ArticlePDF Available

Abstract

In this article, I propose a novel theory to explain the possible physiological origins of the relatively mild mental pain that is often labeled as boredom and possibly loneliness or a negative mood, depending on one’s situation. My admittedly speculative hypothesis is that most people in modern societies are beset by a chronic level of diffuse nociception (DN), due to the lingering effects of past stressors. For most people, most of the time, their DN is mild enough to be kept out of conscious awareness by various distractions. However, when people are deprived of all their usual distractions, DN may enter awareness and provoke a feeling of pain without being associated with any noticeable bodily sensation to which the pain can be localized. Thus, the discomfort is experienced as mental pain. It follows that whatever can reduce DN and/or keep it out of awareness will be positively reinforced, leading to an addiction to various distractions, including mind wandering. In support of my theory, I discuss research on how the activity of well-known neural networks serves to regulate the intensity of physical, as well as mental, pain. I also discuss individual differences in DN and their relationship to boredom proneness and neuroticism. Finally, I describe how stress reactions can create DN, how psychological factors can mitigate mental pain, and how chronic stress reactions may begin early in human development.
Psychology of Consciousness: Theory, Research,
and Practice
Mental Pain, Boredom, and Di󰍎use Nociception
Barry H. Cohen
Online First Publication, November 21, 2024. https://dx.doi.org/10.1037/cns0000405
CITATION
Cohen, B. H. (2024). Mental pain, boredom, and di󰍒use nociception. Psychology of Consciousness: Theory,
Research, and Practice. Advance online publication. https://dx.doi.org/10.1037/cns0000405
Mental Pain, Boredom, and Diffuse Nociception
Barry H. Cohen
Department of Applied Psychology, Steinhardt School of Culture, Education, and Human Development,
New York University
In this article, I propose a novel theory to explain the possible physiological origins of the
relatively mild mental pain that is often labeled as boredom and possibly loneliness or a
negative mood, depending on ones situation. My admittedly speculative hypothesis is
that most people in modern societies are beset by a chronic level of diffuse nociception
(DN), due to the lingering effects of past stressors. For most people, most of the time, their
DN is mild enough to be kept out of conscious awareness by various distractions.
However, when people are deprived of all their usual distractions, DN may enter
awareness and provoke a feeling of pain without being associated with any noticeable
bodily sensation to which the pain can be localized. Thus, the discomfort is experienced
as mental pain. It follows that whatever can reduce DN and/or keep it out of awareness
will be positively reinforced, leading to an addiction to various distractions, including
mind wandering. In support of my theory, I discuss research on how the activity of well-
known neural networks serves to regulate the intensity of physical, as well as mental,
pain. I also discuss individual differences in DN and their relationship to boredom
proneness and neuroticism. Finally, I describe how stress reactions can create DN, how
psychological factors can mitigate mental pain, and how chronic stress reactions may
begin early in human development.
Keywords: boredom, mental pain, nociception, mind wandering, stress
Nociception refers to the process whereby
specialized sensory receptors, called nociceptors,
distributed throughout the skin, the skeletomus-
cular system, and the viscera, are triggered by
physical stimuli potentially harmful to the body
and then send neural signals toward the brain.
Much is now known about the nerve pathways
that carry these signals and how they are
processed and modulated along the way.
However, whereas these signals are generally
capable of producing some conscious experi-
ence of pain, there are a host of psychological
factors that inuence the perceived intensity
and unpleasantness caused by these noxious
sensations.
Damage or extreme stress to a particular part of
the body can produce a highly localized experi-
ence of physical pain. However, I will propose in
this article that relatively mild nociception arising
diffusely from several areas of the body at once,
possibly including both skeletal muscles and the
viscera, can lead to a general level of discomfort
that is perceived as mental or psychological pain.
If the unpleasantness of this stimulation cannot
be subjectively localized to the body, it can easily
be attributed to a feeling or mood arising from
Barry H. Cohen https://orcid.org/0000-0002-6241-
1927
Barry H. Cohen is now at Greenwich, Connecticut, United
States.
The author has no known conicts of interest to disclose.
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons
Attribution-Non Commercial-No Derivatives 4.0 International
License (CC BY-NC-ND 4.0; https://creativecommons.org/
licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0). This license permits copying and
redistributing the work in any medium or format for
noncommercial use provided the original authors and source
are credited and a link to the license is included in attribution.
No derivative works are permitted under this license.
Correspondence concerning this article should be
addressed to Barry H. Cohen, 47 Lafayette Place,
Greenwich, CT 06830, United States. Email:
barry.cohen@nyu.edu
1
Psychology of Consciousness:
Theory, Research, and Practice
© 2024 The Author(s)
ISSN: 2326-5523 https://doi.org/10.1037/cns0000405
ones situation (e.g., boredom if one feels stuck
performing a monotonous task).
Any external sensory stimulation and/or motor
activity that has the consequence of reducing this
mental pain will be positively reinforced and can
therefore easily become psychologically addictive.
In Dopamine Nation,Lembke (2021) explained
how people in modern societies are quickly getting
addicted to the secretion of dopamine associated
with various pleasurable activities. My theory adds
to that framework by suggesting that a chronic low-
level of diffuse nociception (DN) makes most
people that much more susceptible to addiction due
to the avoidance of mental pain that these addictive
activities and experiences provide.
The Two Components of Physical Pain
It has long been recognized that physical pain
has two distinct dimensions; Melzack and Casey
(1968) formalized this notion by referring to them
as sensory and motivational-affective. Modern
pain research is based on this distinction. Price
et al. (1987), for example, asked their participants
to rate their pain on two separate visual analog
scales, one for the level of pain sensation intensity
and one for the degree of unpleasantness. They
found important differences in the relative intensi-
ties of the sensory and affective components of
bodily pain according to the participantsinterpre-
tation of their situation (e.g., given equal levels of
painintensity,womenfocusingonthebirthoftheir
baby rated their labor pains as less unpleasant than
those who focused mainly on their pain). Other
studies have shown that pain of a given intensity is
less aversive if it can be predicted (Ploghaus et al.,
2003)orcontrolled(Wiech et al., 2006).
In fact, in some special circumstances, the
sensory dimension of pain can be felt with little or
no unpleasantness. That physical pain has two
distinct components can be seen most clearly
when one component appears in the absence of
the other. An extreme example that illustrates the
separability of the two pain dimensions occurs in
the case of congenital indifference to pain, or pain
asymbolia (Nagasako et al., 2003). Those suffering
from this anomaly frequently injure themselves
because they do not experience any immediate
motivation to withdraw from a stimulus damaging
their body. A somewhat similar indifference to pain
was produced in the early days of psychosurgery
by means of a prefrontal lobotomy. Fortunately,
that crude, highly destructive procedure has been
replaced by a much more specic operation in
which only portions of the anterior cingulate cortex
(ACC) are bilaterally ablated; thus, it is referred to as
a cingulotomy (Wang et al., 2017). Used as a last-
resort treatment for chronic debilitating pain, its
effects were described on the Columbia University
Neurosurgery (n.d.) website in the following way:
Cingulotomy targets the bothersomeaspect of
pain. Although not all patients are completely free
of pain after the procedure, many report feeling less
anxiety and less distress from any pain that remains
(https://www.neurosurgery.columbia.edu/patient-
care/treatments/cingulotomy). Temporary indif-
ference to pain can be produced by various drugs,
but it is especially pronounced upon inhaling
nitrous oxide, which can produce a dramatic
dissociation between the sensory and aversive
dimensions of pain (Chapman et al., 1943).
A dissociation between the two dimensions of
pain occurs in the opposite direction in hyper-
algesia (the aversiveness of pain far exceeds what
could be expected from relatively mild nociceptor
stimulation) or allodynia (pain produced by
nonnociceptive stimuli; Jensen & Finnerup,
2014), but it is not clear if the aversive dimension
of pain can occur without any associated bodily
stimulation.
Is Mental Pain the Same as the Affective
Component of Physical Pain?
The concept of mental pain has received
considerable attention recently because of its close
association with depression and suicidality. In this
clinical context, mental pain is dened largely by its
severity. It is notable that when mental pain is severe
enough, the sufferers of it often describe it in a way
that implies that their mental pain is essentially the
same as the painful component of bodily pain but
more intense, even though it cannot be attributed to
a bodily location. To illustrate this concept, Mee et
al. (2006) presented several quotes from severely
depressed patients who had attempted suicide, such
as: I have suffered from severe, recurrent depre-
ssion for 40 years. The psychological pain that I felt
during my depressed periods was horrible and more
severe than my current physical pain associated
with metastases in my bones from cancer(p. 682),
and The pain from my recent episode passing a
urinary stone did not compare in severity to the pain
and suffering I experienced during my depression
when I was so intensely suicidal(p. 682).
2 COHEN
The concept of mental pain is compelling in the
case of profound grief and severe depression,
given the types of descriptions I just quoted. In
those cases, the pain is strong enough to stand out
from any other feeling. However, I propose that
just as bodily pain can be mild or severe, mental
pain, whether or not it is accompanied by a
noticeable bodily sensation, can also be mild as
well as severe. To answer the question posed by
the title of this subsection, experiences described
as mental pain may be occurrences in which the
cerebral activity underlying the unpleasant
dimension of pain is evoked solely by psychological
causes, such as social or romantic rejection, rather
than bodily nociception. Biro (2010) expressed this
possibility thusly:
If tissue damage is not necessary to feeling pain and if
there is a special affective center in the brain devoted to
such feeling, why cant that center be activated by means
other than the nociceptor pathway? Why isnt it possible
that noxious psychological stimulistimuli that
threaten the emotional well-being of a person, like the
loss of a child or the pain of depression or the suffering
of cancer patientsnd their way to the anterior
cingulate gyrus, making us feel the same way we do
when we experience physical pain? (p. 663)
I will revisit the question posed by this section
in the context of a deep dive into the neural
mechanisms underlying the experience of pain
later in this article.
Is All Pain Mental Pain?
When the sensory component of bodily pain
occurs withnone of the affective componentthat
is, if there is no unpleasantness to itdoes it really
make sense to call it pain?Ontheonehand,it
seems contradictory to say that the pain someone
felt while inhaling nitrous oxide, for instance, was
not painful. On the other hand, it seems perfectly
legitimate to state that severe cases of grief or
depression are painful, even in the absence of any
sensation normally associated with bodily pain.
This realization leads logically to the notion that
all pain is mental. As Joffe and Sandler (1967)
expressed it, pain should be dened broadly as:
consisting essentially of an unpleasant feeling quality
which may be associated with a wide range of ideational
content. Pain referred to the body can then be seen as a
particular instance of pain in which the ideational content
refers to the idea, correct or otherwise, of body damage.
Our general view of pain is that it should not be
restricted to the particular feeling quality associated with
bodily pain, but that it is a general element in all
unpleasant feeling states. (Emphasis in original, p. 71)
Although all pain can be said to be mental, for
clarity, I will adopt the convention of using the
term physical pain for instances in which pain
appears subjectivelyto be coming from a particular
bodily location and mental pain when there is no
associated bodily sensation. I will also use the term
psychological pain when mental pain appears to
have a specic psychological cause, as in the case
of social rejection.
Conceptualizing Boredom as a Form of
Mental Pain
The subjective experience known as boredom
is almost universally identied with a negative,
aversive feeling that one wishes to escape (Goetz
et al., 2014). In that sense, boredom fullls the
denition of mental pain, and, in its milder form,
it appears to be a good example of pure mental
pain (i.e., not colored by specic emotions).
However, recent research, of which there is a
great deal, has been focused mainly on determin-
ing the particular conditions that can produce
subjective reports of boredom in a laboratory
environment, such as having participants perform
tasks that are very easy and inherently uninter-
esting or tasks that are frustratingly difcult
(Westgate & Wilson, 2018). Little research has
touched on the physiological basis of the mental
pain usually associated with states of boredom.
My main question with respect to boredom is:
How does a boring situation lead to activation of
brain activity associated with mental pain? Given
how common and unpleasant experiences of
boredom can be, I believe this is a question worth
addressing. One avenue for understanding the
aversive nature of boredom is to view boredom as
arising from the thwarting of an inherent drive,
analogous to depriving a person of food.
The Exploratory Drive
Boredom has a distinct motivational aspect,
which has led psychologists to theorize that it
likely serves a useful, or even vital, purposeone
that has had an adaptive advantage through the
course of evolution. Bench and Lench (2013)
explained the main function of boredom thusly:
Boredom should encourage the pursuit of goals and
experiences that differ from those currently experienced.
MENTAL PAIN AND DIFFUSE NOCICEPTION 3
In many cases, this would come in the form of novel
stimulation which would introduce opportunities for
cognitive and social growth, even if the alternative
situations might elicit negative emotion. That is, by
creating a desire for change, boredom encourages people
to alter their current situation, which permits the attainment
of opportunities that might have been missed. (p. 464)
It is a commonplace observation that various
members of the animal kingdom, especially
mammals, have what is often described as an
exploratory drive, along with a need for novel
stimulation. Moreover, animals can seem to be
bored by monotonous surroundings. For exam-
ple, Meagher and Mason (2012) found that minks
housed for months in impoverished cages later
responded to all types of stimuli more quickly
than minks that had been housed instead in
enriched cages.
It is easy to see why a need for novel stimulation
would be selected for by evolution. Thus, it is
understandable that humans would share that
need and be especially aware of an urge toward
changing their environments and/or trying new
activities when faced with a monotonous and
unproductive situation. When thwarted, that urge
could be expected to give rise to an uncomfortable
feeling, much like the deprivation of food causes
hunger. The pain of a thwarted drive can be
viewed as a form of mental pain, and its subjective
nature suggests a commonality with physical pain.
The Neurophysiology of Pain
Pain as a Homeostatic Emotion or Drive
According to Craig (2003), pain in humans is
“… an emotion that reects specic primary
homeostatic afferent activity(p. 304). In Figure
1, Craig (2003) illustrated the major pathways
that carry nociceptive signals to the brain and
ultimately lead to the unpleasant motivational
aspect of pain. Neural impulses travel up the
lateral spinothalamic tract, innervating the para-
brachial nucleus and the periaqueductal gray area
(PAG) in the brainstem, before relaying in two
medial nuclei of the thalamus. The ventral medial
nucleus sends highly specic information to the
insular cortex, while the medial dorsal nucleus
sends more integrated homeostatic information to
the ACC. This is the brain structure whose ablation
is called a cingulotomy, and, as mentioned
previously, its destruction can greatly reduce the
aversiveness of physical pain.
Working with a large database of functional
magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) ndings,
Lieberman and Eisenberger (2015) implicated the
dorsal ACC (dACC) specically as the critical
area for pain processing. However, they concep-
tualized the dACC more broadly as mediating
negative affect and serving the role of a neural
alarm system warning the higher cortical areas that
“… hardwired survival-relevant goals are [being]
threatened, including those that do not involve
nociception(p. 15254). These survival-relevant
goals include hunger, thirst, and breathlessness (air
hunger), and Lieberman and Eisenberger present
some evidence that conicts involving these
goals also activate the dACC. As an example of
a survival-relevant goal that does not directly
involve nociception, they offer social rejection,
which has often been found to be associated with
dACC activity.
The Salience Network
The focus of much brain-scanning research in
the last couple of decades has been on neural
networks, which consist of interconnected corti-
cal areas that tend to activate together under
reproducible conditions. This research has reli-
ably identied three major neural networks in
participants at rest: a central executive network; a
default-mode network (DMN); and a salience
network (SN; Goulden et al., 2014;Seeley et al.,
2007;Sridharan et al., 2008). I will discuss the
rst two in a later context, but it is the SN that is
especially relevant to pain. The major hubs of the
SN are the dACC and the anterior insula (AI; or
the larger frontoinsular cortex). The SN also
includes the amygdala and areas in the brainstem.
The name of this network comes from its
activation by salient stimuli, and you will notice
that it includes the brain areas that respond to
pain, which have been referred to as the pain
matrix(Legrain et al., 2011).
As would be expected, nociceptive stimuli
trigger the attention-getting activity of the SN.
However, it can also be expected that the SN will
be activated by interference with nonnociceptive
survival-relevant goals, such as social afliation,
which also involve threats to the well-being of the
organism. From that perspective, the need for
novelty and exploration could be considered a
nonnociceptive survival-relevant goal, such as
social afliation, and when a conict with that
4 COHEN
goal arises, the dACC and other parts of the SN or
pain matrix may be activated.
The Overlap of Neural Activity Subserving
Both Physical and Psychological Pain
The pain of social or romantic rejection is a
good example of a feeling that is experienced
mainly as psychological pain, even though brain-
scanning research has shown that there is a great
deal of overlap in the patterns of cortical activity
associated with social pain and physical pain that
includes brain areas that play a major role in
processing bodily pain (see Eisenberger, 2012,
for a review). Summarizing their results, Kross et
al. (2011) wrote:
Here we demonstrate that when rejection is powerfully
elicitedby having people who recently experienced an
unwanted break-up view a photograph of their ex-
partner as they think about being rejectedareas that
support the sensory components of physical pain
(secondary somatosensory cortex; dorsal posterior
insula) become active. (p. 6270)
These ndings can help to explain the physical
metaphors often used to describe the pain of
romantic rejection, such as heartache. However,
despite the extensive overlap on a macro level,
Woo et al. (2014), using multivariate pattern
analysis, were able to discriminate the neural
activity evoked by social rejection from that
evoked by painful heat. Woo et al.s research was
directed at the theory that, through evolution,
social rejection came to activate the physical pain
system as a means to ensure that social animals
would not casually risk the serious dangers of
social isolation. Their research demonstrated that
social rejection does not activate the same exact
neural areas as painful heat applied to the surface
of the body, though they did show activation of
adjacent areas in the same anatomical brain
regions. Notably, Woo et al. do not attempt to
explain why social rejection should evoke
activity in any parts of the insula or somatosen-
sory cortex, which are strongly associated with
bodily perception (i.e., interoception).
The ndings of Woo et al. (2014) do call into
question whether the mental pain of social
rejection is the same as the aversive component
of physical pain. As a working assumption, I will
adopt a simple form of mindbrain identity theory
that proposes that distinguishable subjective
experiences must correspond to distinct patterns
of brain activity and vice versa. In that case, Woo
et al.s results imply that social pain is not identical
to the aversive feeling of physical pain. However,
both social rejection and bodily harm activate the
SN broadly and narrow the focus of consciousness
to deal with the perceived threat. It may be this
overall mobilization of the brain that is aversive
and is perceived as a painfulexperience, rather
than the activation of specic neurons. I will
present psychologicalevidence in a later section to
support this general notion. First, it is important to
acknowledge the critical role of the prefrontal
cortex in creating the experience of pain.
The Role of the Prefrontal Cortex
Though activation in the dorsal part of the ACC
has been shown consistently to play a major role
in the production of the aversive aspect of pain,
there is solid evidence suggesting that the dACC
has its effect on the unpleasantness of pain
through its neural projections to the medial
portion of the prefrontal cortex (mPFC). If this is
the case, it could be predicted that any experi-
mental manipulation that increases the aversive-
ness of a painful stimulus without increasing the
intensity of the sensory input ought to lead to
increased activity specically in the mPFC. This
hypothesis was conrmed in a study by Bräscher
et al. (2016), who compared controllable and
uncontrollable thermal stimulation while parti-
cipants continuously rated their pain intensity in
an fMRI scanner. As compared to controllable
pain, uncontrollable pain was associated with
greater connectivity between the mPFC and both
the AI and parts of the ACC. The authors suggest
that the mPFC may actually be increasing
nociceptive processing in the insula and ACC
as a result of an increased emotional reaction to
the uncontrollability of the painful stimulation.
They also found that the dorsolateral prefrontal
cortex appeared to be decreasing activity in the
insula and thalamus during controllable pain,
suggesting that the controllability allowed for
downregulation of pain processing.
To be more specic about the part of the mPFC
that is most associated with the unpleasantness of
pain, Jahn et al. (2016), in a fMRI study using
electric shocks as aversive stimuli, found pain
processing to be localized to the more ventral
region of the mPFC (ventromedial prefrontal
cortex). A very recent review of brain-scanning
research on chronic pain patients by Johansson
et al. (2024) came to an even narrower
MENTAL PAIN AND DIFFUSE NOCICEPTION 5
localization of an mPFC area that may be
responsible for cognitive and evaluative responses
that exacerbate the aversive quality of pain:
We suggest that increased dorsal vmPFC activity may
reect a tendency to overthink the meaning of pain for
oneself and ones actions. This may in turn increase the
personal threat of a given context and thereby increase
the susceptibility to experience pain, which we suggest
might be reected by an increased functional connec-
tivity between the dorsal vmPFC and the AIC [anterior
insular cortex]. (p. 8)
A Proposed Physiological Basis for the Pain of
Boredom
Earlier, I described one possible theory for
explaining the unpleasantness of boredom: That
the aversive state known as boredom occurs when
a drive, such as the exploratory drive, is blocked
by ones circumstances, resulting in the activation
of the salience/pain network. Boredom research-
ers have suggested a causal role for the impeding
of other, more specically human, drives, such as
a need to pursue a meaningful goal or to reach an
optimum level of cognitive engagement (Bench &
Lench, 2013;Westgate & Wilson, 2018). I wish to
propose a radically different source for the pain of
boredom, which though speculative, avoids the ad
hoc positing of human drives with no known
physiological basis. My novel proposal is that
much of the unpleasantness of boredom can be
explained by assuming that most people live with a
fairly constant level of nociception that is capable
of evoking mental pain under particular conditions.
Diffuse Nociception
When nociception is caused by, or appears to
be caused by, an intense bodily sensation, it is
experienced as physical pain, such that the sensory
and affective components are fused into a single
subjective experience that cannot be separated
phenomenologically. However, suppose that one is
receiving nociceptive signals that are so diffuse as to
be difcult to localize subjectively in ones body. In
that case, the nociception may activate the unpleas-
ant component of pain far more than any associated
sensory component. Therefore, this DN, although of
bodily origin, might nonetheless be experienced as
mental pain, which may then be falsely attributed to
psychological causes. There are several means by
which DN could occur, but a particularly common
source consists of the physiological changes
that follow the bodys stress reactions, often to
challenging psychological situations.
Possible Sources of DN
Reactions to stressful situations can have
considerable effects on several physiological
systems, and if these reactions occur often or are
sustained over time, the aftereffects can linger or
even lead to chronic physiological adaptations.
Such changes could evoke DN via some of the
mechanisms described next.
Cortisol
Stressful situations often lead quickly to the
activation of the sympathetic branch of the
autonomic nervous system as part of the ght
or ightresponse. In addition to the secretion of
adrenaline (i.e., epinephrine), the stress response
may eventually include the secretion of gluco-
corticoids, especially cortisol, through the activa-
tion of the hypothalamuspituitaryadrenal axis.
Circulating cortisol is very helpful in emergency
situations because it increases the availability of
glucose for energy and curbs inammatory and
immune responses until the emergency has been
resolved, at which point negative feedback loops
work to bring hypothalamuspituitaryadrenal
activity down to normal levels.
Unfortunately, prolonged periods of stress can
lead to glucocorticoid resistance, thus defeating
the feedback loops and keeping the level of
cortisol high. High cortisol levels are particularly
toxic to hippocampal regions and reduce their
volume while increasing the volume of the
amygdala (Lupien et al., 2009). Because amyg-
dalar activity is associated with stress and fear
reactions, and the hippocampus plays a moderat-
ing role on amygdalar activity, the results of
chronic stress may produce hypervigilance and
overly labile affective reactions.
Inammation
Normally, cortisol acts to reduce inammation
in the bodys tissues, but a paradoxical conse-
quence of glucocorticoid resistance is that cortisol
loses its ability to stem inammation, so that levels
of cortisol can be high simultaneously with
relatively high levels of proinammatory cytokines
(Silverman & Sternberg, 2012). One likely candi-
date for the creation of DN is chronic, low-grade
6 COHEN
inammation. In an extensive review article,
Slavich and Irwin (2014) made a convincing
case that stressful events lead to increased levels of
inammation driven by proinammatory cytokines
and that this systemic inammation can, in turn,
produce all the common symptoms of depression.
It may be possible for ones level of
inammation to be too low to produce diagnos-
able depression and yet high enough to alter ones
mood. This possibility was supported by the
results of Eisenberger et al. (2009), who injected
half their participants with an endotoxin in order
to elevate proinammatory cytokines. Compared
to the placebo group, the endotoxin group
exhibited a signicant increase in self-reported
depressed mood 2 hr after the injection. Data
from an fMRI scan were collected at that time,
while the participants were subjected to social
exclusion during a computer game. During
social exclusion, the endotoxin participants who
had higher increases in one proinammatory
cytokine (i.e., interleukin6) also had greater
activity in their AI. In the females only, greater
interleukin6 increases were also associated
with greater increases in activity in the dACC.
If inammation can produce a depressed
mood, it follows that anti-inammatory medica-
tions should be able to reduce depressive
symptoms, and in a systematic review and
meta-analysis, this is what Köhler et al. (2014)
found. However, it is important to bear in mind
that inammation is only one of the conditions
that can lead to depression, so anti-inammatory
medications may not be helpful for depressed
people who have little inammation.
It is also important to note that inammation
can increase pain sensitivity. In their review of the
hyperalgesia caused by inammation, Watkins
and Maier (2000) suggested that increased pain
sensitivity is adaptive for healing, as it leads to
sicknessbehaviors that protect the body from
further damage. These authors discussed several
mechanisms to explain why peripheral inam-
mation commonly leads to neuroinammation
involving the brain and spinal cord. The resulting
vague malaise may be attributed and therefore
labeled in different ways depending on ones
situation: for example, as loneliness, if one feels
deprived specically of social interactions;
nostalgia, if yearning for the good old days;
boredom, if one feels certain that changing
activities will bring relief; or, perhaps, a general
feeling of dissatisfaction with ones life.
Muscle Tension
Another likely source of DN is neural input
from chronically elevated levels of muscle
tension, which are especially prominent among
those diagnosed with generalized anxiety disor-
der. In their review of the association between
muscle tension and generalized anxiety disorder,
Pluess et al. (2009) suggested, among other
possibilities, that “… muscle tension may be a
way of coping with excess arousal caused by
anxiety(p. 8). Goldstein (1965) recorded both
muscle tension as well as autonomic responses to
white noise in groups of psychiatric patients with
different diagnoses. She found the largest increase
in skeletal muscle tension in the depressed patients.
It is common to tense our muscles in antici-
pation of a predictable pain, such as an injection
(Kyle & McNeil, 2014), or a psychological
stressor, and this may be the simplest way we can
voluntarily create a slight amount of discomfort in
a controllable way to distract from the upsetting
stimulation we know is imminent. It is well
known that many people maintain considerable
levels of unnecessary muscle tension, which tend
to increase general arousal (Nielson et al., 1996),
as well as potentially making some people feel
generally uncomfortable.
Visceral Sources
The activation of the sympathetic nervous
system produces changes in blood ow toward
skeletal muscles and away from visceral organs,
such as those of the gastrointestinal tract.
Gastrointestinal complaints are commonly asso-
ciated with anxiety disorders and may, at lower
levels, contribute to ones level of DN.
How Common Is DN in the Human
Population?
This is a key question for my theory, because if
DN is to play a large role in producing a mental
experience as common as boredom, it must be
common as well. First, it is important to note that
there is widespread agreement that an experience
can only be labeled as boredom if it is unpleasant
and if the mental pain involved is fairly mild.
A moderate or severe experience of mental pain,
regardless of the situation in which it occurs,
would more likely be labeled as anxiety, depres-
sion, or, perhaps, existential boredom.
MENTAL PAIN AND DIFFUSE NOCICEPTION 7
Next, I suggest that even a very mild level of
DN can produce an overreaction in terms of
mental pain if negative emotions are evoked
because one feels trapped and resents being stuck
in a boring situation. Finally, symptoms of anxiety
and depression, including those that do not rise to
the level of a clinical diagnosis, are known to be
quite prevalent in developed countries, and these
symptoms are generally associated with physio-
logical changes, including increases in general
arousal, muscle tension, and visceral disturbances.
Thus, I propose that persistent mild physiological
disturbances are likely to be quite prevalent in
modern societies.
Unconscious and Preconscious Nociception
Depending on its intensity, nociception, whether
it is diffuse or localized, can be kept out of
awareness by distraction, and some nociception can
serve an important function without ever entering
conscious awareness.
Unconscious Nociception
Baliki and Apkarian (2015) contended that
much of nociception occurs without conscious
awareness and yet plays an important role in the
preservation of our bodily integrity:
The primary reason I dget in my chair while writing
this article is because nociceptors innervating my skin,
muscle, and bone command that my posture needs
adjustment. Whereas proprioceptors provide (conscious,
but usually habituated) information about the location
and position of my body in space, nociceptors provide
inputs that protect my body from injury. As a result,
the nociceptive control of behavior routinely occurs in
the absence of consciously perceived pain, rendering it
subconscious.(p. 475)
However, note that later in their article, Baliki
and Apkarian refer to unconscious nociception,
so they appear to be using the terms subconscious
and unconscious interchangeably, which is not
unusual. Moreover, they are clearly not using
these terms in the psychoanalytic sense of
experiences that have been actively repressed.
Preconscious Nociception
Freud (1989) drew a useful distinction between
mental activity that is repressed and therefore
stuck in the unconscious as opposed to activity
that is not part of ones awareness at the moment
but could easily become conscious; he referred to
the latter mental processes as being preconscious.
Dehaene et al. (2006) redened the preconscious in
more modern terms as “… a neural process that
potentially carries enough activation for conscious
access but is temporarily buffered in a nonconscious
store because of a lack of top-down attentional
amplication (for example, owing to transient
occupancy of the central workspace system)
(p. 207). A common example of sensory informa-
tion that moves readily from the conscious to the
preconscious is the sound of a motor that drones
steadily and is then noticed only when it stops. With
respect to bodily feelings, you can notice the feeling
of your clothing touching your skin or the feeling of
your body in contact with the chair you are sitting
on, but unless there is some discomfort or you are
askedtopayattentiontothose feelings, you will not
notice these preconscious sensations.
In fact, even somewhat uncomfortable bodily
feelings will fade into the preconscious if you are
sufciently distracted and thus become precon-
scious nociception. Garcia-Larrea and Bastuji
(2018) pointed out that “… the combined activity
in the sensory-specic and second-order networks
is crucial to ensure the passage from pre-conscious
nociception to conscious pain(p. 194). However,
as in the case of peripheral vision,it is reasonable to
suppose that some mental activity in the precon-
scious may be vaguely perceived and that some
preconscious activity may be close enough to the
border of consciousness to have someeffect on our
behavior as well as our feelings. Sensing that DN
is in the background could motivate people to
continue to engage in their preferred distractions.
I will return to the important role of distractions
shortly.
That Which Reduces Physical Pain Tends to
Reduce Psychological Pain
Pain-Relieving Substances
Any substance that has pain-reducing proper-
ties when entering the body will reduce DN as
Ihavedened it, and, if my theory is correct, it will
reduce boredom as well. Common experience
shows that people are rarely bored when under the
inuence of alcohol, marijuana, opiates, or other
strong pain relievers, and that escape from boredom
is often cited as a reason for ingesting those
substances. Although I know of no research on the
8 COHEN
effects of pain relievers on boredom, there are
studies demonstrating the effects of several pain
relievers on other sources of mental pain. Given
that psychological pain is associated with cortical
activation that overlaps a good deal with the
activation produced by nociception, such results
should not be surprising.
Even a pain reliever as mild as acetaminophen
has been shown to reduce the psychological pain
of social rejection. In one eld study, half the
participants were randomly assigned to take two
daily doses of acetaminophen for 3 weeks, while
the other half took placebos (DeWall et al., 2010).
Social pain decreased signicantly over the
course of the 3 weeks for the acetaminophen
group but remained at for the placebo group.
That nding was conrmed in a laboratory
setting, in which social rejection was produced
via a computer game, manipulated to make it
appear that the participant is being excluded by
the other, virtualplayers (Fung & Alden, 2017).
Participants randomly assigned to take acetamino-
phen rather than a placebo pill reported signi-
cantly less social pain. Using the same computer
game in a study of habitual marijuana users, more
frequent use was associated with greater feelings
of acceptance, following exclusion in the game
(Deckman et al., 2014).
The widespread use of alcoholic beverages in
our society for the relief of mental pain is
consistent with the fact that alcohol has pain-
reducing properties, which have been conrmed
by experimental research (see Thompson et al.,
2017, for a review).
The Role of Distractions
In addition to substances that have a direct
effect on the nociceptive system, there are quite a
few types of distractions that can also relieve pain,
though the mechanism by which that occurs is
not always clear. One possible mechanism for
distraction follows from the spotlightmetaphor
of consciousness. If the focus of attention is
inherently limited and further narrowed by a
reaction to nociception, then shifting ones
attention to some engaging perception or activity
may displace the nociceptive sensations, moving
them from the conscious to the preconscious.
However, there is evidence that distracting
activities may have direct neural effects in terms
of the downregulation of nociceptive signals.
Even physical pain can be a distraction from
mental pain, as described next.
Controllable Physical Pain Can Be Preferred
to (Uncontrollable) Mental Pain
The results of one of the multiple studies
included in Wilson et al. (2014) gained a great
deal of attention in the popular press because in
that study some of the participants who were
simply asked to entertain themselves only by
thinking for 15 min, after being deprived of other
means of distraction, self-administered electric
shocks to themselvesshocks that they had
stated previously they would pay to avoid.
Because the Wilson et al.s (2014) study has
received some criticism (e.g., Fox, Thompson,
et al., 2014), it is important to note that the self-
administered shock nding was soon after
replicated in at least two other independent
studies (Havermans et al., 2015;Nederkoorn
et al., 2016), which employed longer and more
monotonous (i.e., boring) conditions.
A more recent study by Yusoufzai et al. (2022)
found that a boredom-inducing condition resul-
ted in a greater frequency and intensity of self-
administered shocks as compared to a neutral
control condition, and that there was a signicant
correlation between the boredom proneness of the
participant and both the frequency and intensity
of those shocks. Of note is that these effects were
signicant when analyzed separately for partici-
pants who reported at least one past incident in
which they engaged in nonsuicidal self-injury
(NSSI), such as cutting themselves, but not when
analyzing only the participants with no NSSI
history. Overall, more than half of the partici-
pants self-administered at least one shock rated
as painful, which included some of the non-NSSI
participants. Surprisingly, although the study
made no attempt to recruit for NSSI, about 55%
of their sample fell into the NSSI category.
Given that the shocks in these studies were
under the control of the participants and that
controllable pain is less aversive than uncon-
trollable pain, it is reasonable to infer that at least
some of these participants were using controlla-
ble pain to distract from the uncontrolled pain of
their boredom. In terms of a possible neural
mechanism for this effect, Wiech et al. (2006)
found that the reduced aversiveness of control-
lable pain may result from downregulation of
MENTAL PAIN AND DIFFUSE NOCICEPTION 9
nociception originating in the anterolateral prefron-
tal cortex, a cortical area associated with cognitive
reappraisal of emotion.
Mind Wandering
The vast majority of people do not deliberately
inict physical pain on themselves, and they do
not constantly experience mental pain. However,
in modern societies, it seems that most people do
engage almost continuously in distracting activi-
ties that may serve the function of keeping mental
pain from entering their awareness, or more
accurately, blocking nociceptive sensations that
would evoke mental pain were they allowed into
awareness. One line of evidence supporting this
assertion is the ubiquity of the subjective
phenomenon known as mind wandering, which
has been studied a great deal in recent years. Mind
wanderingiscommonlydened as mental content
that is independent of ones environment and
external sensations, referred to more formally as
stimulus-independent thought, and is unrelated to
whatever task one is performing, in which case it is
labeled as task-unrelated thought (TUT).
Experience sampling studies have shown that
mind wandering is a common phenomenon for
most people; a recent review estimated that the
average person spends 30%50% of their time
mind wandering (Kucyi et al., 2023). Therefore,
an article by Killingsworth and Gilbert (2010)
stirred up a good deal of controversy when they
claimed that mind wandering generally caused
people to be unhappy, concluding that “… ahuman
mind is a wandering mind, and a wandering mind is
an unhappy mind. The ability to think about what is
not happening is a cognitive achievement that
comes at an emotional cost(p. 932).
The results of the shockstudies discussed in
the previous section were essentially consistent
with the notion that people in general do not enjoy
thinking or just being alone with their thoughts.
However, to determine the causal connection
between mind wandering and negative affect,
Poerio et al. (2013) investigated their temporal
relationship and found that mind wandering was
not routinely followed by a negative mood, though
they did nd that a negative mood could evoke
mind wandering and that negative cognitions could
then exacerbate a negative mood. Analogous to the
self-administration of electric shocks when bored,
some people routinely dwell on negative thoughts
when mind wandering, which creates its own
mental pain. Although this may seem counterpro-
ductive and even masochistic, it is possible that
these individuals are shifting into a problem-
solving mode in a vain attempt to control their
mental pain. They may be trying to gure out the
origin of the pain in terms of past events and/or
planning ways to prevent its recurrence.
It seems paradoxical that regardless of whether
individuals enjoy thinking or nd it generally
unpleasant, it is well known that very few people
can voluntarily stop thinking completely for more
than a few seconds. The addictive quality of mind
wandering, whether in the form of pleasant
daydreaming or obsessive rumination, may be
explained by the consequences of the neural
activity that generates spontaneous thought, as
explained in the next section.
The Role of Neural Network Activity in
Reducing Mental Pain
The Default Mode Network
The neural activity that has been shown to be
largely responsible for mind wandering was rst
discovered when participants were asked merely
to rest in an MRI scanner while waiting for a task
to be given. The brain areas found to be most
active during these periods were referred to by
Raichle et al. (2001) as the DMN because it was
thought that these connected cortical areas become
active by default when no task or interesting
external stimulation is given. The main (hub)
regions of the DMN are generally considered to be
the posterior region of the cingulate cortex, along
with the adjacent precuneuscortex, and the ventro-
medial prefrontal cortex.
There are numerous studies demonstrating that
the DMN is activated when a participant is asked
to recall personal memories or make social
judgments (e.g., Andrews-Hanna et al., 2010;
Spreng et al., 2009). These results suggest that the
type of mental content that is most interesting, and
therefore most distracting, to the average human
waiting for a task in a boring environment consists
of autobiographical memories and thoughts con-
cerning social relationships. Given that the human
is a social animal, this could be expected.
Note that, as Raichle and Snyder (2007) found,
the DMNs generation of spontaneous mind
wandering consumes a surprisingly large amount
of energy, even during rest periods in a scanner,
10 COHEN
so it is reasonable to suspect that there is a strong
motivation prodding its activity. I suggest that,
whereas the DMN originally evolved to serve
several important functions, such as keeping track
of ones social relationships and status, as an
individuals stress increases, the DMN has been
increasingly appropriated for the purpose of
reducing mental pain by generating the spontane-
ous, distracting thoughts known as mind wander-
ing. Moreover, brain-scanning research on DMN
activity suggests a direct neural pathway by which
DMN activity can reduce nociception.
Danckert and Isacescu (2017) recorded neural
activity in the AI as well as the DMN, while
participants watched a boring video and an engaging
one. Not only did they nd the expected increase in
DMN activity during the boring condition, but they
also observed downregulation of the AI (i.e., DMN
and AI activity were anticorrelated). The opposite
pattern was found during the interesting video:
DMN activity decreased, and AI activity increased,
relative to a resting condition. These results suggest
that DMN activity can reduce the pain of boredom
directly by inhibiting AI activity, which plays a
major role in the neural chain that produces the
aversive experience of pain (DMN activity would be
much less needed while watching an interesting
video). Note that a more nuanced study found that
not all tasks have the same inhibitory effect on the
DMN; Ulrich et al. (2016) reported that DMN
activity was signicantly more depressed during a
owcondition (optimal task difculty), compared
to both boring (too easy) and overloading (too hard)
task conditions. Thus, if one has a task to perform but
it is not very engaging, DMN activity may not be
sufciently inhibited, allowing it to create TUTs.
Kucyi et al. (2013) found that participants who
tended to mind wander away from an experimen-
tally produced painful stimulus had stronger
structural (white matter) connections between the
DMN and the PAG of the midbrain, a major
processing area for nociceptive signals. Participants
exhibited greater functional connectivity between
those regions on the trials for which they reported
mind wandering, suggesting that the DMN was
capable of inhibiting nociception even in lower
brain areas. The pain-reducing consequences of
DMN activity may explain why this network is so
frequently found to be active during resting states in
an MRI scanner.
Note that any bodily function that can reduce
mental pain may be usurped for that purpose.
Ingesting food serves a vital biological function,
but it can also be overused in an effort to reduce
the mental pain of loneliness or mild depression,
for instance. DMN activity is particularly well-
suited as a pain reducer because it can be utilized
almost constantly, with apparently no build-up of
tolerance, and without dire physiological con-
sequences, though it does consume a good deal of
energy and can therefore be somewhat exhausting.
Cognitive Activity as a Pain Reducer
In many cases, mind wandering can reduce the
pain of boredom, but an engaging cognitive task,
which activates the central executive network,
can be even more effective against any type of
pain. Several studies have shown how cognitive
activity can directly inhibit nociception, in
addition to reducing activity in the DMN. For
example, Valet et al. (2004) scanned participants
receiving painful thermal stimulation (or only
warmth) while performing a demanding cognitive
(Stroop) task (or not). Subjective ratings of pain
unpleasantness were signicantly reduced during
cognitive distraction compared to no distraction.
This reduction in pain experience was accompanied
by overall reductions in the activity of various
cerebral pain processing regions and greater
connectivity between cingulofrontal cortical areas
and lower brain areas thought to play a role in
inhibiting physical pain signals (e.g., the PAG). The
authors concluded that their results supported the
notion that “… the prefrontal cortex exerts an
inhibitory control of sensory inputs to allow
cognitive networks to perform attention demanding
tasks(p. 405). This reduction in pain could help to
explain the addiction of some individuals to video
games, puzzle solving, and other mentally effortful
hobbies. Perhaps, DMN or central executive
network activity can crowd nociception out of
the spotlight of awareness, but even if not, there is
evidence that activity in those networks can reduce
nociceptive signals heading for the cortex directly
by inhibiting neural activity in lower pain proces-
sing centers.
Pleasurable Sensations Can Reduce Mental
Pain
It hardly needs to be stated that mental pain can
be reduced by activation of the pleasure/reward
circuit in the brain. Very diverse forms of pleasure
(e.g., eating delicious food; listening to a favorite
MENTAL PAIN AND DIFFUSE NOCICEPTION 11
piece of music; meeting a loved one) have been
found to stimulate the same cerebral circuit,
which relies on the activation of the nucleus
accumbens and ventral palladium and reaches its
apex in a region of the orbitofrontal cortex
(Berridge & Kringelbach, 2013,2015). Given
that pleasurable feelings can drown out mild
feelings of pain, it is easy to understand why any
activity that activates the reward system, such as
eating (especially comfort food), sex, gambling,
or even shopping, can easily become psychologi-
cally addicting, to the extent that the activity in
question is successful in greatly reducing ones
mental pain.
When All Distractions Fail
In the absence of successful distraction, DN
can shift from the preconscious to conscious
awareness, at which time it can trigger the cortical
activity that creates the aversive aspect of pain.
Being forced to perform tedious tasks or watch
monotonous videos for a lab experiment may
render mind wandering as the only available
distraction, and research shows that it is not a
strong enough distraction to prevent the feeling of
boredom for most people. However, even when in
daily life better distractions are availablefor
example, a smartphone or tablet is handyan
individual may react to the onset of boredom pain
with a negative emotion. For example, one is
stuck in trafc or on a long checkout line, starts to
feel the pain, and gets upset or angry over being
trapped. The negative emotion may make it difcult
to successfully engage in distraction so that the
boredom persists, as does the resentment over ones
situation. If one is already experiencing a negative
emotion before getting stuck in a boring situation,
the pain of boredom would only exacerbate the
negative affect.
The Role of Mental Attitudes in Reducing
Pain
Our own interpretations of our bodily feelings
can play a major role in reducing or amplifying
the unpleasantness of our pain. For example, if
you had exercised vigorously the day before or
performed some manual labor and then woke up
feeling some muscle pains, these might well serve
as reminders of accomplishing a desired goal and
therefore may even be felt as somewhat pleasurable.
Wake up with the very same pains but no ready
explanation for them, and you may become alarmed
that you have the u or some other disease. These
concerns could lead to a greater focus on those
muscle sensations and even a neural facilitation of
the pain signals. Similarly, the heat of a sauna or the
sun on our skin can be pleasurable if it is a sensation
that we have been seeking, but not if it is being
imposed on us. These two opposing attitudes can be
referred to as sensory intake (acceptance) and
sensory rejection (Williams et al., 1975).
The Placebo Effect
Changing another persons attitude toward
their bodily sensations can have a remarkably
large effect on the degree of pain they experience,
and this applies to mental, as well as physical,
pain. This change in attitude is surprisingly easy
to accomplish in most people via the placebo
effect. Even just the expectation of pain relief is
sufcient to activate some of the brains pain-
reducing systems. Thus far, I have discussed the
way that neocortical activity can have an
inhibitory effect on the activity of nociceptive
processing areas in the lower regions of the brain.
However, there is a good deal of evidence that
reductions in pain perception due to changes in
expectations, such as occur with the placebo effect,
are at least partially mediated by the secretion of
endorphins (see Tracey, 2010, for a review).
Endorphins seem to play a major role in producing
the runners highthat, for many people, is
generated by prolonged vigorous exercise. Much
of the evidence in favor of endorphins comes from
studies in which naloxone, which blocks opiate
receptors, was used to diminish, or even eliminate,
placebo effects.
The Effects of Mindfulness and Acceptance
Mindfulness-based stress reduction (Kabat-
Zinn, 2013) and acceptance and commitment
therapy (Hayes et al., 2006), both of which
incorporate mindfulness meditation techniques,
have helped to spur research on the use of
acceptance strategies for the reduction of physical
pain. A recent laboratory study (Haspert et al.,
2020) conrmed the benets of acceptance
strategy instructions (e.g., allow in any experi-
ence without further evaluation) relative to a
control condition in which participants were
asked to just sense the thermal pain applied to
12 COHEN
their forearms without employing any strategy to
deal with it. These authors found that an attitude
of acceptance signicantly decreased both the
subjective intensity and unpleasantness of the
heat stimulation, relative to control trials.
Gard et al. (2012) scanned the brains of experi-
enced practitioners of mindfulness (Vipassana)
and control participants while they received
electric shocks under two conditions: attending
to the sensation mindfully or not (baseline).
Relative to baseline, the mindfulness practitioners
experienced signicantdecreasesinpainunpleas-
antness, while the controls did not. Their fMRI
results suggested that mindfulness does not use
executive control to mitigate pain but rather allows
ones attention to focus on and fully process (i.e.,
accept) the potentially painful sensations. That is,
mindfulness produced pain modulation through a
mechanism different from that evoked by other
cognitive manipulations, including the use of
placebos.
A more direct comparison of the pain-reducing
mechanisms of mindfulness and placebo condi-
tions was conducted by Zeidan et al. (2015), who
scanned their participantscortical activity during
painful thermal stimulation after they had com-
pleted 4 days of either mindfulness training or
practice using a placebo cream at the stimulation
site. Meditation produced a signicantly greater
reduction in pain intensity and, especially, unpleas-
antness than the placebo. Compared to the placebo
condition, meditation was associated with greater
activity in the orbitofrontal cortex and AI and
reduced activity in lower level pain processing areas
(thalamus and periaqueductal gray). In contrast to
meditation, the placebo condition was associated
with greater activity in the DMN and reduced
activity in the posterior insula and secondary
somatosensory cortex.
Zeidan et al. (2016) followed up their previous
study by using naloxone to block any placebo
effects mediated by endorphins. Participants trained
in mindfulness meditation were compared with a
book listening control group in terms of pain ratings
to thermal stimulation. Half of each group was
given a large intravenous dose of naloxone during
pain testing while the other half received an inactive
saline solution. Both meditation groups gave
signicantly lower ratings in pain intensity and
unpleasantness during meditation than at baseline;
in fact, there was virtually no difference between the
meditators given naloxone and those given saline.
For both control groups, there was actually a slight
increase in pain ratings. These results allowed the
authors to conclude that the pain reduction induced
by mindfulness, with its acceptance of the poten-
tially painful sensations, did not rely on the
secretion of endorphins.
The Effects of Increased Interoceptive
Awareness
There has been a great deal of research in recent
years on the topic of interoception. Carvalho and
Damasio (2021) described the interoceptive
nervous system as “… a large collection of
neural structures (some viscerosensory, some
somatosensory, some autonomic, some periph-
eral, some central) that cooperate to produce a
real-time map of the homeostatic state of the
body(p. 2). Fischer et al. (2017) found that
training in a body-scan form of meditation
improved the accuracy of interoception, as mea-
sured by a heart-rate detection task. Wu et al. (2022)
also found that mindfulness training improved
interoceptive accuracy, as well as reducing negative
mood. Importantly, they found that the effect of
increased mindfulness on reduced negative mood
was fully mediated by the improvement in intero-
ceptive accuracy.
Acceptance of internal sensations involves
greater processing of the sensory dimension of
these stimuli, which can be expected to result in
more neural connections in the part of the brain
doing the processing; in the case of interoception,
that area is the insular cortex. In addition to the
changes in insular activity associated with
meditation, one of the most consistent ndings
with respectto structural brain differences between
meditators and nonmeditators is the greater gray
matter concentration in the insular cortex of
meditators (e.g., Hölzel et al., 2008). In a review
article, Fox, Nijeboer, et al. (2014) pointed out
that: “… the studies reporting insula differences
involved practitioners with an intensive, explicit
focus on body awareness, including attention to
body posture, respiration, ambient tactile sensa-
tions, temperature sensations, etc.(p. 61).
That an attitude of acceptance can reduce the
pain experience is consistent with the possibility
that the neural activity underlying the aversive
aspect of pain is based on a mobilization of the
brains resources to eliminate the source of the
seemingly threatening stimuli (i.e., sensory
rejection). Consequently, there is a narrowing
MENTAL PAIN AND DIFFUSE NOCICEPTION 13
of the eld of attention as activity relevant to
eliminating pain is prioritized, and this narrowed
focus may well enhance the unpleasantness of the
pain experience. That acceptance reduces mental,
as well as physical, pain is supported by a great
deal of meditation research demonstrating reduc-
tions in negative affect and improvements in
mood (see Sedlmeier et al., 2012, for a review).
Individual Differences in Boredom,
Neuroticism, and Interoceptive Accuracy
People vary a great deal with respect to how
easily they can become bored. This difference has
been quantied by several scales of boredom
proneness that have been developed in recent
years (e.g., Vodanovich & Watt, 2015). The wide
variation in boredom proneness found would
seem to be difcult to explain in terms of the
strength of each persons exploratory drive. One
would also have to explain why boredom proneness
is so highly correlated with neuroticism (e.g.,
Mercer-Lynn et al., 2013). First measured quantita-
tively by Eysenck (1983), neuroticism (sometimes
referred to as the opposite of emotional stability) is
considered to be an important personality trait
(McCrae, 1991). Moreover, boredom proneness
has been shown to be associated with various
psychopathologies (Sommers & Vodanovich,
2000), and Seiler et al. (2023) found even stronger
correlations between state boredom and measures
of mild psychopathology in mentally healthy
participants than they did using boredom proneness.
In addition to proposing that DN is a major
contributor to the mental pain of boredom, I would
also suggest that relatively high levels of DN
contribute to feelings of anxiety and depression
and thus add to ones emotional instability. This
possibility could explain the high correlations
between measures of boredom and neuroticism.
If indeed DN plays a role in neuroticism, a
connection between interoceptive ability and self-
reports of anxiety and depression could be
expected. Critchley et al. (2004) tested 13 of their
participants with a heart-beat detection task and
asked them to ll out standard anxiety and
depression surveys. They found that:
Across subjects, anxiety score correlated with intero-
ceptive accuracy during [fMRI] scanning. (Pearson
R=0.64, P<0.05). Relative interoceptive accuracy
tended to correlate with depressive symptoms (R=0.48,
P=0.09) and trait ratings of negative affective
experience (R=0.51, P=0.08). (p. 190)
The Assumptions and Explanatory Power of
the DN Concept
The theory of mental pain and boredom I am
proposing rests on the admittedly speculative
assumption that the bodies of most people produce
some chronic level of DN, based on the various
physiological changes produced by past stressors.
I cannot prove that this is the case, but I have tried
to demonstrate that it is a plausible assumption.
The power of this theory arises from its ability to
explain a wide swath of common human experi-
ences, as well as a great deal of recent research, in a
parsimonious way, accounting for these phenom-
ena by means of well-known neural and hormonal
mechanisms. The main phenomena I have endeav-
ored to explain, at least partially, include the
following:
1. The ubiquitous and persistent occurrence
of mind wandering, and the difculty most
people have when trying to stop thinking.
2. The current addiction to social media,
video and smartphone games, and other
easily accessible distractions.
3. The common presence of mild mental pain
when people are deprived of their usual
distractions.
4. Individual differences in boredom prone-
ness and neuroticism as a function of ones
level of DN are moderated by ones skill at
coping strategies and emotional regulation.
5. The stability of neuroticism as a trait and,
conversely, the stability referred to as the
happiness setpoint(Cummins et al., 2014).
Please note that I would not contend that the
theory I am proposing explains any of these
phenomena completely or even almost completely.
However, I do believe that the possible inuence
DN has on human experience and behavior should
not be overlooked if we want to reach a full
understanding of these phenomena. What remains
to be explained is why the effects of stress are so
common in modern societies, and why there is
evidence of a growing level of feelings of stress,
anxiety, and depression, especially in young people.
Why Is DN so Prevalent in the Human
Population?
I mentioned earlier the ndings that point to a
relationship between even low levels of chronic
14 COHEN
inammation and feelings of sadness or depressed
mood. Unfortunately, this relationship has its roots
in the earliest stages of human development. In fact,
there is evidence that elevated stress hormones can
affect the fetus in utero. Although glucocorticoids
play a critical role in normal fetal development,
a high degree of maternal stress can lead to
abnormally high levels of cortisol and related stress
hormones in the fetal bloodstream, thus repro-
grammingthe fetusstress system to become
hyperactive, which predisposes the later child to
various affective and behavioral disorders, as well
as metabolic diseases (Harris & Seckl, 2011). In this
manner, heightened stress reactivity can be passed
from generation to generation epigenetically. These
predispositions can be exacerbated by poor mater-
nal care in infancy, especially if the mother is
suffering from depression. Moreover, stress hor-
mones can continue to enter the infants body
during breast feeding. Thus, it is possible to imagine
stress accumulating over the generations.
There is a good deal of research demonstrating
that early life stress (e.g., extreme poverty, abuse,
or neglect) has long-range behavioral effects on
later childhood and adolescence, as well as higher
lifetime rates of depression (e.g., Evans &
English, 2002;Slavich & Irwin, 2014). Human
infants, compared to our primate cousins, are in a
totally helpless and dependent state for an
unusually long period of time. During the rst
few months of life and even the rst year or so,
babies need an enormous amount of attention to
avoid stress reactions from not getting their needs
met in a timely fashion, and even the best parental
efforts will undoubtedly fall short of the womb-
like environment infants still need.
Anthropologists have noted that a full-term
human infant is born as much as a year prematurely,
especially when compared to our primate cousins
(Gould, 1977). Although there are certainly
evolutionary advantages to having a large, deeply
convoluted brain, it remains to be seen whether our
intellectual advantages will outweigh the disad-
vantages of early stress that programs our neural
and hormonal systems to deal inefciently with
later stressors.
Proposed Experimental Tests of the Theory
A number of testable hypotheses can be derived
from the theory of boredom that I am proposing,
some of which parallel research cited in this article.
For example, just as an inammation-producing
drug has been shown to increase a depressed
mood, the same type of drug can be expected to
increase the boredom induced by a monotonous
experimental task or video, as well as increasing
mind wandering (i.e., TUTs) and DMN activity
during the task. Any drug or manipulation that can
produce a noticeable amount of DN should have
the effect of increasing the likelihood of boredom
during a monotonous task and increasing the
unpleasantness of any boredom that occurs.
Other possible ways to produce DN in the
laboratory may include raising the room temper-
ature just enough to be a bit uncomfortable,
having the participant wear somewhat uncom-
fortable clothing or assume a slightly uncomfort-
able sitting position. The key to a successful DN
manipulation would be to titrate the conditions
such that the participant is not able to localize the
discomfort or attribute it to the environment.
Conversely, just as a mild pain reliever (i.e.,
acetaminophen) has been shown to reduce the
unpleasant feeling of social exclusion, a pain-
relieving drug, as compared to a placebo, can
be expected to reduce the unpleasantness of an
experimental boredom induction. An anti-
inammatory drug, shown to reduce depression
in some individuals, may have a similar effect.
Alternatively, training in a body-scan meditation
that includes the cultivation of nonjudgmental
attention to, and acceptance of, even uncomfortable
bodily sensations, prior to a boredom induction,
should reduce self-reports of state boredom.
Training in progressive muscle relaxation, by
reducing excess muscle tension, could have
essentially the same ameliorating effect. In a two-
factor boredom induction experiment, one could
cross a DN manipulation with a pain-relieving drug
to test the effects of both independent variables and
their possible interaction.
Summary and Conclusions
In this article, I have attempted to present a
plausible and parsimonious theory to account for
most of the mild mental pain that most humans
seem to experience during boredom. The theory
rests on the assumption that the bodies of most
people, at least in modern societies, generate a
fairly constant level of DN that is intense enough
to evoke a mild degree of mental pain when it
enters conscious awareness. This level varies
from person to person, depending on their history
of stressful events (in terms of the intensity,
MENTAL PAIN AND DIFFUSE NOCICEPTION 15
frequency, and duration of those events), as well
as various personality and physiological factors
that affect the individuals resilience. The level of
DN is low enough in most people to be kept in the
preconscious almost continuously by the use of
coping strategies, often learned early in life, such
as engaging in successful distractions, including
thinking in the form of inner speech. However,
higher levels of DN are related to higher degrees
of boredom proneness and neuroticism. Negative
emotions can increase DN, and the pain evoked
by DN can evoke negative emotions or exacer-
bate ongoing ones.
In general, I view DN as a potential amplier of
normal human drives, to the extent that satisfying
those drives can keep DN in the preconscious.
Thus, as examples, the amplied hunger drive
becomes stress (over)eating; the amplied drive
toward social interaction can lead to overindul-
gence in social media; and the amplied explor-
atory drive can lead to extreme sensation seeking.
On an optimistic note, the research I have described
on the benets of an attitude of acceptance toward
all of ones bodily and mental feelings suggests the
possibility that training ones introspective ability
can reduce negative reactions to nociception and
may ultimately break the vicious cycle that
maintains ones chronic level of DN.
Finally, it has been well established that various
regular meditative practices increase the trait of
mindfulness (e.g., Kiken et al., 2015), which in
turn is negatively related to boredom proneness
and neuroticism. Regular practice of these
methods holds the promise of helping us to raise
our happiness setpoint and lower our neuroticism.
Ironically, the boredom most people feel whenrst
sitting to meditate tends to steer them away from
a practice that could reduce their proneness
to boredom (Osin & Turilina, 2022). A fuller
understanding of why mindfulness practices may
produce benets in the long-term may help to
encourage this practice.
References
Andrews-Hanna, J. R., Reidler, J. S., Huang, C., &
Buckner, R. L. (2010). Evidence for the default
networks role in spontaneous cognition. Journal of
Neurophysiology,104(1), 322335. https://doi.org/
10.1152/jn.00830.2009
Baliki, M. N., & Apkarian, A. V. (2015). Nociception,
pain, negative moods, and behavior selection.
Neuron,87(3), 474491. https://doi.org/10.1016/j
.neuron.2015.06.005
Bench, S. W., & Lench, H. C. (2013). On the function
of boredom. Behavioral Sciences,3(3), 459472.
https://doi.org/10.3390/bs3030459
Berridge, K. C., & Kringelbach, M. L. (2013).
Neuroscience of affect: Brain mechanisms of pleasure
and displeasure. Current Opinion in Neurobiology,
23(3), 294303. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.conb.2013
.01.017
Berridge, K. C., & Kringelbach, M. L. (2015). Pleasure
systems in the brain. Neuron,86(3), 646664. https://
doi.org/10.1016/j.neuron.2015.02.018
Biro, D. (2010). Is there such a thing as psychological
pain? And why it matters. Culture, Medicine, and
Psychiatry,34(4), 658667. https://doi.org/10.1007/
s11013-010-9190-y
Bräscher, A. K., Becker, S., Hoeppli, M. E., &
Schweinhardt, P. (2016). Different brain circuitries
mediating controllable and uncontrollable pain. The
Journal of Neuroscience,36(18), 50135025. https://
doi.org/10.1523/JNEUROSCI.1954-15.2016
Carvalho, G. B., & Damasio, A. (2021). Interoception
and the origin of feelings: A new synthesis. BioEssays,
43(6), Article e2000261. https://doi.org/10.1002/bies
.202000261
Chapman, W. P., Arrowood, J. G., & Beecher, H. K.
(1943). The analgetic effects of low concentrations
of nitrous oxide compared in man with morphine
sulphate. The Journal of Clinical Investigation,22(6),
871875. https://doi.org/10.1172/JCI101461
Columbia University Neurosurgery. (n.d.). Cingulotomy.
Retrieved August 22, 2022, from https://www.neuro
surgery.columbia.edu/patient-care/treatments/cingu
lotomy
Craig, A. D. (2003). A new view of pain as a
homeostatic emotion. Trends in Neurosciences,
26(6), 303307. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0166-
2236(03)00123-1
Critchley, H. D., Wiens, S., Rotshtein, P., Ohman, A., &
Dolan, R. J. (2004). Neural systems supporting
interoceptive awareness. Nature Neuroscience,7(2),
189195. https://doi.org/10.1038/nn1176
Cummins, R. A., Li, N., Wooden, M., & Stokes, M.
(2014). A demonstration of set-points for subjective
wellbeing. Journal of Happiness Studies,15(1),
183206. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10902-013-9444-9
Danckert, J., & Isacescu, J. (2017). The bored brain:
Insular cortex and the default mode network.
PsyArXiv. https://doi.org/10.17605/osf.io/aqbcd
Deckman, T., DeWall, C. N., Way, B., Gilman, R., &
Richman, S. (2014). Can marijuana reduce social
pain? Social Psychological and Personality Science,
5(2), 131139. https://doi.org/10.1177/1948550613
488949
Dehaene, S., Changeux, J. P., Naccache, L., Sackur, J.,
& Sergent, C. (2006). Conscious, preconscious, and
subliminal processing: A testable taxonomy. Trends
in Cognitive Sciences,10(5), 204211. https://doi.org/
10.1016/j.tics.2006.03.007
16 COHEN
DeWall, C. N., Macdonald, G., Webster, G. D.,
Masten, C. L., Baumeister, R. F., Powell, C.,
Combs, D., Schurtz, D. R., Stillman, T. F., Tice,
D. M., & Eisenberger, N. I. (2010). Acetaminophen
reduces social pain: Behavioral and neural evi-
dence. Psychological Science,21(7), 931937.
https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797610374741
Eisenberger, N. I. (2012). The pain of social
disconnection: Examining the shared neural under-
pinnings of physical and social pain. Nature Reviews
Neuroscience,13(6), 421434. https://doi.org/10
.1038/nrn3231
Eisenberger, N. I., Inagaki, T. K., Rameson, L. T.,
Mashal, N. M., & Irwin, M. R. (2009). An fMRI
study of cytokine-induced depressed mood and
social pain: The role of sex differences. NeuroImage,
47(3), 881890. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuroima
ge.2009.04.040
Evans, G. W., & English, K. (2002). The environment of
poverty: Multiple stressor exposure, psychophysio-
logical stress, and socioemotional adjustment. Child
Development,73(4), 12381248. https://doi.org/10
.1111/1467-8624.00469
Eysenck, H. J. (1983). Psychophysiology and person-
ality: Extraversion, neuroticism and psychoticism.
In A. Gale & J. A. Edwards, (Eds.), Individual
differences and psychopathology (pp. 1330).
Academic Press. https://doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-
12-273903-3.50007-9
Fischer, D., Messner, M., & Pollatos, O. (2017).
Improvement of interoceptive processes after an 8-
week body scan intervention. Frontiers in Human
Neuroscience,11, Article 452. https://doi.org/10
.3389/fnhum.2017.00452
Fox, K. C., Nijeboer, S., Dixon, M. L., Floman, J. L.,
Ellamil, M., Rumak, S. P., Sedlmeier, P., &
Christoff, K. (2014). Is meditation associated
with altered brain structure? A systematic review
and meta-analysis of morphometric neuroimaging
in meditation practitioners. Neuroscience and
Biobehavioral Reviews,43,4873. https://doi.org/
10.1016/j.neubiorev.2014.03.016
Fox, K. C., Thompson, E., Andrews-Hanna, J. R., &
Christoff, K. (2014). Is thinking really aversive? A
commentary on Wilson et al.sJust think: The
challenges of the disengaged mind.Frontiers in
Psychology,5, Article 1427. https://doi.org/10
.3389/fpsyg.2014.01427
Freud, S. (1989). The ego and the id (1923). TACD
Journal,17(1), 522. https://doi.org/10.1080/
1046171X.1989.12034344 (Original work pub-
lished 1923)
Fung, K., & Alden, L. E. (2017). Once hurt, twice shy:
Social pain contributes to social anxiety. Emotion,
17(2), 231239. https://doi.org/10.1037/emo00
00223
Garcia-Larrea, L., & Bastuji, H. (2018). Pain and
consciousness. Progress in Neuro-Psychopharma-
cology & Biological Psychiatry,87, 193199.
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pnpbp.2017.10.007
Gard, T., Hölzel, B. K., Sack, A. T., Hempel, H.,
Lazar, S. W., Vaitl, D., & Ott, U. (2012). Pain
attenuation through mindfulness is associated with
decreased cognitive control and increased sensory
processing in the brain. Cerebral Cortex,22(11),
26922702. https://doi.org/10.1093/cercor/bhr352
Goetz, T., Frenzel, A. C., Hall, N. C., Nett, U. E.,
Pekrun, R., & Lipnevich, A. A. (2014). Types of
boredom: An experience sampling approach.
Motivation and Emotion,38(3), 401419. https://
doi.org/10.1007/s11031-013-9385-y
Goldstein, I. B. (1965). The relationship of muscle
tension and autonomic activity to psychiatric dis-
orders. Psychosomatic Medicine,27(1), 3952.
https://doi.org/10.1097/00006842-196501000-00006
Gould, S. J. (1977). Ontogeny and phylogeny.
Belknap Press.
Goulden, N., Khusnulina, A., Davis, N. J., Bracewell,
R. M., Bokde, A. L., McNulty, J. P., & Mullins,
P. G. (2014). The salience network is responsible
for switching between the default mode network
and the central executive network: Replication from
DCM. NeuroImage,99, 180190. https://doi.org/10
.1016/j.neuroimage.2014.05.052
Harris, A., & Seckl, J. (2011). Glucocorticoids,
prenatal stress and the programming of disease.
Hormones and Behavior,59(3), 279289. https://
doi.org/10.1016/j.yhbeh.2010.06.007
Haspert, V., Wieser, M. J., Pauli, P., & Reicherts, P.
(2020). Acceptance-based emotion regulation re-
duces subjective and physiological pain responses.
Frontiers in Psychology,11, Article 1514. https://
doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2020.01514
Havermans, R. C., Vancleef, L., Kalamatianos, A., &
Nederkoorn, C. (2015). Eating and inicting pain
out of boredom. Appetite,85,5257. https://doi.org/
10.1016/j.appet.2014.11.007
Hayes, S. C., Luoma, J. B., Bond, F. W., Masuda, A., &
Lillis, J. (2006). Acceptance and commitment therapy:
Model, processes and outcomes. Behaviour Research
and Therapy,44(1), 125. https://doi.org/10.1016/j
.brat.2005.06.006
Hölzel, B. K., Ott, U., Gard, T., Hempel, H., Weygandt,
M., Morgen, K., & Vaitl, D. (2008). Investigation of
mindfulness meditation practitioners with voxel-
based morphometry. Social Cognitive and Affective
Neuroscience,3(1), 5561. https://doi.org/10.1093/
scan/nsm038
Jahn, A., Nee, D. E., Alexander, W. H., & Brown,J. W.
(2016). Distinct regions within medial prefrontal
cortex process pain and cognition. The Journal of
Neuroscience,36(49), 1238512392. https://doi.org/
10.1523/JNEUROSCI.2180-16.2016
Jensen, T. S., & Finnerup, N. B. (2014). Allodynia and
hyperalgesia in neuropathic pain: Clinical manifes-
tations and mechanisms. Lancet Neurology,13(9),
MENTAL PAIN AND DIFFUSE NOCICEPTION 17
924935. https://doi.org/10.1016/S1474-4422(14)
70102-4
Joffe, W. G., & Sandler, J. (1967). On the concept of
pain, with special reference to depression and
psychogenic pain. Journal of Psychosomatic
Research,11(1), 6975. https://doi.org/10.1016/
0022-3999(67)90058-X
Johansson, E., Xiong, H. Y., Polli, A., Coppieters, I.,
& Nijs, J. (2024). Towards a real-life understanding
of the altered functional behaviour of the default
mode and salience network in chronic pain: Are
people with chronic pain overthinking the meaning
of their pain? Journal of Clinical Medicine,13(6),
Article 1645. https://doi.org/10.3390/jcm13061645
Kabat-Zinn, J. (2013). Full catastrophe living: Using
the wisdom of your body and mind to face stress,
pain, and illness (Rev. ed.). Bantam Books.
Kiken, L. G., Garland, E. L., Bluth, K., Palsson, O. S.,
& Gaylord, S. A. (2015). From a state to a trait:
Trajectories of state mindfulness in meditation
during intervention predict changes in trait mind-
fulness. Personality and Individual Differences,81,
4146. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.paid.2014.12.044
Killingsworth, M. A., & Gilbert, D. T. (2010). A
wandering mind is an unhappy mind. Science,
330(6006), 932. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.11
92439
Köhler, O., Benros, M. E., Nordentoft, M., Farkouh,
M. E., Iyengar, R. L., Mors, O., & Krogh, J. (2014).
Effect of anti-inammatory treatment on depres-
sion, depressive symptoms, and adverse effects: A
systematic review and meta-analysis of randomized
clinical trials. JAMA Psychiatry,71(12), 13811391.
https://doi.org/10.1001/jamapsychiatry.2014.1611
Kross, E., Berman, M. G., Mischel, W., Smith, E. E.,
& Wager, T. D. (2011). Social rejection shares
somatosensory representations with physical pain.
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of
the United States of America,108(15), 62706275.
https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1102693108
Kucyi, A., Kam, J. W. Y., Andrews-Hanna, J. R.,
Christoff, K., & Whiteld-Gabrieli, S. (2023).
Recent advances in the neuroscience of spontaneous
and off-task thought: Implications for mental health.
Nature Mental Health,1(11), 827840. https://
doi.org/10.1038/s44220-023-00133-w
Kucyi, A., Salomons, T. V., & Davis, K. D. (2013).
Mind wandering away from pain dynamically
engages antinociceptive and default mode brain
networks. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences of the United States of America,110(46),
1869218697. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.13129
02110
Kyle, B. N., & McNeil, D. W. (2014). Autonomic
arousal and experimentally induced pain: A critical
review of the literature. Pain Research & Manage-
ment,19(3), 159167. https://doi.org/10.1155/2014/
536859
Legrain, V., Iannetti, G. D., Plaghki, L., & Mouraux,
A. (2011). The pain matrix reloaded: A salience
detection system for the body. Progress in Neuro-
biology,93(1), 111124. https://doi.org/10.1016/j
.pneurobio.2010.10.005
Lembke, A. (2021). Dopamine nation: Finding
balance in the age of indulgence. Dutton Books.
Lieberman, M. D., & Eisenberger, N. I. (2015). The
dorsal anterior cingulate cortex is selective for pain:
Results from large-scale reverse inference. Procee-
dings of the National Academy of Sciences of the
United States of America,112(49), 1525015255.
https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1515083112
Lupien, S. J., McEwen, B. S., Gunnar, M. R., & Heim,
C. (2009). Effects of stress throughout the lifespan
on the brain, behaviour and cognition. Nature
Reviews Neuroscience,10(6), 434445. https://
doi.org/10.1038/nrn2639
McCrae, R. R. (1991). The ve-factor model and its
assessment in clinical settings. Journal of
Personality Assessment,57(3), 399414. https://
doi.org/10.1207/s15327752jpa5703_2
Meagher, R. K., & Mason, G. J. (2012). Environmental
enrichment reduces signs of boredom in caged mink.
PLOS ONE,7(11), Article e49180. https://doi.org/10
.1371/journal.pone.0049180
Mee, S., Bunney, B. G., Reist, C., Potkin, S. G., &
Bunney, W. E. (2006). Psychological pain: A review
of evidence. Journal of Psychiatric Research,40(8),
680690. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jpsychires.2006
.03.003
Melzack, R., & Casey, K. L. (1968). Sensory,
motivational, and central control determinants of
pain: A new conceptual model. In D. L. Kenshalo
(Ed.), The skin senses (pp. 423435). Thomas.
Mercer-Lynn, K. B., Hunter, J. A., & Eastwood, J. D.
(2013). Is trait boredom redundant? Journal of
Social and Clinical Psychology,32(8), 897916.
https://doi.org/10.1521/jscp.2013.32.8.897
Nagasako, E. M., Oaklander, A. L., & Dworkin, R. H.
(2003). Congenital insensitivity to pain: An update.
Pain,101(3), 213219. https://doi.org/10.1016/
S0304-3959(02)00482-7
Nederkoorn, C., Vancleef, L., Wilkenhöner, A., Claes,
L., & Havermans, R. C. (2016). Self-inicted pain
out of boredom. Psychiatry Research,237,127132.
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.psychres.2016.01.063
Nielson, K. A., Radtke, R. C., & Jensen, R. A. (1996).
Arousal-induced modulation of memory storage
processes in humans. Neurobiology of Learning and
Memory,66(2), 133142. https://doi.org/10.1006/
nlme.1996.0054
Osin, E. N., & Turilina, I. I. (2022). Mindfulness
meditation experiences of novice practitioners in an
online intervention: Trajectories, predictors, and
challenges. Applied Psychology: Health and Well-
Being,14(1), 101121. https://doi.org/10.1111/ap
hw.12293
18 COHEN
Ploghaus, A., Becerra, L., Borras, C., & Borsook, D.
(2003). Neural circuitry underlying pain modulation:
Expectation, hypnosis, placebo. Trends in Cognitive
Sciences,7(5), 197200. https://doi.org/10.1016/
S1364-6613(03)00061-5
Pluess, M., Conrad, A., & Wilhelm, F. H. (2009).
Muscle tension in generalized anxiety disorder: A
critical review of the literature. Journal of Anxiety
Disorders,23(1), 111. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ja
nxdis.2008.03.016
Poerio, G. L., Totterdell, P., & Miles, E. (2013). Mind-
wandering and negative mood: Does one thing really
lead to another? Consciousness and Cognition,
22(4), 14121421. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog
.2013.09.012
Price, D. D., Harkins, S. W., & Baker, C. (1987).
Sensory-affective relationships among different
types of clinical and experimental pain. Pain,
28(3), 297307. https://doi.org/10.1016/0304-39
59(87)90065-0
Raichle, M. E., MacLeod, A. M., Snyder, A. Z.,
Powers, W. J., Gusnard, D. A., & Shulman, G. L.
(2001). A default mode of brain function.
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences
of the United States of America,98(2), 676682.
https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.98.2.676
Raichle, M. E., & Snyder, A. Z. (2007). A default
mode of brain function: A brief history of an
evolving idea. NeuroImage,37(4), 10831090.
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuroimage.2007.02.041
Sedlmeier, P., Eberth, J., Schwarz, M., Zimmermann,
D., Haarig, F., Jaeger, S., & Kunze, S. (2012). The
psychological effects of meditation: A meta-analy-
sis. Psychological Bulletin,138(6), 11391171.
https://doi.org/10.1037/a0028168
Seeley, W. W., Menon, V., Schatzberg, A. F., Keller,
J., Glover, G. H., Kenna, H., Reiss, A. L., &
Greicius, M. D. (2007). Dissociable intrinsic
connectivity networks for salience processing and
executive control. The Journal of Neuroscience,
27(9), 23492356. https://doi.org/10.1523/JNEURO
SCI.5587-06.2007
Seiler, J. P.-H., Zerr, K., Rumpel, S., & Tüscher, O.
(2023). High state boredom vastly affects psychiat-
ric inpatients and predicts their treatment duration.
Translational Psychiatry,13(1), Article 350. https://
doi.org/10.1038/s41398-023-02650-9
Silverman, M. N., & Sternberg, E. M. (2012).
Glucocorticoid regulation of inammation and its
functional correlates: From HPA axis to glucocor-
ticoid receptor dysfunction. Annals of the New York
Academy of Sciences,1261(1), 5563. https://
doi.org/10.1111/j.1749-6632.2012.06633.x
Slavich, G. M., & Irwin, M. R. (2014). From stress to
inammation and major depressive disorder: A
social signal transduction theory of depression.
Psychological Bulletin,140(3), 774815. https://
doi.org/10.1037/a0035302
Sommers, J., & Vodanovich, S. J. (2000). Boredom
proneness: Its relationship to psychological- and
physical-health symptoms. Journal of Clinical
Psychology,56(1), 149155. https://doi.org/10
.1002/(SICI)1097-4679(200001)56:1<149::AID-
JCLP14>3.0.CO;2-Y
Spreng, R. N., Mar, R. A., & Kim, A. S. N. (2009). The
common neural basis of autobiographical memory,
prospection, navigation, theory of mind, and the
default mode: A quantitative meta-analysis. Journal
of Cognitive Neuroscience,21(3), 489510. https://
doi.org/10.1162/jocn.2008.21029
Sridharan, D., Levitin, D. J., & Menon, V. (2008). A
critical role for the right fronto-insular cortex in
switching between central-executive and default-
mode networks. Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences,105(34), 1256912574.
https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0800005105
Thompson, T., Oram, C., Correll, C. U., Tsermentseli,
S., & Stubbs, B. (2017). Analgesic effects of
alcohol: A systematic review and meta-analysis of
controlled experimental studies in healthy partici-
pants. The Journal of Pain,18(5), 499510. https://
doi.org/10.1016/j.jpain.2016.11.009
Tracey, I. (2010). Getting the pain you expect:
Mechanisms of placebo, nocebo and reapprai-
sal effects in humans. Nature Medicine,16(11),
12771283. https://doi.org/10.1038/nm.2229
Ulrich, M., Keller, J., & Grön, G. (2016). Neural
signatures of experimentally induced ow experi-
ences identied in a typical fMRI block design with
BOLD imaging. Social Cognitive and Affective
Neuroscience,11(3), 496507. https://doi.org/10
.1093/scan/nsv133
Valet, M., Sprenger, T., Boecker, H., Willoch, F.,
Rummeny, E., Conrad, B., Erhard, P., & Tolle, T. R.
(2004). Distraction modulates connectivity of the
cingulo-frontal cortex and the midbrain during
painAn fMRI analysis. Pain,109(3), 399408.
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pain.2004.02.033
Vodanovich, S. J., & Watt, J. D. (2015). Self-report
measures of boredom: An updated review of the
literature. The Journal of Psychology: Interdisci-
plinary and Applied,150(2), 196228. https://
doi.org/10.1080/00223980.2015.1074531
Wang, G. C., Harnod, T., Chiu, T. L., & Chen, K. P.
(2017). Effect of an anterior cingulotomy on pain,
cognition, and sensory pathways. World Neuro-
surgery,102, 593597. https://doi.org/10.1016/j
.wneu.2017.03.053
Watkins, L. R., & Maier, S. F. (2000). The pain of
being sick: Implications of immune-to-brain com-
munication for understanding pain. Annual Review
of Psychology,51(1), 2957. https://doi.org/10
.1146/annurev.psych.51.1.29
Westgate, E. C., & Wilson, T. D. (2018). Boring
thoughts and bored minds: The MAC model of
boredom and cognitive engagement. Psychological
MENTAL PAIN AND DIFFUSE NOCICEPTION 19
Review,125(5), 689713. https://doi.org/10.1037/
rev0000097
Wiech, K., Kalisch, R., Weiskopf, N., Pleger, B.,
Stephan, K. E., & Dolan, R. J. (2006). Anterolateral
prefrontal cortex mediates the analgesic effect of
expected and perceived control over pain. The Journal
of Neuroscience,26(44), 1150111509. https://
doi.org/10.1523/JNEUROSCI.2568-06.2006
Williams, R. B., Jr., Bittker, T. E., Buchsbaum, M. S., &
Wynne, L. C. (1975). Cardiovascular and neurophys-
iologic correlates of sensory intake and rejection. I.
Effect of cognitive tasks. Psychophysiology,12(4),
427433. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1469-8986.1975
.tb00017.x
Wilson, T. D., Reinhard, D. A., Westgate, E. C.,
Gilbert, D. T., Ellerbeck, N., Hahn, C., Brown,
C. L., & Shaked, A. (2014). Just think: The
challenges of the disengaged mind. Science,
345(6192), 7577. https://doi.org/10.1126/science
.1250830
Woo, C. W., Koban, L., Kross, E., Lindquist, M. A.,
Banich, M. T., Ruzic, L., Andrews-Hanna, J. R., &
Wager, T. D. (2014). Separate neural representa-
tions for physical pain and social rejection. Nature
Communications,5(1), Article 5380. https://
doi.org/10.1038/ncomms6380
Wu, Q., Mao, X., Luo, W., Fan, J., Liu, X., & Wu, Y.
(2022). Enhanced interoceptive attention mediates
the relationship between mindfulness training and
the reduction of negative mood. Psychophysiology,
59(4), Article e13991. https://doi.org/10.1111/psyp
.13991
Yusoufzai, M. K., Vancleef, L., Lobbestael, J., &
Nederkoorn, C. (2022). Painfully bored: The role of
negative urgency and history of non-suicidal self-
injury in self-administering painful stimuli. Motivation
and Emotion,46(5), 689701. https://doi.org/10
.1007/s11031-022-09970-1
Zeidan, F., Adler-Neal, A. L., Wells, R. E., Stagnaro,
E., May, L. M., Eisenach, J. C., McHafe, J. G., &
Coghill, R. C. (2016). Mindfulness-meditation-
based pain relief is not mediated by endogenous
opioids. The Journal of Neuroscience,36(11),
33913397. https://doi.org/10.1523/JNEUROSCI
.4328-15.2016
Zeidan, F., Emerson, N. M., Farris, S. R., Ray, J. N.,
Jung, Y., McHafe, J. G., & Coghill, R. C. (2015).
Mindfulness meditation-based pain relief employs
different neural mechanisms than placebo and sham
mindfulness meditation-induced analgesia. The
Journal of Neuroscience,35(46), 1530715325.
https://doi.org/10.1523/JNEUROSCI.2542-15.2015
Received December 30, 2022
Revision received July 22, 2024
Accepted July 30, 2024
20 COHEN
ResearchGate has not been able to resolve any citations for this publication.
Article
Full-text available
Chronic pain is a source of substantial physical and psychological suffering, yet a clear understanding of the pathogenesis of chronic pain is lacking. Repeated studies have reported an altered behaviour of the salience network (SN) and default mode network (DMN) in people with chronic pain, and a majority of these studies report an altered behaviour of the dorsal ventromedial prefrontal cortex (vmPFC) within the anterior DMN. In this topical review, we therefore focus specifically on the role of the dorsal vmPFC in chronic pain to provide an updated perspective on the cortical mechanisms of chronic pain. We suggest that increased activity in the dorsal vmPFC may reflect maladaptive overthinking about the meaning of pain for oneself and one’s actions. We also suggest that such overthinking, if negative, may increase the personal “threat” of a given context, as possibly reflected by increased activity in, and functional connectivity to, the anterior insular cortex within the SN.
Article
Full-text available
Boredom is a ubiquitous, aversive human experience typically elicited by low information and monotony. Boredom can occur either as a transient mental state that prompts individuals to adapt their behavior to avoid monotony or as a temporally stable trait, describing a chronic susceptibility to feeling bored. Increased trait boredom was found to correlate with various psychopathologies and indicators of mental burden. However, the role of state boredom in psychopathological conditions and its implications for psychiatric treatment remain elusive. Here, we address this issue by investigating state boredom and trait boredom in a cohort of psychiatric inpatients and a healthy control cohort. We find that in both groups, state boredom, even more than trait boredom, shows remarkable associations with psychopathology. In the inpatient group, state boredom is implicated broadly in multiple mental disorders and shows an association with treatment in closed psychiatric wards. Furthermore, through statistical modeling, we find that high-state boredom during inpatient therapy is predictive of a longer therapy duration. Thus, we show that state boredom constitutes an indicator of mild and severe psychopathology in different mental disorders, affecting the outcome of psychiatric patients. Potential therapeutic interventions are discussed, aiming to enhance information flow in the brain in order to alleviate boredom in clinical settings.
Article
Full-text available
The current study aims to examine the causal effect of boredom on non-suicidal self-injury (NSSI), expanding prior experimental research by including an anger induction to compare to a boredom induction, and additionally measuring whether participants specifically seek painful stimulation. In a sample of mostly undergraduate students (N = 146), emotional state was manipulated through video induction, and NSSI behavior was simultaneously measured, operationalized through self-administration of electric shocks. Participants’ pain thresholds were measured beforehand. NSSI history and negative urgency were included as potential moderators. Results showed that boredom increased both frequency and intensity of self-administered electric shocks, especially in participants with an NSSI history. Negative urgency was not a significant moderator. No causal anger-NSSI link was found, possibly due to the anger induction not being sufficiently effective. Clinical implications are considered through suggestions of boredom coping skills training as an intervention strategy in NSSI populations.
Article
Full-text available
Background: The benefits of mindfulness interventions are well-known, but their challenges and individual differences in reactions to these challenges are much less clear. Methods: The study used a mixed-methods design to investigate the individual trajectories of daily experiences during meditation in a sample of novice volunteers participating in a 3-week, distance-based, guided meditation intervention (N = 175). Results: Multilevel modelling revealed individual differences in the change trajectories of the experiences of effort, meaning, and boredom during meditation, indicating that meditation gradually became less effortful, less boring, more interesting, and more important over the 3 weeks. The individual differences in the levels of these experiences and their change trends were associated with baseline differences in well-being, reflective processes, self-management, and self-control skills, as well as autonomous motivation to engage in the course. Conclusions: Individuals who are initially more autonomous and mindful find it easier to engage with online mindfulness interventions and draw more benefits from the process, whereas those with lower self-regulation skills or higher proneness to rumination are more likely to experience mindfulness as effortful and boring, and, eventually, to give it up.
Article
Full-text available
Acceptance-based regulation of pain, which focuses on the allowing of pain and pain related thoughts and emotions, was found to modulate pain. However, results so far are inconsistent regarding different pain modalities and indices. Moreover, studies so far often lack a suitable control condition, focus on behavioral pain measures rather than physiological correlates, and often use between-subject designs, which potentially impede the evaluation of the effectiveness of the strategies. Therefore, we investigated whether acceptance-based strategies can reduce subjective and physiological markers of acute pain in comparison to a control condition in a within-subject design. To this end, participants (N = 30) completed 24 trials comprising 10 s of heat pain stimulation. Each trial started with a cue instructing participants to welcome and experience pain (acceptance trials) or to react to the pain as it is without employing any regulation strategies (control trials). In addition to pain intensity and unpleasantness ratings, heart rate (HR) and skin conductance (SC) were recorded. Results showed significantly decreased pain intensity and unpleasantness ratings for acceptance compared to control trials. Additionally, HR was significantly lower during acceptance compared to control trials, whereas SC revealed no significant differences. These results demonstrate the effectiveness of acceptance-based strategies in reducing subjective and physiological pain responses relative to a control condition, even after short training. Therefore, the systematic investigation of acceptance in different pain modalities in healthy and chronic pain patients is warranted.
Article
The relationship between boredom proneness and health-symptom reporting was examined. Undergraduate students (N 5 200) completed the Boredom Proneness Scale and the Hopkins Symptom Checklist. A multiple analysis of covariance indicated that individuals with high boredomproneness total scores reported significantly higher ratings on all five subscales of the Hopkins Symptom Checklist (Obsessive–Compulsive, Somatization, Anxiety, Interpersonal Sensitivity, and Depression). The results suggest that boredom proneness may be an important element to consider when assessing symptom reporting. Implications for determining the effects of boredom proneness on psychological- and physical-health symptoms, as well as the application in clinical settings, are discussed. © 2000 John Wiley & Sons, Inc. J Clin Psychol 56: 149–155, 2000.
Article
Although accumulating evidence has revealed the effect of mindfulness training on the reduction of general stress and the improvement of mental well-being, the underlying mechanism remains unclear. In this study, we investigated whether interoceptive attention to respiratory signals plays a role. Healthy adults were randomly assigned to either receive an 8-week mindfulness training (n = 29) or inactive control (n = 28). The pre- and post-training self-reported states of negative mood were assessed together with an objective measure of interoceptive attention to respiration. Compared to the control group, mindfulness training led to a decrease in the level of negative mood and an increase in interoceptive sensitivity. Mediation analysis further showed that the effect of mindfulness training on the reduction of negative mood was fully mediated by increased interoceptive sensitivity. These results suggest that mindfulness training effectively alleviates negative mood by enhancing interoceptive attention to respiratory signals.
Article
Feelings are conscious mental events that represent body states as they undergo homeostatic regulation. Feelings depend on the interoceptive nervous system (INS), a collection of peripheral and central pathways, nuclei and cortical regions which continuously sense chemical and anatomical changes in the organism. How such humoral and neural signals come to generate conscious mental states has been a major scientific question. The answer proposed here invokes (1) several distinctive and poorly known physiological features of the INS; and (2) a unique interaction between the body (the ‘object’ of interoception) and the central nervous system (which generates the 'subject' of interoception). The atypical traits of the INS and the direct interactions between neural and non‐neural physiological compartments of the organism, neither of which is present in exteroceptive systems, plausibly explain the qualitative and subjective aspects of feelings, thus accounting for their conscious nature.