ArticlePDF Available

Abstract

This paper argues that three widely accepted motivating factors subsumed under the broad heading of iconicity, namely iconicity of quantity, iconicity of complexity and iconicity of cohesion in fact have no role in explaining grammatical asymmetries and should be discarded. The iconicity accounts of the relevant phenomena have been proposed by authorities like Jakobson, Haiman and Giv贸n, but I argue that these linguists did not sufficiently consider alternative usage-based explanations in terms of frequency of use. A closer look shows that the well-known Zipfian effects of frequency of use (leading to shortness and fusion) can be made responsible for all of the alleged iconicity effects, and initial corpus data for a range of phenomena confirm the correctness of the approach.
1
13. April 2005, F.-S.-Universität Jena
Iconicity versus frequency
in explaining grammatical asymmetries
MARTIN HASPELMATH
Max-Planck-Institut für evolutionäre Anthropologie
1. Introduction
"the intuition behind iconicity is that the structure of language reflects in
some way the structure of experience" Croft's (2003:102)
(1) Iconicity of quantity
Greater quantities in meaning are expressed by greater quantities of form.
Example: In Latin adjective inflection, the comparative and superlative
denote increasingly higher degrees and are coded by increasingly longer
suffixes (long(-us) 'long', long-ior 'longer', long-issim(-us) 'longest').
(2) Iconicity of complexity
More complex meanings are expressed by more complex forms.
Example: Causatives are more complex semantically than the
corresponding non-causatives, so they are coded by more complex forms,
e.g. Turkish ş(-mek) 'fall', causative ş-ür(-mek) 'make fall, drop'.
(3) Iconicity of cohesion
Meanings that belong together more closely are expressed by
more cohesive forms.
Example: In possessive noun phrases with body-part terms, the possessum
and the possessor are conceptually inseparable. This is mirrored in
greater cohesion of coding in many languages, e.g. Maltese id 'hand', id-i
'my hand', siġġu 'chair', is-siġġu tiegħ-i [the-chair of-me] 'my chair'
(*siġġ(u)-i).
• these three types of iconicity play no role in explaining grammatical
asymmetries of the type long(-us)/long-ior, ş(-mek)/ş-ür(-mek), id-i/is-siġġu
tiegħ-i.
• such formal asymmetries can be explained by frequency asymmetries:
In all these cases, the shorter and more cohesive expression types occur
significantly more frequently than the longer and less cohesive expression
types, and this suffices to explain their formal properties.
• Iconicity is not only not necessary, but also makes wrong predictions.
• I make no claims about other types of iconicity, such as
iconicity of paradigmatic isomorphism (one form, one meaning, i.e.
synonymy and homonymy are avoided; Haiman 1980, Croft 1990a)
iconicity of syntagmatic isomorphism (each form has a meaning, each
meaning has a form, i.e. empty and zero morphs are avoided; Croft 1990a)
iconicity of sequence (sequence of forms matches sequence of
experiences; e.g. Greenberg 1963:103)
iconicity of contiguity (forms that belong together semantically occur
next to each other)
2
iconicity of repetition (repeated forms signal repetition in experience, as
when reduplication expresses plurality or distribution).
• explanation vs. observation:
"The traditional view of language is that most relationships between linguistic units and
the corresponding meanings are arbitrary... But the cognitive claim is that the degree of
iconicity in language is much higher than has traditionally been thought to be the case."
(Lee 2001:...)
• What I am denying is that iconicity is playing a motivating role and
should be invoked in explaining why the patterns are the way they are.
• some authors (e.g. Givón 1985, 1991) seem to use the term "iconicity" as a
kind of antonym of "arbitrariness", so that almost anything about language
structure that is not arbitrary fals under iconicity.
2. Iconicity of quantity
2.1. Advocates and examples
(4) Greater quantities in meaning are expressed by greater quantities of form.
Jakobson (1965[1971:352]) and (1971), three examples:
(i) In many languages, "the positive, comparative and superlative degrees
of adjectives show a gradual increase in the number of phonemes, e.g. high-
higher-highest, [Latin] altus, altior, altissimus. In this way, the signantia reflect
the gradation gamut of the signata" (1965[1971:352]). The higher the degree,
the longer the adjective.
(ii) "The signans of the plural tends to echo the meaning of a numeral
increment by an increased length of the form" (1965[1971:352]). The more
referents, the more phonemes (e.g. singular book, plural books, French singular
je finis 'I finish', plural nous finissons 'we finish').
(iii) In Russian, the perfective aspect expresses "a limitation in the extent
of the narrated event", and it is expressed by a more limited (i.e. a smaller)
number of phonemes (e.g. perfective zamoroz-it', imperfective zamoraž-ivat'
'freeze') (Jakobson 1971).
(see also Plank (1979:123), Haiman (1980:528-9), Anttila (1989:17), and
Taylor's (2002:46) Cognitive Grammar textbook).
2.2. Frequency-based explanation
Any efficient sign system in which costs correlate with signal length will
follow the following economy principle:
(5) The more predictable a sign, the shorter it is.
Since frequency implies predictability, we also get the folloiwng prediction
for efficient sign systems:
(6) The more frequent a sign is, the shorter it is.
(well known at least since Horn's (1921) and Zipf's (1935) work)
3
• universally comparative and superlative forms are significantly rarer
than positive forms of adjectives, and singular forms are significantly rarer
than plural forms (see Greenberg 1966:34-37, 40-41)
• for Russian, Fenk-Oczlon (1990) has shown that there is a strong
correlation between length and frequency of a verb form: in general, the more
frequent member of an aspectual pair is also shorter.
• the principle of iconicity of quantity makes many wrong predictions (as
was also observed by Haiman 2000:287):
– that plurals should generally be longer than duals,
– that augmentatives should generally be longer than diminutives,
– that words for 'ten' should be longer than words for 'seven', or even
– that words for 'long' should be longer than words for 'short', or
– that words for 'elephant' should be longer than words for 'mouse'
3. Iconicity of complexity
3.1. Advocates and examples
(7) More complex meanings are expressed by more complex forms.
some quotations from the literature that describe this principle and refer to it as "isomorphic"
or "iconic":
• Lehmann (1974:111): "Je komplexer die semantische Repräsentation eines
Zeichens, desto komplexer seine phonologische Repräsentation."
• Mayerthaler (1981:25): "Was semantisch "mehr" ist, sollte auch
konstruktionell "mehr" sein."
• Givón (1991:§2.2): "A larger chunk of information will be given a larger
chunk of code."
• Haiman (2000:283): "The more abstract the concept, the more reduced its
morphological expression will tend to be. Morphological bulk corresponds
directly and iconically to conceptual intension."
• Langacker (2000:77): "[I]t is worth noting an iconicity between of's
phonological value and the meaning ascribed to it (cf. Haiman 1983). Of all
the English prepositions, of is phonologically the weakest by any
reasonable criterion.... Now as one facet of its iconicity, of is arguably the
most tenuous of the English prepositions from the semantic standpoint as
well..."
often iconicity of complexity is described as a kind of "iconicity of markedness matching":
(8) Marked meanings are expressed by marked forms.
• Jakobson (1963[1966:270]): "language tends to avoid any chiasmus between
pairs of unmarked/marked categories, on the one hand, and pairs of
zero/nonzero affixes...on the other hand"
• Plank (1979:139): "Die formale Markiertheitsopposition bildet die
konzeptuell-semantische Markiertheitsopposition d[iagrammatisch]-
ikonisch ab."
• Haiman (1980:528): "Categories that are marked morphologically and
syntactically are also marked semantically."
4
• Mayerthaler (1987: 48-9): If (and only if) a semantically more marked
category Cj is encoded as "more" featured [=formally complex] than a less
marked category Ci, the encoding of Cj is said to be iconic."
• Givón 1991: "The meta-iconic markedness principle: Categories that are
cognitively marked—i.e. complex—tend to also to structurally marked."
• Aissen 2003:§3: "Iconicity favors the morphological marking of syntactically
marked configurations."
see also Matthews (1991:236), Newmeyer (1992:763), Helmbrecht (2004:226)
"formally marked" = "expressed overtly"; typical examples of such
markedness matching:
(9) less marked/unmarked (more) marked
number SINGULAR (tree-Ø) PLURAL (tree-s)
case SUBJECT (Latin homo-Ø) OBJECT (homin-em)
tense PRESENT (play-Ø) PAST (play-ed)
person THIRD (Spanish canta-Ø) SECOND (canta-s)
gender MASCULINE (petit) FEMININE (petit-e)
causation NON-CAUSATIVE CAUSATIVE
(Turkish ş-Ø-mek 'fall') (ş-ür-mek 'fell, drop')
object INANIMATE ANIMATE
(Spanish Veo la casa Veo a la niña.
'I see the house' 'I see the girl.')
These universal formal asymmetries have been known since Greenberg (1966)
(who did not invoke iconicty to explain them!)
3.2. Iconicity of complexity: frequency-based explanation
Greenberg (1966): frequency asymmetries explain formal asymmetries:
– "less marked" forms are more frequent, and "more marked" forms are less
frequent across languages
• the English preposition of is not only the most "semantically tenuous", but
also the most frequent of all the English prepositions.
• not only sufficient to account for the relevant phenomena, but also
necessary, because iconicity of complexity makes wrong predictions:
(10) less marked/unmarked (more) marked
number PLURAL SINGULAR
Welsh plu 'feathers' plu 'feather'
case OBJECT CASE SUBJECT CASE
Godoberi mak'i 'child' mak'i-di (ergative)
person SECOND P. IMPERATIVE THIRD P. IMPERATIVE
Latin canta-Ø 'sing!' canta-to 'let her sing'
gender FEMALE MALE
English widow-Ø widow-er
causation CAUSATIVE NONCAUSATIVE
German öffnen sich öffnen
• in all these cases, frequency makes the right predictions!
• often: "markedness reversal"
• "unmarkedness" = 'frequency': "Marked" means "rare", and "unmarked"
means "frequent". Cf. Haiman (2000:287):
5
"...what is fundamentally at issue is markedness. Where plurality is the norm, it is
the plural which is unmarked, and a derived marked singulative is employed to
signal oneness: thus, essentially, wheat vs. grain of wheat."
• what is fundamentally at issue is frequency, not markedness!
(see Haspelmath 2005 for further arguments why a notion of markedness is
superfluous in linguistics)
• Lehmann (1974) and Haiman (2000): grammatical morphemes are
universally shorter than lexical morphemes, and this iconically mirrors their
more abstract or less complex meaning.
• But again frequency and economy account for the same facts!
• Iconicity makes the wrong prediction that lexical items with highly abstract
or simple meanings should be consistently shorter than items with more
concrete or complex meanings (as noted by Ronneberger-Sibold 1980:239).
• It predicts, e.g., that entity should be shorter than thing or action, that animal
should be shorter than cat, that perceive should be shorter than see, etc.
3.3. The causative-inchoative alternation: Economy instead of iconicity
(Haspelmath 1993)
puzzle: the apparent counter-iconicity of anticausatives:
Russian otkryvat' otkryvat'-sja
'cause to open' 'open (intr.)'
Observation in Haspelmath 1993 (cf. also Croft 1990b):
different verb meanings behave differently across languages:
preferably coded as causatives: 'freeze', 'dry', 'sink', 'go out', 'melt', etc.
(spontaneous)
preferably coded as anticausatives: 'split', 'break', close', 'open', 'gather', etc.
(agent-caused)
Saving the iconicity hypothesis:
"Iconicity in language is based [not on objective meaning but] on conceptual
meaning... Events that are more likely to occur spontaneously will be associated
with a conceptual stereotype (or prototype) of a spontaneous event, and this will
be expressed in a structurally unmarked way." (Haspelmath 1993:106-7)
Simpler explanation:
Spontaneous verb meanings tend to occur more frequently as inchoatives;
agent-caused verb meanings occur more frequently as causatives. Due to
economic motivation, the rarer elements tend to be overtly coded.
cf. Wright (2001: 127-8):
% transitive
freeze 62% more causatives
dry 61%
melt 72%
burn 76%
open 80%
break 90% more anticausatives
6
3.4. Differential object marking: Economy instead of iconicity
(Aissen 2003)
Observation (Blansitt 1973, Comrie 1981, Bossong 1985, 1998, etc.):
The higher a direct-object is on the animacy scale, the more likely it is to be
overtly coded (i.e. accusative-marked).
Comrie 1989:128: "...the most natural kind of transitive construction is one where
the A[gent] is high in animacy and definiteness and the P[atient] is lower in
animacy and definiteness; and any deviation from this pattern leads to a more
marked construction."
Aissen 2003:§3 proposes a constraint subhierarchy involving local conjunction
of a "markedness hierarchy" of relation/animacy constraints with a constraint
against non-coding (*ØCASE):
"markedness subhierarchy":
*OBJ/HUM >> * OBJ/ANIM >> *OBJ/INAN
local conjunction with *ØCASE:
*OBJ/HUM & *ØCASE >> * OBJ/ANIM & *ØCASE >> *OBJ/INAN & CASE
"The effect of local conjunction here is to link markedness of content (expressed
by the markedness subhierarchy) to markedness of expression (expressed by
*Ø). That content and expression are linked in this way is a fundamental idea of
markedness theory (Jakobson 1939; Greenberg 1966). In the domain of
Differential Object Marking, this is expressed formally through the constraints
[shown immediately above]. Thus they are ICONICITY CONSTRAINTS: they favor
morphological marks for marked configurations." (Aissen 2003)
Simpler explanation:
Inanimate NPs occur more frequently as objects; animate NPs occur more
frequently as subjects. Due to economic motivation, the rarer elements tend
to be overtly coded.
4. Iconicity of cohesion
4.1. Advocates and examples
(11) Meanings that belong together more closely are expressed by more
cohesive forms
Haiman (1983:782-3): "The linguistic distance between expressions
corresponds to the conceptual distance between them."
(12) Haiman's (1983:782) cohesion scale
a. X word Y (function-word expression)
b. X Y (juxtaposition)
c. X-Y (bound expression)
d. Z (portmanteau expression)
7
• "cohesion" preferable to "distance" (cohesion contiguity!); Newmeyer
(1992:761-2) and Givón (1985:202, 1991:89) conflate cohesion and contiguity)
examples:
(i) Possessive constructions:
Inalienable possession shows at least the same degree of cohesion as alienable
possession, because in inealienable possession (i.e. possession of kinship and
body part terms) the possessor and the possessum belong together more
closely semantically (Haiman 1983:793-5), e.g.
(13) Abun (West Papuan; Berry & Berry 1999:77-82)
a. ji bi nggwe 'my garden'
I of garden
b. ji syim 'my arm'
I arm
(ii) Causative constructions:
Causative constructions showing a greater degree of cohesion tend to express
direct causation (where cause and result belong together more closely),
whereas causative constructions showing less cohesion tend to express
indirect causation (Haiman 1983:783-7; cf. also Comrie 1981:164-7, Dixon 2000:74-8).
(14) Buru (Austronesian; Indonesia; Grimes 1991:211, cit. after Dixon 2000:69)
a. Da puna ringe gosa.
3SG.A cause 3SG.O be.good
'He (did something which, indirectly,) made her well.'
b. Da pe-gosa ringe.
3SG.A CAUS-be.good 3SG.O
'He healed her (directly, with spiritual power
cf. also English cause to die vs. kill
(iii) Coordinating constructions:
Many languages distinguish between "loose coordination" and "tight
coordination" (i.e. less vs. more cohesive patterns), where the first expresses
greater conceptual distance and the latter expresses less conceptual distance
(Haiman 1983:788-90).
(15) Fe'fe' Bamileke (Hyman 1971:43)
a. à gén ntēe nī njwēn lwà'
he PAST go market and buy yams
'He went to the market and also (at some later date) bought yams.'
b. à gén ntēe njwēn lwà'
he PAST go market buy yams
'He went to the market and bought yams (there).'
Wälchli (2005): noun phrase coordination ("accidental coordination" vs.
"natural coordination")
(16) Georgian
a. gveli da k'ac'i 'the snake and the man'
snake and man
b. da-dzma 'brother and sister'
brother-sister
8
According to Haiman (1983), "conceptual dependence" also correlates with
cohesion ("The linguistic separateness of an expression corresponds to the
conceptual independence of the object or event which it represents."):
(iv) Complement clause constructions:
"The more integrated the two events are, the more likely is the complement
verb to be co-lexicalized—i.e. appear contiguously—with the main verb. The
less integrated the two events are, the more likely it is that a subordinating
morpheme will separate the complement clause from the main clause."
(Givón 1991:95-6; cf. also Haiman 1983:799, Cristofaro 2003)
(17) a. She let go of the knife.
b. She made him shave.
c. She told him to leave.
4.2. Iconicity of cohesion: frequency-based explanation
The cohesion scale is also found elsewhere in language structure:
(18) X Y X-Y Z
comparatives more arid dri-er worse
past tense play-ed went
negation doesn't see has-n't won't
gender lady doctor actr-ess nun
diminutive young elephant pig-let puppy
Explanation:
• The items that show greater formal cohesion are simply more frequent.
• High frequency is known to be a favorable environment for
– phonological fusion (e.g. hasn't vs. *knowsn't)
– preservation of older patterns (e.g. actress vs. *protectress)
– preservation/creation of suppletion (see Osthoff 1899, Ronneberger-Sibold 1988)
(i) Possessive constructions:
With inalienable possessed nouns, possessive constructions are of course
much more frequent than with alienable possessed nouns (cf. Nichols 1988).
Preliminary figures (from IDS Goethe corpus):
unpossessed
possessed
24
0
48
2
alienab
le
12
0
32
58
47
22
inalien
able
46
53
Table 1
• What counts is relative frequencies, not absolute frequencies: The
percentage of possessed occurrences of inalienable nouns will always be
significantly higher than the corresponding percentage of alienable nouns.
• Different predictions of the frequency-based explanation:
9
(A) Frequency predicts that the pronominal possessor should tend to be
shorter in inalienable possession, whereas this is not predicted by iconicity.
(19) alienable construction inalienable construction
a. Nakanai luma taku lima-gu
(Johnston 1981:217) house I hand-1SG
'my house' 'my hand'
b. Hua dgai
ʔ
fu d-za
ʔ
(Haiman 1983:793) I pig 1SG-arm
'my pig' 'my arm'
c. Ndjébbana budmánda ngáyabba nga-ngardabbámba
(McKay 1996:302-6) suitcase I 1SG-liver
'my suitcase' 'my liver'
d. Kpelle
ŋ
a p
ɛ
r
ɛ
i m-pôlu
(Welmers 1973:279) I house 1SG-back
'my house' 'my back'
(B) Iconicity (Distance matching) predicts that the additional element in
alienable constructions should occur in the middle between the possessor and
the possessum, as seen in the canonical examples: Maltese is-siġġu tiegħ-i [the-
chair of-me] 'my chair', Abun ji bi nggwe [I of garden] 'my garden'.
• But the extra element may also occur to the left or right of both the
possessor and the possessum:
(20) alienable construction inalienable construction
a. Puluwat nay-iy hamwol pay-iy
(Elbert 1974:55, 61) poss-1SG chief hand-1SG
'my chief' 'my hand'
b. 'O'odham ñ-mi:stol-ga ñ-je'e
(Zepeda 1983) 1SG-cat-POSSD 1SG-mother
'my cat' 'my mother'
c. Koyukon se-tel-e' se-tlee'
(Thompson 1SG-socks-POSSD 1SG-head
1996:654, 667) 'my socks' 'my head'
The frequency-based account makes no prediction about the ordering, so this
is expected.
(C) Some languages show overt coding of alienable nouns as well:
(21) Koyukon unpossessed possessed
alienable teł se-tel-e'
socks 1SG-socks-POSSD
'socks' 'my socks'
inalienable k'e-tlee' se-tlee'
UNSP-head 1SG-head
'head' 'my head'
10
(ii) Causative constructions:
Indirect/direct causative is difficult to study in corpora — verbs like kill, teach,
put, give, send, show are all direct causatives!
*make have: give
*make see: show
*make be: put
*make learn: teach
cf. *female brother: sister
*child woman: girl
*lower hand: foot
Morphological causatives must be more frequent than periphrastic causatives
(but no data available).
Frequency-based account makes a further prediction: markers of indirect
causation should not only be less cohesive, but should also tend to be longer
(cf. Dixon 2000:74-8)
(22) indirect causative direct causative
a. Amharic as-bälla a-bälla
(Haiman 1983:786, CAUS-eat CAUS-eat
Hetzron 1976:379) 'force to eat' 'feed'
b. Hindi ban-vaa- ban-aa-
(Dixon 2000:67, be.built-CAUS be.built-CAUS
Saksena 1982) 'have sth. built' 'build'
c. Jinghpaw -shangun sha-
(Dixon 2000, from Maran & Clifton 1976)
d. Creek -ipeyc -ic
(Martin 2000)
Dixon (2000): more semantic contrasts that are associated with longer/shorter
markers:
(23) longer marker shorter marker
action state
transitive intransitive
causee having control causee lacking control
causee unwilling causee willing
causee fully affected causee partially affected
accidental intentional
with effort naturally
Not all of these can be subsumed under "less conceptual distance", but they
can be plausibly related to frequency asymmetries.
(iii) Coordinating constrictions:
"Natural coordination" is presumably more frequent...
("natural" = "frequent")
11
(iv) Complement-clause constructions:
[I discuss only same-subject vs. different-subject 'want' constructions here; cf.
Haspelmath 1999b]
Givón 1990: 560: “the degree of finiteness is an iconic expression of the degree
of integration of the main and complement events”
"Given a hierarchy of degree of finiteness (or its converse, degree of nominality) of verb forms found in
a language, the more integrated the two events are,
(i) the more noun-like is the complement verb likely to be, and
(ii) the less finite verbal morphology – such as tense-aspect-modality and pronominal agreement
is the verb likely to display." (1990:561)
Cristofaro 2003: "At this stage, an iconic effect is obtained: states of affairs which are semantically
integrated, or conceptually close, are coded by morphosyntactically integrated structures."
• Different predictions of the frequency-based account:
(A) Complementizer may be shorter in same-subject constructions:
(24) Hopi (Uto-Aztecan) (Kalectaca 1978:170-71)
(SS) Pam as nös-ni-qe naawakna.
he PTCL eat-FUT-SS want
‘He wants to eat.’
(DS) Pam as nu-y nös-ni-qat naawakna.
he PTCL I-AKK eat-FUT-DS want
‘He wants me to eat.’
(B) the verb 'want' is sometimes shorter in same-subject constructions:
(25) Samoan (Oceanic) (Mosel & Hovdhaugen 1992:710, 714)
(SS) e fia si‘i e Leona Iosefa
GEN want carry ERG Leona Iosefa
‘Leona wants to carry Iosefa.’
(DS) e le mana‘o le teine e fasi ia le tama
GEN NEG want ART girl [GEN hit she ART boy
‘The girl doesn’t want the boy to hit her.’
5. Conclusion
References
Aissen, Judith. 2003. "Differential object marking: Iconicity vs. economy." Natural Language and Linguistic
Theory 21.3: 435-83.
Anttila, Raimo. 1989. Historical and comparative linguistics. 2nd revised editition. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Archangeli, Diana B. 1997. "Optimality Theory: An introduction to linguistics in the 1990s." In: Archangeli,
Diana B. & Pulleyblank, Douglas G. (eds.) Optimality Theory: an overview. Malden/MA: Blackwell, 1-32.
Blansitt, Edward L. Jr. 1973. "Bitransitive clauses." Working Papers in Language Universals (Stanford) 13: 1-26.
Blevins, Juliette. 2004. Evolutionary phonology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bossong, Georg. 1985. Differenzielle Objektmarkierung in den neuiranischen Sprachen. Tübingen: Narr.
Bossong, Georg. 1998. "Le marquage différentiel de l'objet dans les langues d'Europe". In: Feuillet, Jack (ed.)
Actance et valence dans les langues de l'Europe. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter, 193-258.
Comrie, Bernard. 1981/1989. Language Universals and Linguistic Typology. Oxford: Blackwell.
Croft, William. 1990. Typology and universals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Croft, William. 1990b. "Possible verbs and the structure of events." In: Tsohatzidis, S.L. (ed.) 1990. Meanings
and prototypes: Studies in linguistic categorization. London: Routledge, 48-73.
Croft, William. 2003. Typology and universals. 2nd edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
12
Dressler, Wolfgang U. & Mayerthaler, Willi & Panagl, Oswald & Wurzel, Wolfgang U. 1987. Leitmotifs in
Natural Morphology. (Studies in Langauge Companion Series, 10.) Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Fenk-Oczlon, Gertraud. 1990. "Ikonismus versus Ökonomieprinzip: Am Beispiel russischer Aspekt- und
Kasusbildungen." Papiere zur Linguistik 42.1: 49-69.
Fenk-Oczlon, Gertraud. 1991. "Frequenz und Kognition – Frequenz und Markiertheit." Folia Linguistica 25.3-
4:361-94.
Givón, T. 1985. "Iconicity, isomorphism and non-arbitrary coding in syntax." In: Haiman, John (ed.) 1985.
Iconicity in syntax. Amsterdam: Benjamins, 187-219.
Givón, T. 1990. Syntax: A functional-typological introduction. Vol. II. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Givón, T. 1991. "Isomorphism in the grammatical code: cognitive and biological considerations." Studies in
Language 15.1: 85-114.
Greenberg, Joseph. 1966. Language universals, with special reference to feature hierarchies. (Janua Linguarum,
Series Minor, 59.) The Hague: Mouton.
Haiman, John. 1980. "The iconicity of grammar." Language 56: 515-40.
Haiman, John. 1983. "Iconic and economic motivation." Language 59: 781-819.
Haiman, John. 1985. Natural syntax. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Haiman, John. 1994. "Iconicity." In: R.E. Asher (ed.) The encyclopedia of language and linguistics. Oxford:
Pergamon Press, 1629-33..
Haspelmath, Martin. 1993. "More on the typology of inchoative/causative verb alternations." In: Comrie,
Bernard & Polinsky, Maria (eds.) Causatives and transitivity. (Studies in Language Companion Series,
23.) Amsterdam: Benjamins, 87-120.
Haspelmath, Martin. 1999b. "On the cross-linguistic distribution of same-subject and different-subject
complement clauses: Economic vs. iconic motivation." Presented at the ICLC, Stockholm, July 1999.
(Downloadable handout: http://email.eva.mpg.de/~haspelmt/papers.html)
Haspelmath, Martin. 2003. "Creating economical morphosyntactic patterns in language change." Paper
presented at the workshop "Explaining linguistic universals: historical convergence and Universal
Grammar", University of California at Berkeley, 7-8 March 2003.
Haspelmath, Martin. 2005. "Against markedness (and what to replace it with)". To appear in Journal of
Linguistics
Helmbrecht, Johannes. 2004. "Ikonizität in Personalpronomina." Zeitschrift für Sprachwissenschaft 23: 211-44.
Jakobson, Roman. 1963[1966]. "Implications of language universals for linguistics." In: Greenberg, Joseph H.
(ed.) 1966. Universals of language. 2nd edition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 263-78. [First edition 1963]
Jakobson, Roman. 1965[1971] "Quest for the essence of language." In: Jakobson, Roman. 1971. Selected
Writings, vol. II. The Hague: Mouton, 345-59. [Originally published in Diogenes 51(1965)]
Jakobson, Roman. 1971. "Relationship between Russian stem suffixes and verbal aspects." In: Jakobson,
Roman. 1971. Selected Writings, vol. II. The Hague: Mouton, 198-202.
Kalectaca, Milo (1978), Lessons in Hopi. Tucson: University of Arizona Press.
Koptjevskaja-Tamm, Maria. 1996. "Possessive noun phrases in Maltese: Alienability, iconicity and
grammaticalization." Rivista di Linguistica 8.1: 245-274.
Langacker, Ronald. 2000. "The meaning of of." In: Lancaker, Ronald. 2000. Grammar and conceptualization.
Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter, 73-90.
Lee, David. 2001. Cognitive linguistics: an introduction. Melbourne: Oxford University Press.
Leech, Geoffrey & Rayson, Paul & Wilson, Andrew. 2001. Word frequencies in written and spoken English based
on the British National Corpus. Harlow, England: Pearson Education.
Lehmann, Christian. 1974. "Isomorphismus im sprachlichen Zeichen". Seiler, Hansjakob (ed.), Linguistic
workshop II: Arbeiten des Kölner Universalienprojekts 1973/4. München: Fink (Structura, 8); 98-123.
Levin, Beth & Rappaport Hovav, Malka. 1995. Unaccusativity. Cambridge/MA: MIT Press.
Levinson, Stephen C. 2000. Presumptive meanings: the theory of generalized conversational implicature.
Cambridge/MA: MIT Press.
Mayerthaler, Willi. 1981. Morphologische Natürlichkeit. Wiesbaden: Athenaion. (translated as Mayerthaler 1988)
Mayerthaler, Willi. 1987. "System-independent morphological naturalness." In: Dressler et al. 1987, 25-58.
Mayerthaler, Willi. 1988. Naturalness in morphology. Ann Arbor: Karoma.
Mosel, Ulrike & Hovdhaugen, Even. 1992. Samoan reference grammar. Oslo: Scandinavian University
Press.
Newmeyer, Frederick. 1992. "Iconicity and generative grammar." Language 68: 756-96.
Nichols, Johanna, 1988. "On alienable and inalienable possession." In: Shipley, William (ed.), In honor of
Mary Haas, pp. 557-609. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Osthoff, Hermann. 1899. Vom Suppletivwesen der indogermanischen Sprachen. Heidelberg: Hörning.
Plank, Frans. 1979. "Ikonisierung und De-Ikonisierung als Prinzipien des Sprachwandels."
Sprachwissenschaft 4: 121–158.
Ronneberger-Sibold, Elke. 1988. "Entstehung von Suppletion und Natürliche Morphologie." Zeitschrift für
Phonetik, Sprachwissenschaft und Kommunikationsforschung 41: 453-62.
Taylor, John R. 2002. Cognitive Grammar. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Tiersma, Peter. 1982. "Local and general markedness." Language 58: 832-49.
Thompson, Chad. 1996. "On the grammar of body parts in Koyukon Athabaskan." In: Chappell, Hilary &
McGregor, William (eds.) The grammar of inalienability, 651-676. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Wälchli, Bernhard. 2005. Co-compounds and natural coordination. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Wright, Saundra Kimberly. 2001. Internally caused and externally caused change of state verbs. Ph.D. dissertation,
Northwestern University (Evanston, IL).
... could serve as an explanation for (in)alienability as some concepts are more likely perceived as being linguistically inseparable because of the closer perceptual link. Haspelmath (2017: 21) contests this account since it seems to make predictions which have been refuted by the structural properties of some languages such as Koyukon (Thompson 1996). Haspelmath (2008 thus proffers another explanation, which is based on frequency and predictability. The baseline for this hypothesis is the observation that inalienable nouns (e.g. arm, sister) occur more frequently in possessed contexts than alienable nouns (e.g. garden, knife) (Haspelmath 2008: 19-20;2017: 194, 202). Consequently, speakers expect noun ...
... Consequently, speakers expect nouns like arm to be possessed, which makes an overt possessive marking redundant (Haspelmath 2017). Haspelmath (2008) thus suggests relative frequency in possessive contexts versus non-possessive contexts as a measure, which here means that lexemes that occur in the same slot are compared: for example, all tokens of arm are compared to all tokens of my arm. One of the great advantages of this approach is that it allows the comparison of high-frequency alienable nouns (e.g. ...
... Alienability was also a significant predictor in models contrasting the reduced variants. The data also provide confirmation for the frequency hypothesis (Haspelmath 2008(Haspelmath , 2017, revealing that nouns that are more likely to appear in possessed contexts are more likely to occur with a reduced 1POS. While most linguistic constraints are stable across time, the oldest and youngest cohorts show some variability in the constraint system underlying the grammar of 1POS as they age, which means that speaker grammar continues to be variable past critical age. ...
Article
Full-text available
This article explores intraspeaker malleability in the realisation of the first-person possessive in the North-East of England ([maɪ], versus [mi] and [ma]). The analysis relies on a combination of a trend sample and a novel dynamic panel corpus that covers the entire adult lifespan. While [mi] has been around at least since the 1970s on Tyneside, [ma] appears to have made its way into the system during the 1980s and 1990s. The panel data add intraspeaker information to this ongoing change, revealing a turnover in the proportional usage of possessive variants between two recordings that are on average ten years apart. Regression modelling provides differentiated information about intraspeaker changes across the lifespan, suggesting that, with only a few exceptions, intraspeaker grammars are stable across the lifespan. The analysis supports recent panel research that has argued for the importance of considering the socio-demographic trajectory of the individual: while speakers who are part of the ‘marché scolaire’ (Bourdieu & Boltanski 1975: 7) orient towards the standard, speakers working as professional carers (e.g. nurses) tend to retain high rates of the reduced variants across their lifespans to do local identity work and establish better interpersonal relations with their clients.
... marking strategies illustrated in Table 2 Numerous empirical studies have shown that the morphological marking of the causative alternation correlates with spontaneity (Croft 1990;Haspelmath 1993Haspelmath , 2008Haspelmath , 2016Haspelmath et al. 2014;Nedjalkov 1969). Haspelmath (1993: 103) contends that the more spontaneous an event is, the more likely it is to be expressed with a marked causative: ...
... Conversely, the causative expression type [=marked causative] is favored if the event is quite likely to happen even if no outside force is present. (Haspelmath 1993: 103;modified) This study has been extended, and its results have been reinterpreted with a novel explanation in Haspelmath (2008Haspelmath ( , 2016 and Haspelmath et al. (2014). In Haspelmath's view, the recurrent pattern in the encoding of the alternation reflects a principle of efficient communication: unmarked forms remain unmarked due to their high frequency of use (as measured by corpus frequency) irrespective of the lexical properties of verbs. ...
Article
Full-text available
Many verbs in English show causative and noncausative uses. The goal of this paper is to identify a factor most strongly associated with the realizations of the causative alternation. We report a corpus study that tested effects of three semantic and contextual factors-intentionality, contextual identifiability, and external causality-against 3,864 instances of causative and noncausative uses of 135 alternating verbs extracted from the automatically parsed British National Corpus. Our results of a series of multifactorial analyses of the corpus data indicate that intentionality and contextual identifiability are significantly associated with the realizations, with contextual identifiability being the most predictive factor: causative situations with a clear identifiable agent are realized predominantly as a causative, whereas those with a less clear, non-agentive cause are generally expressed noncausatively. Building on Rappaport Hovav's(2014) and H. Lee's(2023) accounts of contextual constraints on the causative alternation, we propose that the observed pattern of form-meaning associations in the data can be interpreted as a consequence of general principles of communicative efficiency.
... Ruiz de Mendoza (2020, 2023 introduced this dimension through the notion of iconic 5 contiguity (see Croft 2008;Givón 1985Givón , 1995, noting that, in metaphor, the source and target concepts are brought together through direct copula support, which creates contiguity between the source and target concepts and calls for a restricted interpretation, thereby endowing the resulting expression with subjectivity (evaluative and intensifying effects). In like-simile, by contrast, the explicit comparison marker "like" dissociates the source and target concepts, creating formal discontiguity (in Haspelmath's (2008) terminology) between the mapped concepts and endowing the resulting expression with open-endedness and, therefore, objectivity (e.g., prototype effects). For example, She is an angel is more impacting from the point of view of assessment than the corresponding statement She is like an angel, considering the following: ...
Article
Full-text available
Cognitive-oriented work on simile has developed out of attempts to pinpoint features distinguishing simile and metaphor. This development has had such consequences as 1) focusing on simile as an analogy-based process and 2) giving very little attention to the way simile and metaphor work together, treating them as independent rather than cooperating phenomena. Addressing these shortcomings, this study examines the ability of non-ironic like-simile to imply contrasts between the asserted source-target similarity and a thought or belief evoked by this similarity, giving rise to context-bound attitudinal and illocutionary implications. In cases of like-simile scaffolded by metaphors, the contrast-based process arises from the cooperation of the two phenomena in the sense that the scenario created by the like-simile rests on manipulating the conceptual metaphor(s) supporting the comparison. The analysis of these cases is placed in the Extended Conceptual Metaphor Theory (ECMT) – a contextual, multilevel theory of figurative language conceptualisation. The contrast-based process, drawn from the model of irony developed within the Lexical Constructional Model (LCM), is added to this theory as a mental-space level activity. Raykowski’s sensory schema (a generalized notion of accumulation intuitions) is also added above the image-schema level metaphors, presenting the manipulation of the scaffolding metaphors as based on the expression of this schema.
... See Zipf (1935) and Haspelmath (2008) on the way that high predictability and also high frequency of a sign can lead to its shorter phonological realization. marinis Journal of Greek Linguistics 24 (2024) 242-263 ...
Article
Full-text available
In this study, I parameterize the five tests proposed by Stevens (2005) for characterizing an element as an affixoid and formulate ten criteria for prefixation. Using these criteria, I analyze the morphological status of the initial components of Modern Greek words beginning with pale- and paʎo-. Contrary to Giannoulopoulou’s (1999) analysis of paleo- as a “confix” and paʎo- as a “stem”, I argue that pale- is a stem that has two allomorphic realizations: pale~paʎ. pale- is marked as [+learnèd] and paʎ- as [-learnèd]. While paʎo- historically derives from pale-, it has acquired a distinct morphological status and should now be considered a prefixoid. The ten criteria I present could serve as a model for determining the morphological status of initial elements in other Greek morphological structures and potentially in other languages where this status is ambiguous. Finally, I propose that prefixation in Greek differs from that in word-based languages. In Greek, prefixation is not a case of morphologization; rather, prefixes originate in and remain confined to the morphological domain.
... Thus, while it is normal for alienably possessed nouns to be separated from the possessor by a functional morpheme, this is not the case with inalienably possessed nouns that are supposed to be closer to the possessor as they express relational or part-to-whole relation. According to Haiman (2008) and Haspelmath (2008a), the inalienable/alienable dichotomy is a clear manifestation of diagrammatic iconicity. That is, correspondence always appears between conceptual distance and syntactic distance. ...
Conference Paper
Full-text available
Many of the world's languages grammaticalize a distinction between alienable and inalienable possession. Inalienable possession is defined as an unchanging, permanent semantic relationship between two nominals, the possessee and the possessor while alienable possession is a changing, context-dependent relationship between the possessee and the possessor (Heine 1997 and Alexiadu 2003). Such a dichotomy of acquired vs. inherited possession (as identified by Alexiadou 2003) does not exist in Standard Arabic in which possession is expressed by simple juxtaposition of the possessee and the possessor nominals, a structure known as the Semitic construct state (Benmamoun & Choueiri 2013). However, in Makkan Arabic (MA) an alternative possessive construction has emerged (besides the construct state) in which possession is expressed by using the morpheme ħaɡ between the possessee and the possessor. This morpheme might be followed by a possessor NP as in (1a) or take an enclitic possessive pronoun as in (1b-c) and it agrees with the possessed NP in gender as in (1c). (1) a. (al)-kita:b ħaɡ Sami b. (al)-kita:b ħaɡɡ-i c. al-waraɡ-a ħaɡɡ-at-i DEF-book POSS Sami. DEF-book POSS-1SG DEF-paper-F POSS-F-1SG 'Sami's book' 'my book' 'my paper' Cross-linguistically, kinship and body parts terms are prototypical members of the class of inalienably possessed nouns in languages that display distinct grammatical markings for in/alienable possession (Nichols 1992, Heine 1997, and Alexiadu 2003). These two noun classes are incompatible with the emergent periphrastic possessive construction in MA, as indicated by the ungrammaticality of (2a) and (2b). Thus, I assume that the emergent possessive construction in MA is specific to alienable possession and that it is the outcome of the grammaticalization of the inalienable/alienable split in this variety of Arabic. (2) a. *ʕam ħaɡɡ-i b. *Ra:s ħaɡɡ-i uncle POSS-1SG head POSS-1SG (Intended) 'my uncle' (Intended) 'my head' In this paper I argue that the possessive marker ħaɡ is a functional morpheme that has been grammaticalized from the noun ħaɡ 'right'. As a noun, ħaɡ 'right' can (a) be pluralized: ħuɡu:ɡ 'rights' and (b) take the definite article: al-ħaɡ 'the right'. However, the grammaticalized functional possessive morpheme, ħaɡ lost these properties, so it is incompatible with the definite article (3a) and cannot be pluralized (3b). Nonetheless, grammaticalization does involve gains (Hopper & Traugot, 2003), ħaɡ as a possessive morpheme inflects for gender as in (1c), a property which does not apply to the lexical source, the noun ħaɡ. (3) a. *(al)-kita:b al-ħaɡ Sami b. *al-kutub huɡu:ɡ Sami DEF-book DEF-POSS Sami DEF -books POSS.PL Sami (Intended) 'Sami's book' (Intended) 'Sami's books' In the recent study, I show that the possessive morpheme ħaɡ conforms to Hopper's (1991) five principles of Grammaticalization, namely (1) layering, (2) divergence, (3) specialization, (4) persistence, and (5) decategorialization. Moreover, the choice of noun ħaɡ to be grammaticalized as a possessive marker is not arbitrary but complies with the principle of specialization on the basis of textual frequency and semantic generalizations (Hopper 2003). This cline of grammaticalization in MA is consistent with the insights of grammaticalization as a cyclical process (Hopper and Traugott 2003), and, interestingly, it is in line with a similar cline of grammaticalization in Maltese and Egyptian Arabic (Stolz 2011 and Sultan 2007).
... The Morphilizer component contained an overgeneralizing algorithm that is still part of the current 3rd version as a robust backup in case a word could not be retrieved via the OED interface. Since this algorithm works astonishingly well for rare and therefore regularly formed words (Haspelmath 2008;Haspelmath & Karjus 2017: 1218-1219), it will be presented here in more detail. It should be explicitly noted that the algorithm will fail if the root of the word also happens to be a suffix or prefix form (see example (4)). ...
Article
Full-text available
This paper addresses the development of lexical affixation throughout the last 700 years of the English language. More specifically, it pursues two objectives. First, a short outline of the methodological approaches will be devised reaching from stand-alone applications (Peukert 2014) and shared-work solutions (Peukert 2018) to requesting the OED RESTful API. Second, two sets of results will be presented. The first set includes overall aggregations of all productive affixes as well as their shares on the total number of each affix type. The second set of results elaborates on two interesting cases chosen from highly productive prefixes and suffixes. The contribution closes with a short discussion on alternative explanations and limitations of the chosen approach. Although the affix token frequencies by and large replicate the findings in Peukert (2016), which are based on type frequencies, the presented data substantiate the idea that, in terms of lexical morpheme usage, English reveals more and more characteristics of a prefixing language.
Chapter
The volume is of direct interest to scholars, from senior academics to PhD students, interested in linguistically relevant phonetic and gestural information and in the relationship between multimodal communication and grammar. It contains important work in a relatively new, dynamic and exploratory field that is receiving a lot of attention, namely the relation of multimodal communication with grammatical frameworks, notably Construction Grammar. Drawing on case studies in different languages (English, Modern Greek, Czech, Hebrew, Italian), the chapters provide both the necessary theoretical discussion and solid empirical evidence (corpus-based or experimental) for integrating multimodal interactional features with grammatical description and analysis. This timely collection of studies highlights the recent marriage of cognitive/constructional and interactional approaches and addresses head-on questions and challenges like: which multimodal features are systematic and conventional enough to be integrated into grammar and what are appropriate ways of achieving the integration.
Chapter
Iconicity: East Meets West presents an intersection of East-West scholarship on Iconicity. Several of its chapters thus deal with Asian languages and cultures, or a comparison of world languages. Divided into four categories: general issues; sound symbolism and mimetics; iconicity in literary texts; and iconic motivation in grammar, the chapters show the diversity and dynamics of iconicity research, ranging from iconicity as a driving force in language structure and change, to the various uses of images, diagrams and metaphors at all levels of the literary text, in both narrative and poetic forms, as well as on all varieties of discourse, including the visual and the oral.
Article
Full-text available
This study examines zero marking, i.e. the absence of an overt exponent, in adjectival, nominal, and verbal inflectional morphology across languages. The first part of the study provides an overview of the distribution of zero markers in inflection paradigms using the UniMorph dataset. The results show that there is a general preference against zero marking. The distribution of zero markers varies to a great extent across languages and lemmas, the only robust trend being that they are avoided in cells that express a high number of grammatical values. The second part of this study examines the association between marker frequencies and phonological length, using the Universal Dependencies treebanks. While token frequency is a good predictor for the length of overt markers, it does not account for the occurrence of zero markers. This is taken as evidence to support a differential non-development scenario of zero marking rather than a phonetic reduction scenario.
Chapter
This volume comprises a selection of papers that were presented at the 24th International Conference on Historical Linguistics (ICHL24), which took place at the Australian National University (ANU) in Canberra from 1-5 July, 2019. The volume’s aim is to reflect the breadth of research presented at the conference, with each chapter representative of a workshop or themed session. A striking aspect of ICHL24 was the three-day workshop on computational and quantitative approaches to historical linguistics and two of the chapters represent different aspects of this workshop. A number of chapters present research that explores mechanisms and processes of change within specific domains of language, while others explore interactions of change across linguistic domains. Two chapters represent a common theme at the conference and consider the role of historical linguistics in explaining non-linguistic histories of language diversification.
Chapter
Full-text available
The papers in this volume all explore one kind of functional explanation for various aspects of linguistic form – iconicity: linguistic forms are frequently the way they are because they resemble the conceptual structures they are used to convey, or, linguistic structures resemble each other because the different conceptual domains they represent are thought of in the same way. The papers in Part I of this volume deal with aspects of motivation, the ways in which the linguistic form is a diagram of conceptual structure, and homologous with it in interesting ways. Most of the papers in Part II focus on isomorphism, the tendency to associate a single invariant meaning with each single invariant form. The papers in Part III deal with the apparent arbitrariness that arises from competing motivations.
Article
Full-text available
Unmarked terms in the lexicon, compared to marked ones, are typically more frequent in use, less complex in form, and acquired earlier by children learning a language. Terms which are unmarked in single languages are often unmarked in all languages; however, marking is not always invariable across languages, or through time within individual languages. The present work focuses on variation in cultural importance as a factor which influences marking. As the importance of a referent changes within a speech community, the marking value of its label alters, often resulting in lexical change. Introductions of previously unknown referents in culture contact situations-e.g. domestic plants and animals-frequently have led to shifts in cultural importance. Such examples illustrate how cultural factors, by influencing the assignment of marking, often play an important role in lexical change.
Book
"This is the latest version of the 1956 book which began the modern study of universals, and provides the foundation for many inquiries that followed. The hypotheses are cast at a moderate level of abstraction, and so are likely to survive as a basis for inquiry for many decades to come." Prof. Dr. William Labov. 1966, 2005 by Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co. KG, 10785 Berlin. All rights reserved.
Article
The distinction between contactive and non-contactive causation shows up repeatedly in languages (Masica 1976, Chap. 3; Cole 1976), and is claimed by Xolodovič 1969 to be 'fundamental' in their description. Arguing against earlier descriptions, this paper provides an alternate analysis of this important contrast.