ArticlePDF Available

On the Minskyan business cycle

Authors:

Abstract

The essential insight Minsky drew from Keynes was that optimistic expectations about the future create a margin, reflected in higher asset prices, which makes it possible for borrowers to access finance in the present. In other words, the capitalized expected future earnings work as the collateral against which firms can borrow in financial markets or from banks. But, then, the value of long-lived assets cannot be assessed on any firm basis, as they are highly sensitive to the degree of confidence that markets have about certain events and circumstances that will unfold in the future. This means that any sustained shortfall in economic performance in relation to the level of expectations that are already capitalized in asset prices may promote the view that asset prices are excessive. Once the view that asset prices are excessive takes hold in financial markets, higher asset prices cease to be a stimulant. Initially debt-led, the economy becomes debt-burdened. In this article, it is argued that Keynes’s views on the alternation of the bull and bear sentiment and asset price speculation over the business cycle can explain two of Minsky’s central propositions relative to business cycle turning points that have often been found less than fully persuasive: (1) that financial fragility increases gradually over the expansion, and, (2) that the interest rate sooner or later, increases setting off a downward spiral bringing the expansion to an end.
Working Paper No. 474
On the Minskyan Business Cycle
by
Korkut A. Erturk
University of Utah
and
The Levy Economics Institute of Bard College
erturk@economics.utah.edu
August 2006
The Levy Economics Institute Working Paper Collection presents research in progress by
Levy Institute scholars and conference participants. The purpose of the series is to
disseminate ideas to and elicit comments from academics and professionals.
The Levy Economics Institute of Bard College, founded in 1986, is a nonprofit,
nonpartisan, independently funded research organization devoted to public service.
Through scholarship and economic research it generates viable, effective public policy
responses to important economic problems that profoundly affect the quality of life in
the United States and abroad.
The Levy Economics Institute
P.O. Box 5000
Annandale-on-Hudson, NY 12504-5000
http://www.levy.org
Copyright © The Levy Economics Institute 2006 All rights reserved.
1
ABSTRACT
The essential insight Minsky drew from Keynes was that optimistic expectations about
the future create a margin, reflected in higher asset prices, which makes it possible for
borrowers to access finance in the present. In other words, the capitalized expected future
earnings work as the collateral against which firms can borrow in financial markets or
from banks. But, then, the value of long-lived assets cannot be assessed on any firm
basis, as they are highly sensitive to the degree of confidence that markets have about
certain events and circumstances that will unfold in the future. This means that any
sustained shortfall in economic performance in relation to the level of expectations that
are already capitalized in asset prices may promote the view that asset prices are
excessive. Once the view that asset prices are excessive takes hold in financial markets,
higher asset prices cease to be a stimulant. Initially debt-led, the economy becomes debt-
burdened. In this article, it is argued that Keynes’s views on the alternation of the “bull”
and “bear” sentiment and asset price speculation over the business cycle can explain two
of Minsky’s central propositions relative to business cycle turning points that have often
been found less than fully persuasive: (1) that financial fragility increases gradually over
the expansion, and, (2) that the interest rate sooner or later, increases setting off a
downward spiral bringing the expansion to an end.
Keywords: Minsky, two-price theory, speculation, financial fragility
JEL Codes: B22, E12, E44
2
INTRODUCTION
Minsky’s seminal contribution was to underscore the importance of speculation in
economic activity. Emphasizing that a firm’s investment decision is inherently a
speculative one, he reintroduced asset prices back into Keynesian theory of investment.
Any decision to acquire real capital assets, as he was keen to emphasize, bequeaths the
firm with a certain liability structure that shapes its balance sheet for a long time to come.
This liability structure is either validated or contradicted by future events, with possibly
dire consequences as firms’ expected returns might never be realized. Yet, despite this
emphasis on the speculative character of investment decisions, Minsky paid little
attention to asset price speculation per se, ignoring asset price bubbles and their
macroeconomic effects.
From the point of view of history of thought, Minsky can be seen to have revived
a good part of Keynes’s analysis in the Treatise (Kregel 1992) that was eclipsed by the
General Theory. But, at the same time, he not only ignored the role asset price
speculation played in Keynes’s analysis of the business cycle in the Treatise, but also,
generally refrained from crediting this work as the source of his “two-price” theory. In
Keynes’s famous Quarterly Journal of Economics article (Keynes 1937a), which Minsky
extensively referenced throughout his work, Keynes talked about how people in financial
markets tend to fall back on convention in forming expectations about an uncertain
future, and emphasized how valuations can change drastically and violently because
doubts of panic have a life of their own close to the surface. In the Treatise, the changing
size of the bear position was the very index of what was brewing under the surface, of
what he called the “other view.” It provided a convenient setting for analyzing the
macroeconomic effects of asset prices the preponderance of market opinion held to be
misaligned (Erturk 2006). This was the thread of the argument in the Treatise Minsky
overlooked, either because his views were formed during the era of financial regulation,
when speculation “could do no harm as bubbles on a steady stream of enterprise,” or,
perhaps, he just wanted to stay clear of the acrimonious debates that broke out between
Keynes and his critics on the rate of interest after the publication of the General Theory.
Whatever might have been Minsky’s real reason, we neither can know nor does it matter
that we do. What, however, is worthwhile is to discuss the importance of the missing part
3
of the analysis from the Treatise for Minsky’s own account of how a business cycle
expansion comes to an end. The point of the article is to make that connection.
The essential insight Minsky drew from Keynes was that optimistic expectations
about the future create a margin, reflected in higher asset prices, which makes it possible
for borrowers to access finance in the present. In other words, the capitalized expected
future earnings work as the collateral against which firms can borrow in financial markets
or from banks. But, the value of long-lived assets cannot be assessed on any firm basis as
they are highly sensitive to the degree of confidence markets have about certain states of
the world coming to pass in the future. This means that any sustained shortfall in
economic performance in relation to the level of expectations that are already capitalized
in asset prices is susceptible to engendering the view that asset prices are excessive. Once
the view that asset prices are excessive takes hold in financial markets, higher asset prices
cease to be a stimulant and turn into a drag on the economy. Initially debt-led, the
economy becomes debt-burdened.
In this article, I suggest that Keynes’s views on the alternation of the “bull” and
“bear” sentiment and asset price speculation over the business cycle can provide a
satisfactory explanation for two of Minsky’s central propositions in relation to business
cycle turning points that have often been found less than fully persuasive in the way they
have been expounded: (1) that financial fragility increases gradually over the expansion,
and, (2) that the interest rate sooner or later increases setting off a downward spiral
bringing the expansion to an end.1 The gist of the said argument from the Treatise says
that the rise of the bear position during late expansion impairs the ability of the banking
system to accommodate rising levels of economic activity and, thus, is the real culprit
behind the eventual rise in the interest rate during a business cycle expansion. This is
typically caused not because fear of inflation, or some other extraneous consideration,
forces the central bank to curtail credit to the system but because financial sentiment
shifts for the worse and asset prices all of a sudden begin to look excessive.
The following discussion is organized in five sections. First section gives a brief
overview of the conceptual structure of the argument in the Treatise, and the second
discusses the role asset price speculation plays over the business cycle in it. The third
1 See, among others, Lavoie (1986, 1992, p. 199)
4
section draws out some of the theoretical implications of the argument in the Treatise
with respect to the conditions under which speculation can be both stabilizing and
destabilizing. The fourth section situates Minsky’s contribution in the historical context
of the marginalization of the two-price theory in the Treatise as it has become
increasingly overshadowed by the theoretical developments following the General
Theory. The last section includes a few concluding comments.
STRUCTURE OF THE ARGUMENT IN THE TREATISE
Keynes’s main contention in his A Tract on Monetary Reform was that price fluctuations
over a business cycle were characterized by systematic changes in the demand for real
money balances rather than by exogenous shifts in the money supply. That was why any
attempt on the part of monetary authorities to keep the money supply steady would fail to
achieve price stability (Keynes 1973 vol. IV, p. 69). Instead, the more effective policy in
Keynes’s view had to aim at changing the money supply to compensate for the systemic
shifts taking place in the demand for real money balances over the credit cycle. If
changes in desired money-balances had a systemic character, this also meant that the
excess of investment over saving could correspond to a fall in demand for money in
relation to supply as well. In other words, the dual of the difference between investment
and savings did not just have to be an increased supply of money as Wicksell laid out, but
could also come about by a fall in the demand for money balances through dishoarding.
Likewise, periods of excess savings would be characterized either by increased monetary
hoarding or decreasing money supply, or some combination of both. The disaggregation
of money demand by the type of agent and transaction in the Treatise was thus motivated
in part by Keynes’s desire to analyze changes in hoarding over the credit cycle.
Keynes’s second insight was that a credit cycle expansion, or the transition from
one position of equilibrium to a higher one in the sense of the quantity theory of money,
the prices of capital goods varied systematically in relation to those of consumer goods.
Later revived by Minsky, this view held that the prices of capital goods are determined in
financial markets by profit expectations that are reflected—though not always accurately
as we shall see—in securities prices, while consumer goods prices are determined by the
relative magnitude of consumer demand in relation to the available supply. Thus, the very
5
modus operandi of monetary expansion involved changes in the relative values of capital
and consumer goods, and that is why the classical dichotomy, Keynes held, was not
viable.2
Finally, in the Treatise, Keynes then linked expected changes in securities prices
over the credit cycle to changes in net hoarding—his first innovation—through the
variations in the stock demand for financial assets, by what he called the “state of
bearishness.” For instance, a period of early expansion is typically characterized in his
view by excess investment, expected increases in asset prices and falling state of
bearishness, and thus net dishoarding. This makes it all the easier for banks to
accommodate a rising level of activity without having to raise the rate of interest. In this
approach, speculation about asset price expectations is an integral part of the investment
savings nexus, where changes in the state of bearishness has a direct quantity effect on
the relative size of inactive balances without necessarily causing a change in the rate of
interest or asset prices in general.
ASSET PRICE SPECULATION IN THE TREATISE
In the Treatise, monetary circulation is divided into industrial and financial parts,
associated, respectively, with the circulation of goods and services and that of titles to
financial wealth. The amount of money in industrial circulation is closely related to the
level of output and expenditures. Financial circulation, by contrast, primarily reflects the
size of the bear position, referring to those who choose to keep their resources in liquid
form having sold securities short. Keynes took the volume of cash deposits as a rough
measure of the size of industrial circulation and savings deposits as that of the financial
circulation.3
The desire to remain more, or less, liquid is of course not independent of the actual
changes in security prices. The fall (rise) in security prices in relation to the short-term
2 After the General Theory, this idea all but disappeared as macroeconomics came to be
associated with one-commodity models even among Keynesians (Leijonhufvud 1968, p.
23).
3 Keynes maintained that saving deposits would typically be held in the form of “deposit
accounts” (which corresponds to time deposits in the U.S.) and while cash deposits would
take the form of “current accounts” (checking or demand deposits in the U.S.).
6
rate of interest can partially offset the bearish (bullish) sentiment, thus the actual increase
(decrease) in the volume of savings deposits also depends on the extent of the fall in
securities prices. This implies that, “[t]here will be a level of security prices which on the
average opinion just balances the bullishness [or bearishness], so that the volume of
savings deposits is unchanged. (Keynes 1973 vol.V, p. 224). If security prices fall (rise)
beyond this point, then the savings deposits might actually decrease (increase).
In the Treatise, Keynes defines four types of speculative markets in connection with
different configurations of the bear position (Keynes 1973 vol. V, p. 226). These
typically correspond to different phases of the business cycle. The first involves a
decreasing bear position, i.e., a decreasing volume of saving deposits, at a time of rising
security prices. Keynes calls this a “bull market with a consensus of opinion” and
distinguishes it from a “bull market with a difference of opinion” where the bear position
is increasing at a time when security prices are also rising. In the former case, which
typically holds during early expansion, the preponderance of market opinion holds that
security prices have not risen sufficiently, while in the latter case, corresponding
normally to late expansion, an ever rising segment of the market thinks that security
prices have risen more than sufficiently. The third case, which corresponds to early
recession, is a “bear market with a consensus,” and again Keynes distinguishes this from
a “bear market with a division of opinion.” The former involves a rising bear position,
i.e., increasing volume of saving deposits, at a time of falling security prices and the latter
a decreasing bear position when security prices are still falling. In the former, the
predominant market opinion is that security prices have not fallen sufficiently and that
they have fallen more than sufficiently in the latter.
From the point of view of orthodox theory of finance, it does not make any sense to
say that security prices have increased or decreased more, or less, than sufficiently if no
new information has emerged at a given point in time. For, if securities are thought to be
undervalued, then arbitrageurs would continue to buy them until their prices are bid up to
a level that is no longer considered low. Likewise, if securities are thought to be
overvalued, again, arbitrage would bring their value down to a level consistent with what
is considered to be their “true” value. Thus, at a given point in time, with an unchanged
7
information set, the prevailing asset prices must be the best estimates of fundamental
values.4
However, Keynes’s approach in the Treatise is consistent with the modern “noise
trader” (or the so-called behavioral) approach to finance, which holds that riskless
arbitrage is not effective in relation to the prices of shares or bonds as a whole and
severely limited even when it comes to the relative prices of individual assets (Shleifer &
Summers 1990, Shleifer & Vishny 1997). According to this view, even when it is
assumed that arbitrageurs know what fundamental values are, they face no riskless
arbitrage opportunities when actual prices deviate from their true values. For with a finite
time horizon, an arbitrageur faces two kinds of risk: when s/he, say, sells overvalued
assets short it is possible that by the time s/he is supposed to liquidate his/her position (1)
economy can grow so rapidly that the true values increase, or, more importantly, (2) asset
prices might be even more overpriced. In both cases, the arbitrageur would be
experiencing losses. Thus, the fear of loss would limit the initial positions the
arbitrageurs take and thus prevent them from driving prices down in any significant way.
Moreover, if we drop the assumption that arbitrageurs know what the true values are, the
risk of loss they face is higher, and the compensatory shift in demand for the undervalued
securities smaller.
In a vein very similar to the modern behavioral approach, in the Treatise, Keynes
remarks that when prices deviate from their “true” values no automatic mechanism exists
in the short run to check their deviation. Opinion, or what we would today call, noise
(Black 1986) moves prices. “If everyone agrees that securities are worth more, and if
everyone is a ‘bull’ in the sense of preferring securities at a rising price to increasing his
savings deposits, there is no limit to the rise in price of securities and no effective check
4 The more elaborate justification of this position is based on “the efficient market
hypothesis,” which has gained currency among economists after Samuelson’s (1965)
“proof” that in a market that is efficient in appropriating all available information stock
prices should exhibit a random walk and Fama’s (1965) demonstration that they almost
actually do. But, neither proposition is considered valid any longer in the finance
literature. Empirically, it is shown that stock prices do not exhibit random walk, and
theoretically it is shown that unforeseeable prices are neither necessary nor sufficient for
rationally determined stock prices. See, among others, Lo & MacKinlay (1999),
Bossaerts (2002) and Shleifer (2000).
8
arises from a shortage of money” (Keynes 1973 vol. V, p. 229). However, as prices
continue to rise, a “bear” position begins to develop, and that is what can eventually
check the rise in prices. “…[I]n proportion as the prevailing opinion comes to seem
unreasonable to more cautious people, the ‘other view’ will tend to develop, with the
result of an increase in the ‘bear’ position…” (Keynes 1973 vol. V, p. 228-9).
In Keynes’s discussion in the Treatise, the rise of the bear position at a time when
security prices are rising plays an important role in explaining the turning point of a
business cycle expansion. In his view, “it is astonishing … how large a change in the
earnings bill can be looked after by the banking system without an apparent breach in its
principles and traditions” (Keynes 1973 vol. V, p. 272). Yet, the banking system’s ability
to accommodate a rising level of production is typically impaired at some point during a
business cycle expansion. That happens typically not because the banking sector is held
back by the central bank or faces some intrinsic difficulty, but because the financial
sentiment falters. The trigger can have a myriad of immediate causes but the underlying
reason is almost invariably the fact that the actual performance of profits, though they
might still be rising, falls short of the high expectations that underlie asset prices. As the
view that the market might be overvalued begins to take hold, the bear position develops,
and “…the tendency of the financial circulation to increase, on the top of the increase in
the industrial circulation …break[s] the back of the banking system and cause it at long
last to impose a rate of interest, which is not only fully equal to the natural rate but, very
likely in the changed circumstances, well above it” (Keynes 1973 vol. V, p. 272).
“BEAUTY CONTEST” AND ASSET PRICE BUBBLES
Ever since Friedman (1953) argued that destabilizing speculation would be unprofitable,
and, thus, unsustainable in the long run, the mainstream view among economists has
assumed that speculation as a rule could not be destabilizing. Asset price bubbles were
considered highly unlikely if not impossible in a “normally” functioning market.
The intuition behind Friedman’s argument rested on a simple view of arbitrage, in
which the market comprises smart traders who know the true values and misinformed
noise traders. If securities are undervalued, as the argument goes, then the smart traders
would continue to buy them until their prices are bid up to their true value. Likewise, if
9
securities are overvalued, smart traders would sell them, bringing their price down to
their true value. Indeed, under these conditions, speculation is always stabilizing and
profitable. Misinformed noise traders create riskless arbitrage opportunities that smart
traders profit from, while making losses themselves. In other words, this implies that the
rate of current price change is a function of the difference between the current price and
the expected future price, which is by assumption equal to true value. In simple terms:
)( PPj
dt
dP e= , (1)
where, e
P
, the future expected price, is assumed to be constant ( PPe
=
) and equal to
the true value, and j is the adjustment coefficient indicating the speed with which traders
respond to changes in current price. When
e
P
P
> then 0<
dt
dP
and e
P
P
< then 0>
dt
dP .
The time path of price is given by,
ejt PePtP +=
)0()(,
which clearly cannot be unstable, since the stability condition 0>j is always satisfied
because the speed of adjustment is positive by definition.
Undoubtedly, the assumption that smart traders or speculators know with
certainty what the true value is is exceedingly unrealistic. But, even under this strong
assumption, it does not necessarily follow that the deviation of the current price of an
asset from its true value creates a riskless arbitrage opportunity. As mentioned above, the
speculator who sells overvalued assets short can find that by the time s/he is supposed to
close his/her position, the true value has increased, or, that the assets in question have
10
become even more overpriced.5 In both situations, the speculators who have sold
securities short would be making losses. Even if the true value is known, it does not
follow that it would be equal to the expected future price. Thus, because the fear of
making losses would cause smart traders to limit the initial positions they take in an over
or undervalued asset, current price might not smoothly adjust to its true value. Needless
to say, if we drop the assumption that speculators know what the true value is, the risk of
loss they perceive is likely to be higher, and the compensatory shift in demand for
undervalued assets smaller. That is why the modern behavioral approach to finance holds
that the effect of arbitrage can be severely limited.
This also takes us very close to a world described in Keynes’s (1936, Ch. 12)
famous beauty contest analogy, where speculators base their expectations of future asset
prices not only on what they think the true values is, but, more importantly, on what they
think the average opinion about the average opinion is. In other words, noise (Black
1986) is at least as important as information about true values in causing asset price
changes, rendering the resale price uncertain. Uncertainty about the future resale price
means that traders lack a terminal value from which to backwardize, which in turn
implies that they must not only form higher order expectations (i.e., on what others think
others think) but also decide how much weight to assign them relative to what they
themselves think the true value is (Hirota & Sunder 2003). Since no direct information
exists on others’ higher order expectations, traders have to infer that from market trends,
i.e., the magnitude and direction of changes in current price.
For instance, if a trader observes that the price of an asset (or an asset group)
which s/he thinks is already overvalued is still rising in price, s/he is led to surmise that
either her/his opinion about the true value is wrong or that the price increase indicates a
bubble, i.e., a self-sustained rise in price on account of noise trading driven by the
average opinion thinking that the average opinion thinks the price will keep on rising. In
either case, the current price changes are likely to gain in importance in how the trader
forms his/her expectation about the future price. The current change in price becomes
5 Shleifer & Summers (1990) call these, respectively, the fundamental value and noise
trader risk,
11
either a proxy for the higher order expectations or a corrective on opinions about the true
value, or, some combination of both.
If so, the crucial variable that determines whether speculation is stabilizing or not
very much depends on the relative weight traders assign to their higher order expectations
(i.e., what they think others think others think) relative to their own assessment of what
the true value is. To the extent that they do, they become more responsive to the current
price change in forming their expectations about the future price. In Kaldor’s (1939)
formulation, whether speculation is stabilizing or not in this setting depends on the
elasticity of future price expectations with respect to present price changes.6
If indeed the expected future price can be thought to comprise two parts, then we
can write:
dt
dP
PPe
σ
+= , (2)
where
P
is what the true value is believed to be (and is assumed constant for simplicity),
and
σ
is the coefficient of elasticity for expectation of elasticity of the future price with
respect to the current change in price.
Plugging (2) in (1) gives:
][ P
dt
dP
Pj
dt
dP +=
σ
,
and rearranging we get;
P
j
j
P
j
j
dt
dP
σσ
=
+11
which, in turn yields the following time path of price;
PePPtP t
j
j
+=
σ
1
])0([)(
6 See also Hicks (1946, pp. 205-6).
12
The stability condition, j
1
<
σ
, shows that stability depends on both the elasticity
of expectations and the reaction speed. If the reaction speed is assumed instantaneous
()1=j, a less than unitary elasticity of expectations ( )1
<
σ
ensures stability as Kaldor
argued. In other words, destabilizing speculation—and an asset price bubble—requires
that traders revise their expected future price proportionally more than the change in
current price. However, the lower the reaction speed (j < 1), the greater is the extent to
which the threshold value of
σ
exceeds unity.
It is highly plausible that both the reaction speed (j) and the elasticity of
expectations (
σ
) might respond to changes in market opinion as to the degree to which
asset prices are overvalued. As remarked above, if a trader observes that the actual price
is well above what s/he thinks the true value is and still rising, s/he either begins to lose
confidence in his/her own opinion on what is reasonable or think that asset price
increases have acquired the character of a bubble. In either case, an increasing number of
traders who might think alike will either leave the market or become much more
responsive to current price movements in forming expectations about the future price—
either naively as noise traders or smartly as speculators are presumed to do. In this
setting, unlike what Friedman foresaw, successful (read rational) speculators are those
who engage in “trend” speculation, where they act like noise traders themselves in the
short run, trying to feed the bubble rather than help deflate it (De Long et al. 1990).7
Because the successful speculative strategy entails jumping on the bandwagon of noise
traders and knowing when to get off while the rest rides on, this might also imply a rising
reaction speed. Thus, any sustained trend of a current price increase from what the market
opinion generally holds to be the true value, whatever the cause, is likely to raise both the
elasticity of expectations and the reaction speed. While this does not explain how initially
prices become misaligned, it suggests speculation can become destabilizing once price
deviations exceed in size and duration a certain threshold.
7 In the modern finance literature on asset price bubbles the emphasis, until recently, was
on rational traders’ risk aversion which was thought to prevent them from eliminating
noise-driven price movements. However, the focus has been shifting to “trend”
speculation as the winning strategy for speculators, a fact well known to market
participants all along (Soros 1987; Temin and Voth 2004).
13
In a similar manner, Keynes’s discussion on how asset prices behave over the
business cycle, in his Treatise, seems to presuppose that speculation can be both
stabilizing and destabilizing, depending on the phase of the cycle. As discussed in the
previous section, Keynes argues that agents form expectations about the trend value of
asset prices and the weighted average of these opinions tend to shift over the course of a
business cycle expansion, which are then reflected in the changing size of the bear
position in the economy. He stylistically divides the expansion phase of a business cycle
into two parts, where the preponderance of market opinion holds that asset prices are
alternately undervalued and overvalued during the early and late periods of the cycle. The
latter period owes its existence, and is prolonged in duration, to the extent that the
banking system transfers the bear funds (bank deposits of those who have sold securities
short) to those who still have a bullish sentiment that asset prices will continue to rise. In
other words, while asset prices are rising in both periods, in the former their increase is
driven by fundamentals and in the latter by speculation. By implication, while
speculation is stabilizing in the former period it becomes destabilizing during late
expansion, giving rise to a bubble.
Thus, Keynes’s argument in the Treatise, implies that the elasticity of
expectations can vary endogenously over the business cycle. When traders observe that
the actual price is well above what they think the true value is and still rising, they not
only infer that higher order expectations are at work but also in increasing numbers
assign greater weight to them (what they think others think others think) over their own
opinion. They begin to either lose confidence in their own judgment of what is reasonable
or think that asset price increases have acquired the character of a bubble. In either case,
they become much more responsive to changes in current price in forming expectations
about the future price. That, in other words, implies a regime shift from inelastic to elastic
expectations as traders begin to discount their own opinions in forming expectations
about the future price.
Keynes’s discussion of the trade cycle in the Treatise presupposes a regime shift
of this sort. During the upswing, actual profits cannot increase at an increasing rate, while
asset prices often will. Thus, sooner or later, optimistic expectations, and thus the asset
prices that they underlie, outstrip the actual performance of profits. The latter, though still
14
rising, eventually falls short of the former, but the bullish sentiment tends to persist.
Thus, what eventually “breaks the back of the banking system,” causing the rate of
interest to rise, is the development of the “other view” which holds that asset prices have
become excessive.
DEBATE ON THE TWO-PRICE THEORY
Robertson (1931) objected to Keynes’s employment of two separate principles to
determine, respectively, the investment and consumer goods prices in his Treatise. He
argued that Keynes could insulate the price level of new investment goods from changes
in the flow of savings only because he was assuming that over saving was associated with
hoarding and under-saving with dishoarding. This argument was only partially true in
part because it mis-specified the real issue of contention between them. The very logic of
the quantity equation as an accounting identity, as Wicksell laid bare, requires that a
reduction in monetary income (over-saving) involves a decreased monetary circulation.
This can come about either through a fall in the total quantity of money or increased
hoarding, or some combination of the two. Thus, if the quantity of total money is not
decreasing, over saving has to be associated with an increase in net hoarding, and thus a
fall in the overall velocity for the broad money supply. Otherwise, over saving and thus a
fall in monetary income could not have occurred.8 So, there was something to
Robertson’s objection. But, the real contentious issue in his criticism was whether or not
this increase in inactive balances (hoarding) would also translate into excess demand for
financial assets. If it did, as Robertson seems to have argued, then, clearly the price of
securities (and thus that of new investment goods) could not be determined independently
of savings as Keynes had. Thus, Keynes’s “two price” theory was (or should have been)
the central issue in this debate.
8 In his haste to make the point that excess savings and increased hoarding were not one
and the same, Keynes appears to have caused confusion by insisting that over saving had
no particular relation to increased inactive balances unless the banking sector chose to
supply a higher amount of saving deposits, without however indicating that what he took
as his default case was an endogenous fall in the supply of money. Though, technically,
excess savings can be associated with neither a fall in the money supply nor increased net
hoarding in a given period if “non-GDP” transactions increase inordinately relative to
those on the currently produced output, but this cannot be generally the case.
15
In his rebuttal of Robertson, Keynes argued that a situation of over-savings
involves windfall losses for a class of entrepreneurs who would be forced to liquidate a
part of their asset positions in order to be able to meet their current financial obligations
that can no longer be covered by sale proceeds (Keynes 1973 vol. XIII, pp. 219-36).
Thus, the increased demand for financial assets, if indeed inactive balances caused that,
would be balanced by the increased supply coming from those entrepreneurs running
down their reserves of financial assets to compensate for their windfall losses. In other
words, the increase of wealth savers experience at the end of the period would be
matched by the decrease of wealth experienced by entrepreneurs facing windfall losses.
The prices of financial assets would then remain basically unchanged, provided that the
state of bearishness of savers is not significantly different than that of entrepreneurs.
While this argument is plausible, it might have detracted attention from the real issue.
For Keynes’s stronger argument is of course the broader justification for his “two-
price” theory, which he also restated in his rebuttal (Keynes 1973 vol. XIII, pp. 220). In
the language of modern finance theory, this can perhaps be put more succinctly: The
price of an asset is determined solely by its expected future price, independently of its
current flows of supply and demand, if these flows are dwarfed by speculative stocks that
are very large. Thus, the impact of “outside” supply and demand on the current price can
be only indirect, through its influence, if any, on the expected future price of the asset in
question.9 In a nutshell, this was the gist of Keynes’s argument in justification of his
“two-price” theory. Already in the Treatise, Keynes had made a distinction between the
decision to save in the sense of non-consumption, and the decision on how to dispose of
what is not consumed, and remarked that the main consideration in making the latter
decision is the current and expected future asset prices, which also influenced how all
financial wealth was held. Because the marginal increase in financial wealth, equal to
current savings used to purchase securities, was “trifling” in magnitude compared to the
total stock of wealth, expectations about the future asset prices were much more
important than the marginal increase in the demand for financial assets. The way he put
9 Ironically, the “efficient market hypothesis,” which the detractors of Keynes were quick
to embrace, also presupposes that the current asset prices are solely determined by their
expected future prices independently of outside supply and demand.
16
it, the “excess bearish” factor, an inverse index of the stock demand for securities,
reflected the public’s demand for inactive balances (saving deposits) given their
expectations (and degree of their confidence in them) about future asset prices, and the
current asset prices changed accordingly to the extent the banking sector chose not to
accommodate the changes in public’s demand for saving deposits (inactive balances). In
other words, with a given banking sector policy, future asset price expectations governed
the current prices of securities (and thus those of investment goods), reflecting in part
profit expectations in the real economy along with the other considerations summarized
under Keynes’s famous “beauty contest” analogy discussed above.
The “finance” debate that broke out after the publication of the General Theory
was essentially a continuation of the disagreement Robertson had with Keynes in 1931. It
again involved two separate issues—one, about consistency in macro accounting and, the
other, on economic behavior—that were entangled together, and the former continued to
detract attention from the more important disagreement with respect to the latter
involving Keynes’s “two-price” theory. As Keynes redefined investment and savings in
the General Theory, insisting that they were separate but always equal, agreement first
had to be reached on expressing “investment-saving” disequilibrium in terms of a
discrepancy between intended and actual magnitudes, with all the attending confusion
about what intended savings meant. Then, the focus of the debate again became the
monetary corollary of the discrepancy between investment and savings.
In 1931, the issue was the connection between excess savings and increased
hoarding (i.e., in the absence of an endogenous fall in the money supply); after the
General Theory, it became a debate about what the corollary of an increase in “intended”
investment was. A rise in the money supply was ruled out by assumption and
“dishoarding” had an immediate price effect by definition. Thus, this time around, the
whole debate could only be framed from the “money demand” side and focus on the
pressure an increase in planned expenditures would exert on the interest rate. In his
exchanges with his critics, including Robertson among others, Keynes (1937a, 1937b,
1937c, 1938) had to concede that a rise in planned investment would also raise the
demand for money prior to its execution, and, thus, all other things being equal, the
interest rate. He emphasized banks’ overdraft facilities to argue that this effect on the
17
interest rate would not amount to much in practice. Decades later, in another round of
“finance” debate an article by Asimakopulos (1983) set off, it was in a similar vein
accepted that additional bank finance would be required until the multiplier process
worked itself out, generating enough savings to equal the higher level of investment
(Chick 1983, 1997).
The effect of these rounds of “finance” debates was to link the increased
“planned” expenditures to a prospective increase in the money supply or the interest rate,
without however bringing into forefront the more important issue about economic
behavior. If anything, this preoccupation with the accounting problem alone had the
effect of placing undue emphasis on the so-called finance demand as a separate
motivation to hold money, which appears to have weakened the essential aspect of
Keynes’s “two-price” theory. In Davidson’s (1978) well-known incorporation of the idea
into the IS-LM model, an increase in planned investment not only shifts up the IS
schedule but the LM schedule as well, causing the interest rate to go up faster and sooner
whenever the level of activity rose. Of course, the verbal explanation of why the interest
rate rises was very different than Robertson’s “loanable funds” account, but the end result
was the same in obliterating whatever remained intact from what Hicks’ called Keynes’s
“special theory.”10
CONCLUSION
As it evolved after the General Theory, Keynesian theory had so strayed away from the
two-price theory that Minsky (1975) had to reestablish that Keynes was essentially about
“an investment theory of fluctuations in real demand and a financial theory of
10 While Hicks (1937) arguably stood Keynes’s General Theory on its head in his famous
review article, he also appears to have identified accurately what was unique about his
theory. This was in his opinion the notion that an increase in expenditures and income did
not necessarily put an upward pressure on the interest rate. Hicks called this Keynes’s
“special theory,” and distinguished it from the GT which in his view was closer to
orthodoxy since Keynes’s argument there implied that—as his IS/LM formulation he
believed made evident—an increase in expenditure led to a rise in the interest rate, all
other things being equal (p. 152). The “special theory” Hicks was referring to is but the
essential feature of the “two-price” theory, whereby asset prices are determined
independently of investment and saving flows.
18
fluctuations in real investment” (p. 57). Restating the two-price theory, Minsky
reemphasized that changing views about the future exert their influence on the present
through their impact on the current asset prices, reflecting the expected profitability of
producing investment goods. But, at the same time, Minsky paid little attention to asset
price speculation and its macroeconomic effects, and left untouched that part of Keynes’s
analysis in the Treatise on how self-sustained biases in asset prices affect financial
sentiment in financial markets over the business cycle.
The point of this paper has been to argue that what Minsky overlooked in the
Treatise is of importance for his argument, in that Keynes’s account of how financial
sentiment shifts over the cycle in this work can help provide a satisfactory explanation of
the turning point of a Minskian business cycle expansion. Just as in Minsky’s account,
the expansion in the Treatise begins with optimistic expectations enabling firms to
capitalize their expected earnings in financial markets and thereby finance their
investment expenditures. During the upswing, the actual increase in profits validates the
higher asset prices, spurring them to increase further. But, unlike asset prices, actual
profits cannot increase at an increasing rate in the course of an expansion. Thus, the rise
in profits increasingly lags behind the upward movement in asset prices. As economic
performance begins to fall short of the level of expectations that are capitalized in asset
values, the view that asset prices are excessive begins to take hold in financial markets
and the bear position rises. This is the point at which higher asset prices tend to become a
drag on the economy rather than a stimulant, and the pressure on the banking system to
raise the interest rate begins to build. Thus, what ultimately impairs the ability of the
banking system to accommodate a rising level of economic activity is the fact that at
some point during an expansion the financial sentiment falters, and that is why sooner or
later the interest rate rises as Minsky insisted that it does.
19
REFERENCES
Asimakopulos, A. (1983). “Kalecki and Keynes on Finance, Investment and Savings,”
Cambridge Journal of Economics, 7, pp. 221-33.
Black, F. (1986). “Noise,” Journal of Finance, July, 41, pp. 529-43
Bossaerts, P. (2002). The Paradox of Asset Pricing. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Chick, V. 1983. Macroeconomics After Keynes. Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
_____. 1997. “The Multiplier and Finance.” In G.C. Harcourt and P.A. Riach (eds.)
A “Second Edition” of The General Theory Vol. 1. London: Routledge.
Davidson, P. (1978). Money and the Real World, Macmillan.
De Long, J.B., Schleifer, A., Summers, L., & R. Waldmann (1990). “Noise Trader Risk
in Financial Markets,” Journal of Political Economy, 98(4), August, 703-38.
Erturk, K. (2006). “Asset Price Bubbles, Liquidity Preference and the Business Cycle,”
forthcoming in Metroeconomica.
Fama, E. (1965): “The Behavior of Stock Market Prices,” Journal of Political Economy,
96, 246-73.
Friedman, M. (1953). “The Case for Flexible Exchange Rates,” Essays in Positive
Economics, Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Hicks, J.R. (1937). “Mr. Keynes and the ‘Classics’: A Suggested Interpretation,”
Econometrica, 5, pp. 147-59.
Hicks, J.R. (1946). Value and Capital: An Inquiry into Some Fundamental Principles of
Economic Theory. 2nd Edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hirota, S. and S. Sunder (2003). “Price Bubbles sans Dividend Anchors: Evidence From
Laboratory Stock Markets,” Working Paper. Posted at:
http://www.som.yale.edu/faculty/Sunder/research.html
Kaldor, N. (1939). “Speculation and Economic Stability.” Review of Economic Studies,
6(3), pp. 1-27.
Keynes, J.M. (1937a). “General Theory of Employment,” Quarterly Journal of
Economics, 51, pp. 209-23.
20
Keynes, J.M. (1937b). “Alternative Theories of the Rate of Interest,” Economic
Journal, 47, pp. 241-52.
Keynes, J.M. (1937c). “‘Ex-Ante’ Theory of the Rate of Interest,” Economic Journal,
48, pp. 663-9.
Keynes, J.M. (1938). “Mr. Keynes on ‘Finance’,” Economic Journal, 48, pp. 318-22.
Keynes, J.M. (1964) [1936]. The General Theory of Employment, Interest, and Money,
Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, New York.
Keynes, J.M (1973) [1923]. A Tract on Monetary Reform in Moggridge, D.E. (ed.):
Collected Writings of J.M. Keynes, (CW), vol. IV, Macmillan for The Royal
Economic Society, London.
Keynes, J.M. (1973) [1930]. A Treatise on Money, vol. I, in Moggridge, D.E. (ed.):
Collected Writings of J.M. Keynes, (CW), vol. V, Macmillan for The Royal
Economic Society, London.
Keynes, J.M (1973). Collected Works of J.M. Keynes, vol. XIII, edited by D.E.
Moggridge, Macmillan for The Royal Economic Society, London.
Kregel, J. (1992). “Minsky's "Two Price" Theory of Financial Instability and Monetary
Policy: Discounting versus Open Market Intervention,” Fazzari, Steven and D.B.
Papadimitriou, (eds). Financial Conditions and Macroeconomic Performance:
Essays in Honor of Hyman P. Minsky. 85-103, Armonk, N.Y. and London:
Sharpe.
Lavoie, M. (1986). “Minsky’s Law or the Theorem of Systemic Financial Fragility,”
Studi Economici, 29(3), pp. 3-28.
Lavoie, M. (1992). Foundations of Post Keynesian Economic Analysis. Aldershot:
Edward Elgar.
Leijonhufvud, A. (1968). Keynesian Economics and the Economics of Keynes. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Lo, A. and A.C. MacKinlay (1999). A Non-Random Walk Down Wall Street. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Minsky, H. (1975). John Maynard Keynes, Columbia University Press.
Robertson, D.H. (1931). “Mr. Keynes’s Theory of Money,” Economic Journal,
41(163), pp. 395-411.
21
Samuelson, P. (1965): “Proof that Properly Anticipated Prices Fluctuate Randomly,”
Industrial Management Review, 6, pp. 41-50.
Shleifer, A. (2000). Inefficient Markets. An Introduction to Behavioral Finance.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Shleifer, A. and L. Summers (1990). The Noise Trader Approach to Finance. Journal of
Economic Perspectives, vol. 4, no. 2, pp. 19-33.
Shleifer, A. and R. Vishny (1997). “The Limits of Arbitrage.” Journal of Finance, vol.
52, no. 1, pp. 35 - 55.
Soros, G. (1987). The Alchemy of Finance: Reading the Mind of the Market. New York:
Simon & Schuster.
Temin, P. & H. Voth (2004). “Riding the South Sea Bubble,” CEPR Discussion Paper
4221.
ResearchGate has not been able to resolve any citations for this publication.
Article
In the first part of the article the author shows that the double objective of the return to convertibility and the liberalisation of imports cannot be reached unless exchange rates are allowed to move. In the second and third parts he treats the longer run aspect of the problem, giving exhaustive analysis of possible methods of dealing with a deficit in the balance of payments. This is done first by discussing the disadvantages of the various alternative ways that may be adopted under the system of fixed exchange rates, and second by showing that a policy of fluctuating rates is superior to these methods. In the fourth part the suggestion for combining the policy of flexible rates with establishment of stabilisation funds is discussed. In concluding the author points to the possibility of adopting in the early stages a system of “limited flexibility” under which exchange rates would be allowed to fluctuate between limits that were well defined but considerably wider than those which prevail at present. JEL: E42, F31, F32
Article
For over half a century, financial experts have regarded the movements of markets as a random walk--unpredictable meanderings akin to a drunkard's unsteady gait--and this hypothesis has become a cornerstone of modern financial economics and many investment strategies. Here Andrew W. Lo and A. Craig MacKinlay put the Random Walk Hypothesis to the test. In this volume, which elegantly integrates their most important articles, Lo and MacKinlay find that markets are not completely random after all, and that predictable components do exist in recent stock and bond returns. Their book provides a state-of-the-art account of the techniques for detecting predictabilities and evaluating their statistical and economic significance, and offers a tantalizing glimpse into the financial technologies of the future. The articles track the exciting course of Lo and MacKinlay's research on the predictability of stock prices from their early work on rejecting random walks in short-horizon returns to their analysis of long-term memory in stock market prices. A particular highlight is their now-famous inquiry into the pitfalls of "data-snooping biases" that have arisen from the widespread use of the same historical databases for discovering anomalies and developing seemingly profitable investment strategies. This book invites scholars to reconsider the Random Walk Hypothesis, and, by carefully documenting the presence of predictable components in the stock market, also directs investment professionals toward superior long-term investment returns through disciplined active investment management.
Article
The purpose of the following paper is to examine, in the light of recent doctrines, the effects of speculation on economic stability. Speculation, for the purposes of this paper, may be defined as the purchase (or sale) of goods with a view to re-sale (re-purchase) at a later date, where the motive behind such action is the expectation of a change in the relevant prices relatively to the ruling price and not a gain accruing through their use, or any kind of transformation effected in them or their transfer between different markets. Thus, while merchants and other dealers do make purchases and sales which might be termed ‘speculative’, their ordinary transactions do not fall within this category. What distinguishes speculative purchases and sales from other kinds of purchases and sales is the expectation of an impending change in the ruling market price as the sole motive of action. Hence ‘speculative stocks’ of anything may be defined as the difference between the amount actually held and the amount that would be held if, other things being the same, the price of that thing were expected to remain unchanged; and they can be either positive or negative.1