voters in terms of their control over the
incumbent (see Fearon, Chapter 2 in this volume).
Note immediately that the following nightmare may arise
(Ferejohn 1986; Banks and Sundaram 1993): if voters always think
that the challenger is better, then the incumbent can never be
reelected, and he will always choose to extract high rents. In turn,
Elections and Representation
45
Manin, Przeworski, and Stokes
46
if incumbents extract high rents, voters will never vote for them.
The incumbent knows that voters will always be swayed by the
promises of the challenger and always extract maximal rents,
which means that if voters believe that politicians are not all the
same, they are certain that the challengers will be better for them.
In this situation, voters’ control breaks down completely.14
Yet, while voters may be gullible, they cannot be that
ingenuous. The performance of the incumbent is informative. As
Bartels (1988) discovered, in the United States at least, the past
performance of a president is a good predictor of his future per-
formance (and not of a challenger’s). Thus, voters who use their
vote prospectively have good reasons to rely on retrospective
information. Harrington (1993b) shows that the more uncertain
voters are about the effect of policies on outcomes, the more they
should rely on information about past performance. They can
observe the past performance of the incumbent and then decide
how likely it is that a challenger is better. Nevertheless, as long as
voters use their vote to elect a better government, they must lower
the power of incentives for the incumbent.
Madison (Federalist no. 57) thought that “The aim of every
political constitution is, or ought to be, first to obtain for rulers
men who possess most wisdom to discern, and most virtue to
pursue, the common good of the society; and in the next place, to
take the most effectual precautions for keeping them virtuous
whilst they continue to hold their public trust.” Using the vote for
both purposes – to obtain the best rulers and to keep them virtuous
– is not irrational: while voters lose some control over the
incumbent, in exchange they elect a better government. Yet the
system Madison and his colleagues designed makes it possible to
strive for one goal only at the expense of the other.
Institutions, Elections, and Representation
Democracies are not all the same, and it is possible that some
democratic systems foster representation better than others.
14 This may seem farfetched. But several countries, notably Ecuador and Poland,
experienced a series of elections in which the challenger promised to pursue an
expansionary policy, was believed by voters, switched upon election to a con-
tractionary one, to be defeated by a challenger promising an expansionary
policy, etc.
While we have little systematic knowledge about the effects of
particular institutional arrangements on voters’ control over
politicians, some institutional factors merit attention.
1. Voters must be able to assign clearly the responsibility for
government performance. Their ability to do so is limited when
the government is a coalition. It is also limited when the pres-
idency and the congress are controlled by different parties. It takes
an elaborate theory of government to figure out who is responsible
for what under such conditions (but see Anderson 1995).
Hamilton argued in Federalist no. 70 that accountability is
obscured under a plural, that is, cabinet executive: “But one of the
weightiest objections to a plurality in the executive . . . is that it
tends to conceal faults and destroy responsibility....The cir-
cumstances which may have led to any national miscarriage
or misfortune are sometimes so complicated that there are a
number of actors who have different degrees and kinds of agency,
though we may clearly see upon the whole that there has been
mismanagement, yet it may be impracticable to pronounce to
whose account the evil which may have been incurred is truly
chargeable.” But a similar ambiguity arises in presidential
systems. Bagehot (1992: 67) expressed this view most forcefully:
“Two clever men never exactly agree about a budget.
. . . They are sure to quarrel, and the result is sure to satisfy
neither. And when the taxes do not yield as they were expected to
yield, who is responsible? Very likely the secretary of the treasury
could not persuade the chairman – very likely the chairman could
not persuade his committee – very likely the committee could not
persuade the assembly. Whom, then, can you punish – whom can
you abolish – when your taxes run short?”
The empirical findings concerning clarity of responsibility, most
of them due to Powell and his collaborators, are confusing.
Majority-inducing institutions increase the distance between the
ideal position of the median voter and of the government (Huber
and Powell 1996), but they increase what Powell (1990) measures
as the “clarity of responsibility,” which, in turn, makes voting
for incumbents more sensitive to economic performance (Powell
and Whitten 1993). Hence, it seems that majoritarian institu-
tions generate governments that are farther from voters in policy
space but more accountable. The relation between citizens’
preferences and the actual policies – not studied by Powell – is
thus indeterminate.
Elections and Representation
47
Manin, Przeworski, and Stokes
48
2. Voters must be able to vote out of office parties responsible
for bad performance, and the parties they select must be able to
enter government. These may appear to be universal features
of democracy, but under some electoral systems they are next
to impossible: witness the continued tenure of the Christian
Democrats in Italy or of the LDP in Japan, or the weak connection
between voting results and electoral outcomes in Bolivia. As
Pasquino (1994: 25) put it with regard to Italy, “governing parties
seemed to expropriate the voters of the political influence by
making and unmaking governments at all levels with very little
respect for electoral results.”
3. Politicians must have incentives to want to be reelected. This
condition becomes problematic when there are limitations on
reeligibility, ubiquitous in presidential systems (Cheibub and
Przeworski, Chapter 7 in this volume), and when political parties
are not continuing bureaucratic organizations that offer their
militants career prospects (Zielinski 1997). Paldam (1991)
observed that the coefficients of the function relating the
probability of reelection to economic outcomes are higher and
their estimates are tighter when the party system is stable.
4. The opposition must monitor the performance of the
government and inform citizens. Indeed, any reasonable under-
standing of representation must include the opposition. Citizens
have two agents, not just one: the incumbents who govern and the
opposition that wants to become the government. The opposition
is an agent of citizens because it wants to win office and, in order
to win office, it must also anticipate the retrospective judgments
that voters will make about the incumbents at election time.
Anticipating these judgments, the opposition has incentives to
monitor the government and to inform (truthfully or not) voters
about the performance of the incumbents.
Yet the existence of an opposition that wants to and can
monitor government performance should not be taken for granted.
Opposition can collude with the government15 or it can be so
15 Crain (1977) argued that in a single-member, single-district electoral system
incumbents are unlikely to ever run against each other and that they therefore
share an interest in raising barriers to entry of challengers from either party.
Dasgupta (1993) offered another model of collusion and an argument that we
should subsidize new parties.
... gobierno representativo constituye el sustento de una accountability que es denominada "electoral" y considerada como el principal mecanismo de sintonización entre representante y representados; mecanismo, no obstante, con conocidas limitaciones como mecanismo efectivo de control democrático (Przeworski et al., 1999;Powell, 2000). ...
... asumiendo que la primera preferencia de los políticos es reelegirse y sabiendo que serán evaluados en las elecciones, ellos deciden políticas anticipando los efectos de tales políticas en el veredicto electoral de los ciudadanos; estos, a su vez, examinan retrospectivamente la elección de los incumbentes y les renuevan el mandato o "los echan a la calle", optando por las promesas de campaña de la oposición (Przeworski et al., 1999). Así entendido, el funcionamiento de la accountability electoral depende de demasiados supuestos: por ejemplo, en relación con el electorado, sobre la memoria, nitidez de los efectos de las políticas, existencia de información fidedigna y preferencias ideológicas razonables. ...
Article
Full-text available
Qué se espera que los ciudadanos controlen en una democracia? Revista do Serviço Público (RSP), Brasília 75(especial A) 10-34 agosto 2024 | 10 El artículo examina cuatro argumentos generales con amplia circulación e influencia y que ofrecen respuestas típicas a la pregunta ¿Qué se espera que los ciudadanos controlen en una democracia? Las respuestas dependen de cómo se entiende la relación entre democracia, representación, participación y control. Esos elementos encuentran formulación cristalizada en los cuatro argumentos que constituyen un continuum de posibilidades: el control como veredicto del pueblo, el control como conexión substantiva entre representantes y representados, el control como soberanía popular efectiva y el control como la realización de procesos decisorios inclusivos. El desarrollo del último argumento ha sido estimulado por procesos de innovación democrática en relación con los cuales América Latina, y especialmente Brasil, han sido referencia en el debate internacional. Sustentamos la importancia del control sobre las funciones del Estado (las políticas y no sólo la política) y desarrollamos una respuesta centrada en la participación como control social, examinando los límites, supuestos y ventajas de los argumentos generales.
... Scrutinizing the strength of responsiveness, early studies on the topic often reported optimistic results. On average, the governments of many established democracies in Europe and North America seemed to follow the will of their publics (see, e.g., Brooks & Manza, 2006Budge et al., 2012;Cohen, 1999;Erikson et al., 2002;Hobolt & Klemmensen, 2008;Kang & Powell, 2010;Przeworski et al., 1999;Rasmussen et al., 2019;Roberts & Kim, 2011;Soroka & Wlezien, 2010;Wlezien, 2004). All these studies found at least some empirical evidence in favour of the relevance of public opinion for policymaking -or for the congruence between government ideology and policy outputs. ...
Article
Full-text available
Government responsiveness is a key feature and justification for democracy. Yet, previous studies show that the ability of governments to deliver responsive policies critically depends on the availability of resources. This study suggests that the shadow economy hurts democratic responsiveness because it reduces government revenues and decreases the reliability of economic statistics. Governments facing lower resources then respond to wider economic constraints and not to their publics. Using Eurobarometer data to evaluate public opinion in 15 European democracies and data on welfare generosity to measure policy outputs, this study finds that larger submerged economies correspond to less responsive governments. Additionally, the empirical analysis highlights that the shadow economy makes welfare systems less generous and taxation rates more demanding. These novel results have important implications for our understanding of democracy and help us clarify the conditions under which governments are more or less likely to deliver responsive policies. Finally, these results demonstrate the importance of studying the political consequences of the shadow economy.
... Although modern democracies build on the idea of representation, representation is in itself a convoluted theoretical concept (Manin et al., 1999;Mansbridge, 1999Mansbridge, , 2003Mansbridge, , 2011Phillips, 1995;Pitkin, 1967). It is multidimensional and comprises, potentially, four dimensions: formal representation, descriptive representation, substantive representation, and symbolic representation (Franceschet et al., 2012;Lawless, 2004;Pitkin, 1967;Schwindt-Bayer and Mishler, 2005). ...
Article
Full-text available
This study examines the potential link between descriptive and substantive representation. More precisely, we examine whether a higher level of political descriptive representation of women improves their substantive representation in terms of policy spending in areas that are known to be prioritized by women. We use data from a pooled sample of all of the 290 Swedish municipalities covering the years from 1994 to 2021. We make at least four contributions to the research field: we use multiple measures of (1) women’s political representation and (2) policy spending, and we also (3) test assumptions at the subnational level, where policy spending matters most, and (4) assess them over a longer period of time, stretching across almost three decades. In contrast to our expectations, the findings show that the descriptive representation of women has no influence on policy spending; instead, economic and demographical aspects dominate.
Article
Full-text available
El incumplimiento de las promesas hechas por los políticos se percibe como una práctica frecuente en los países de América Latina, afectando, entre otros aspectos, la confianza ciudadana hacia la democracia. En este artículo se analizan cuatro países —Colombia, Ecuador, Perú y Bolivia— que presentan casos únicos en el mundo al implementar un mecanismo particular de rendición de cuentas: la revocatoria de mandato por incumplimiento del programa electoral. Principalmente, se busca responder a la pregunta: ¿cómo ha sido el desarrollo de la aplicación de este mecanismo? Para ello se analizan diferentes aspectos, desde el marco legal que da forma a este mecanismo, hasta su implementación en los diferentes países. Asimismo, se presta especial atención a la discusión teórica que ha existido en torno a los «mandatos vinculantes». El análisis comparado permitió identificar que se trata de un mecanismo con fortalezas, pero también serias debilidades, sobre todo, en su implementación, las cuales tienen que ser atendidas con miras a mejorar estos mecanismos tan relevantes en estos países.
Article
Full-text available
The functioning of representative democracy depends on a “responsible electorate” that rewards and punishes parties according to their promises. Holding representatives accountable is the only way for voters to keep control over the government. This article draws on the normative assumption of accountability theory to investigate the impact of information on pledge fulfillment on citizens’ trust in government, taking into account moderators of this relationship. In a two-wave panel experiment ( N = 841; broken pledges, fulfilled pledges, control group), results supported the hypotheses that fulfilled election pledges resulted in increased trust in the government, whereas broken pledges decreased trust. However, only when citizens had been satisfied with the government’s performance in the past or when they attributed relevance to governmental pledge fulfillment did trust levels depend on pledge fulfillment. These findings provide insights into the process of democratic accountability and highlight the relevance of trust in studying the effects of election pledges. Additionally, our study makes a case for the use of repeated measurements in experimental research, as examining intraindividual changes can provide a more comprehensive understanding, such as by assessing effect sizes.
Article
Satisfaction with democracy is a widely studied measure of political support that is key for democratic stability. In this article, I explore its relationship with party system closure, that is the extent to which inter-party relations in the governmental area are stable and predictable. I argue that this relationship captures a trade-off between two key democratic outputs: representation and accountability. Analysing a dataset of 755 observations from 26 European countries throughout the period 1973–2019, I show that this trade-off manifests in an ‘inverted-U’ shaped relationship between party system closure and satisfaction with democracy. This result implies an optimal level of party system closure which reconciles the tension between the two in a way that maximises satisfaction with democracy.
Chapter
Election pledges are a key topic in democracies, as well as in both public and scientific debates. They constitute an integral part of the representative relationship between political parties and citizens. There is kind of a “natural expectation” that electoral promises are meant to be kept. Especially before elections, the public and media show a high interest in parties’ election pledges and their performance in fulfilling or breaking their promises.
Chapter
Is there such a thing as retrospective pledge voting (RPV)? Thus, are government parties rewarded for pledge fulfilment? And do they have to fear electoral punishments if they fail to deliver on their election pledges? While there isn’t ample evidence supporting a reward effect, there is strong evidence of a punishment effect. This happened not only to the German liberal party FDP, that was sure of victory, but experienced a tremendous electoral loss in 2013 after having failed to keep many of its pledges.
Chapter
The findings of this book improve our understanding of democratic processes and the relation between parties and voters. The findings can—and should—enrich debates in normative democratic theory and also stimulate public debates beyond academic circles on what good government performance means.
Chapter
This chapter introduces the main theoretical concepts and provides theoretical arguments for why a government party’s election outcome is expected to depend on its pledge performance. This theory of retrospective pledge voting (RPV) offers an integrative perspective between different models on voting: it combines a prospective oriented approach emphasising the crucial role of preferential differences between parties for citizens’ vote decisions, and retrospective oriented approaches focussing on electoral sanctioning of government performance.
ResearchGate has not been able to resolve any references for this publication.