Content uploaded by Sean T. H. Lee
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Sean T. H. Lee on Nov 15, 2024
Content may be subject to copyright.
https://doi.org/10.1177/25152459241268249
Advances in Methods and
Practices in Psychological Science
October-December 2024, Vol. 7, No. 4,
pp. 1 –4
© The Author(s) 2024
Article reuse guidelines:
sagepub.com/journals-permissions
DOI: 10.1177/25152459241268249
www.psychologicalscience.org/AMPPS
ASSOCIATION FOR
PSYCHOLOGICAL SCIENCE
Creative Commons CC BY: This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 License
(https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/) which permits any use, reproduction and distribution of the work without further permission
provided the original work is attributed as specified on the SAGE and Open Access pages (https://us.sagepub.com/en-us/nam/open-access-at-sage).
Commentary
The conditions under which laypeople attribute knowl-
edge to protagonists have long been debated by experi-
mental philosophers (Colaço etal., 2014; Nagel etal.,
2013; Weinberg etal., 2001). Consider the case of “Dar-
rel,” who accurately recognizes the species of an animal
in the woods even though it was the only one of its kind
among many animals of an identical-looking species.
Responses to this so-called “Gettier-type” case have been
studied to examine whether laypeople consider luckily
true beliefs as constituting actual knowledge. In their
Experiment 1, Turri et al. (2015) compared knowledge
attributions in this version of the “Darrel” case to a ver-
sion in which his belief is a clear case of knowledge;
they found no difference between these conditions and
concluded that “a salient but failed threat to the truth of
a judgment does not significantly affect whether it is
viewed as knowledge” (p. 381). Hall etal. (2024) repli-
cated and extended Experiment 1 of Turri etal., testing
condition differences by using the Darrel case alongside
two other counterfeit-object Gettier-type cases in a large
multinational study. Hall etal. found that participants
were less likely to attribute knowledge to the protago-
nists when beliefs were only luckily true (i.e., the Gettier
conditions) than when the truth of the beliefs was not
under threat (i.e., the knowledge conditions). This sig-
nificant condition difference reported by Hall etal. stands
in contrast to the null result reported by Turri etal.
In their commentary on Hall etal., Buckwalter and
Friedman (2024) claimed that the replication should have
been interpreted as successful, argued that the research-
ers’ conclusions were incorrect, and implied that the
replication effort was misguided. As a subset of contribu-
tors to the Hall et al. replication, we appreciate the
opportunity to respond to their comment. Although we
recognize the potential for disagreement in the interpre-
tation of research results, Buckwalter and Friedman’s
critique ignored several key features of the research, and
many of their arguments and proposed interpretations
were already addressed by Hall etal. (2024). In response
to their comment, we (a) explain why Hall etal. did not
replicate all of the original findings, (b) emphasize how
1268249AMPXXX10.1177/25152459241268249Schmidt et al.Advances in Methods and Practices in Psychological Science
research-article2024
Corresponding Author:
Jordan Wagge, School of Psychology, Avila University, Kansas City,
Missouri
Email: jordan.wagge@avila.edu
A Response to a Comment
on Hall etal. (2024)
Kathleen Schmidt1, Gerald J. Haeffel2, Neil Levy3,4 ,
David Moreau5,6 , Sean T. H. Lee7, Erin M. Buchanan8,
Anthony J. Krafnick9, Martin Voracek10 , Gerit Pfuhl11,
Krystian Barzykowski12, Marta Kowal13 , and Jordan Wagge14
1Department of Psychology, Ashland University, Ashland, Ohio; 2Department of Psychology, University
of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, Indiana; 3Department of Philosophy, Macquarie University, Sydney,
Australia; 4Uehiro Centre for Practical Ethics, University of Oxford, Oxford, England; 5School of
Psychology, University of Auckland, Auckland, New Zealand; 6Centre for Brain Research, University
of Auckland, Auckland, New Zealand; 7School of Social and Health Sciences, James Cook University,
Singapore; 8Analytics, Harrisburg University of Science and Technology, Harrisburg, Pennsylvania;
9Department of Psychology, Dominican University, River Forest, Illinois; 10Department of Cognition,
Emotion, and Methods in Psychology, Faculty of Psychology, University of Vienna, Vienna, Austria;
11Department of Psychology, Norwegian University of Science and Technology, Trondheim, Norway;
12Institute of Psychology, Faculty of Philosophy, Jagiellonian University, Krakow, Poland; 13IDN
Being Human Lab - Institute of Psychology, University of Wrocław, Wrocław, Poland; and 14School of
Psychology, Avila University, Kansas City, Missouri
Keywords
epistemic intuitions, Gettier cases, knowledge, replication
Received 5/31/24; Revision accepted 7/1/24
2 Schmidt et al.
Hall etal. were accurate and nuanced in the description
and interpretation of their results, and (c) caution against
focusing on the mechanisms underlying a psychological
phenomenon before it is clearly established.
Different Statistical and Interpretive
Conclusions
Although Hall etal. (2024) found evidence for several
of the original claims of Turri etal. (2015), they did not
replicate one notable null result: Unlike Turri etal., they
observed a difference in knowledge attribution between
the Gettier condition and the knowledge control condi-
tion. Although small in magnitude, this difference was
identified robustly across three tested vignettes, different
measures of knowledge attribution, and multiple analy-
ses. Hall etal. further examined possible moderators,
none of which eliminated the condition difference that
Turri etal. failed to find. Given two studies that differ
on the statistical significance of their results, we contend
that the study with the larger, more diverse sample and
higher analytic power to detect differences is more likely
to yield valid, replicable, and generalizable results.
Because the difference between the aforementioned
conditions is absolutely central to the philosophical
debate over Gettier cases, and the experimental philo-
sophical literature has accordingly focused on it, we are
confident that Hall etal.’s failure to replicate the original
null result is an important contribution.
Nonetheless, Buckwalter and Friedman (2024) con-
cluded that the two discrepant findings were “basically
the same.” This assertion is based on their interpretation
of descriptive differences in the frequencies of knowl-
edge attributions between conditions and enables them
to generate a narrative (or, reframing) that would align
with that of Turri etal. (2015). However, Hall etal.’s
(2024) preregistered analysis plan did not include this
method of assessing the results. The purpose of prereg-
istration is to reduce researcher degrees of freedom and
to discourage exploratory analyses disguised as confir-
matory, especially those that support preferred narratives
(e.g., Nosek etal., 2018; Wicherts et al., 2016). In this
case, Hall etal. anticipated a null result aligned with the
original finding, conducted a prespecified analysis with
any data-driven changes transparently noted, detected a
nominally significant result, and reported those findings
accordingly. Based on these prespecified conditions and
consistent with the framework of null hypothesis signifi-
cance testing (NHST), we must state that Hall etal.’s
findings were different from those of the original study.
Although one can, and Hall etal. (2024) did, calculate
an effect size from the null result reported in Experiment
1 of Turri etal. (2015; i.e., odds ratio [OR] = 2.00, 95%
confidence interval [CI] = [0.77, 5.21]), interpreting the
results of the statistical test beyond a failure to reject the
null hypothesis would violate the logic of NHST (e.g.,
Frick, 1996). The null result merely indicates that Turri
etal. had insufficient evidence to support a claim of a
difference between conditions. Nonetheless, as Hall
etal. acknowledged, the effect they observed (i.e., OR =
1.86, 95% CI = [1.78, 1.94]) was similar in size to the
original. Accordingly, as both Hall etal. and Buckwalter
and Friedman (2024) pointed out, the large sample in
the replication study may be one explanation for the
difference in statistical conclusions. Lacking this insight,
Turri etal. concluded that knowledge attributions were
insensitive to the differences in Gettier and knowledge
conditions in their Experiment 1—a claim that was
not supported by the results of Hall etal. Nonetheless,
Buckwalter and Friedman suggested that the percentage
differences in the original, likely underpowered, Turri
etal. study should have been the sole criteria for replica-
tion rather than the statistical conclusions or interpreta-
tions therefrom. However, the CI of the original effect
is quite wide and includes effect sizes that would imply
a greater likelihood of knowledge attribution in the
knowledge condition than the Gettier condition (OR > 1),
a null result (OR = 1), and a greater likelihood of knowl-
edge attribution in the Gettier condition than the knowl-
edge condition (OR < 1); therefore, their results were
inconclusive. In contrast, the results from Hall etal. rep-
resent a clear, albeit small, Gettier-intuition effect. The
results of the original study simply cannot be classified
as “basically the same” as those presented by Hall etal.
Accurate and Nuanced
Contrary to Buckwalter and Friedman’s (2024) reading,
Hall etal. (2024) did not “claim to . . . show that people
deny knowledge to lucky agents” or “infer from this
finding that there is a common psychological tendency
to deny that true-by-luck beliefs are knowledge.” Rather,
Hall etal. accurately reported a nominally significant
condition difference, which they then interpreted accord-
ingly. For example, they stated the following:
This result did not correspond to that found by
Turri etal., who failed to detect a significant dif-
ference in knowledge attribution between these
two conditions . . . we did find effect sizes in the
same range as Turri etal. when directly comparing
like conditions; however, the null result did not
replicate.
Hall etal. (2024) further noted their sample’s baseline
skepticism (i.e., that a “notable number of participants
[43.41%; see Table 7] denied knowledge to protagonists
even in clear cases of justified true belief”) and for this
Advances in Methods and Practices in Psychological Science 7(4) 3
reason, were careful in their interpretation of the condi-
tion difference. Specifically, they acknowledged that
“Gettier intuitions were by no means common,” “the
small size of the effect suggests that Gettier intuitions
were not prevalent in our research,” and that “given the
small size of the observed effect, the theoretical signifi-
cance of this result is debatable.” They also provided a
nuanced discussion of how differences in methods,
design, analytic approach, and geographical origin and
composition of the samples could have affected results.
Constructs and Mechanisms
We agree with Buckwalter and Friedman (2024) that
researchers who claim to answer vague questions about
poorly defined constructs may very well lead readers to
inappropriate conclusions. However, Hall etal.’s (2024)
rhetorical use of “Gettier-type case” and “Gettier intu-
ition” did not preclude the specificity of their claims or
the recognition of their constraints on generality. Their
limitations were readily acknowledged. Contrary to what
Buckwalter and Friedman implied, Hall etal. did not
make strong statements about the theoretical implica-
tions of their results.
Buckwalter and Friedman (2024) argued for the devel-
opment of theories and identification of mechanisms in
research on luckily true beliefs. We agree that the study
of mechanisms is important; in fact, Hall etal. (2024)
explored the moderating role of luck attributions directly
in their analyses.1 However, the examination of mecha-
nisms should, in our view, follow the confirmation of an
effect’s replicability. The approach of Hall etal. was to
first establish the presence of the phenomenon before
(and alongside) identifying the factors that influence it.
Turri etal. (2015) employed a particular strategy and
methodology for studying knowledge attributions in their
Experiment 1 and made conclusions based on the results.
The purpose of Hall etal.’s replication was to use similar
strategies to determine whether Turri etal.’s findings
were robust. The replication results demonstrate that
prior to studying mechanisms, establishing agreement on
what researchers are trying to understand is necessary.
Examining “specific forms of luck” and theorizing about
their importance, as Buckwalter and Friedman recom-
mended, would have been premature. When results do
not conform to hypotheses, researchers tend to avoid
accepting the conclusion that their theory may not be
correct (i.e., refuted; Popper, 1959). Instead, not infre-
quently, they embark on subtle searches for subgroups
or moderators for which their theory may hold. Hall etal.
found differences and highlighted methodological issues,
which, had they not been identified, could have hindered
progress on theoretical development.
Balancing Replication Goals
Buckwalter and Friedman (2024) suggested that Hall
etal. (2024) did not appreciate the tension between two
replication goals: that of assessing reliability and that
of understanding phenomena. Hall etal. set out to do
a simple, direct replication study with both pedagogical
and scientific goals. Because of the partnership between
the Psychological Science Accelerator (Moshontz etal.,
2018) and the Collaborative Replications and Education
Project (Grahe et al., 2024; Wagge etal., 2019), the
research project increased in complexity and scope over
the course of the Stage 1 Registered Report review
process. As a consequence, additional piloted vignettes
were incorporated, measures were added and changed,
alternative response options were included, extension
hypotheses were proposed by coauthors, and plans to
assess moderating variables were formulated. The con-
ceptual replication Hall etal. conducted emerged out
of precisely those tensions noted by Buckwalter and
Friedman and the additional consideration of pedagogi-
cal value. We hope that the findings of Hall etal. will
contribute to the incremental understanding of epis-
temic intuitions and, in turn, inspire future inquiry along
these lines, that is, examining subtypes, mechanisms,
and moderators of so-called Gettier intuitions.
Transparency
Action Editor: David A. Sbarra
Editor: David A. Sbarra
Author Contributions
Kathleen Schmidt: Conceptualization; Project adminis-
tration; Writing – original draft; Writing – review &
editing.
Gerald J. Haeffel: Conceptualization; Writing – original
draft; Writing – review & editing.
Neil Levy: Conceptualization; Writing – review & editing.
David Moreau: Conceptualization; Writing – review &
editing.
Sean T. H. Lee: Conceptualization; Writing – review &
editing.
Erin M. Buchanan: Conceptualization; Writing – review
& editing.
Anthony J. Krafnick: Conceptualization; Writing – review
& editing.
Martin Voracek: Conceptualization; Writing – review &
editing.
Gerit Pfuhl: Conceptualization; Writing – review &
editing.
Krystian Barzykowski: Conceptualization; Writing –
review & editing.
Marta Kowal: Conceptualization; Writing – review &
editing.
Jordan Wagge: Conceptualization; Project administration;
Writing – original draft; Writing – review & editing.
4 Schmidt et al.
Declaration of Conflicting Interests
The author(s) declared that there were no conflicts of inter-
est with respect to the authorship or the publication of this
article.
Funding
K. Schmidt was supported by a grant from the John Temple-
ton Foundation (61825). N. Levy was supported by
a grant from the John Templeton Foundation (62631).
K. Barzykowski was supported by a grant from the National
Science Centre, Poland (2019/35/B/HS6/00528). J. Wagge
was supported by a grant from the National Science Foun-
dation (2141930).
ORCID iDs
Kathleen Schmidt https://orcid.org/0000-0002-9946-5953
Gerald J. Haeffel https://orcid.org/0000-0002-4029-1493
Neil Levy https://orcid.org/0000-0002-5679-1986
David Moreau https://orcid.org/0000-0002-1957-1941
Sean T. H. Lee https://orcid.org/0000-0002-4059-9738
Erin M. Buchanan https://orcid.org/0000-0002-9689-4189
Anthony J. Krafnick https://orcid.org/0000-0002-1692-
0413
Martin Voracek https://orcid.org/0000-0001-6109-6155
Marta Kowal https://orcid.org/0000-0001-9050-1471
Jordan Wagge https://orcid.org/0000-0002-5105-2084
Note
1. In this analysis, luck attributions did not moderate the Gettier-
intuition effect.
References
Buckwalter, W., & Friedman, O. (2024). Robust evidence for
knowledge attribution and luck: A comment on Hall etal.
(2024). Advances in Methods and Practices in Psychological
Science, 7(4). https://doi.org/10.1177/25152459241268220
Colaço, D., Buckwalter, W., Stich, S., & Machery, E. (2014).
Epistemic intuitions in fake-barn thought experiments.
Episteme, 11(2), 199–212. https://doi.org/10.1017/epi.2014.7
Frick, R. W. (1996). The appropriate use of null hypothesis
testing. Psychological Methods, 1(4), 379–390. https://doi
.org/10.1037/1082-989X.1.4.379
Grahe, J. E., Brandt, M. J., Wagge, J. R., Legate, N., Wiggins, B. J.,
Christopherson, C. D., Weisberg, Y., Corker, K. S., Chartier,
C. R., Fallon, M., Hildebrandt, L., Hurst, M. A., Lazarevic, L.,
Levitan, C., McFall, J., McLaughlin, H., Pazda, A.,
IJzerman, H., Nosek, B. A., . . . France, H. (2024).
Collaborative Replications and Education Project (CREP).
OSF. https://doi.org/10.17605/OSF.IO/WFC6U
Hall, B. F., Schmidt, K., Wagge, J. R., Lewis, S. C., Weissgerber,
S. C., Kiunke, F., Pfuhl, G., Stieger, S., Tran, U. S.,
Barzykowski, K., Bogatyreva, N., Kowal, M., Massar, K.,
Pernerstorfer, F., Sorokowski, P., Voracek, M., Chartier, C. R.,
Brandt, M. J., Grahe, J. E., . . . Buchanan, E. M. (2024).
Registered Replication Report: A large multilab cross-
cultural conceptual replication of Turri et al. (2015).
Advances in Methods and Practices in Psychological
Science, 7(4). https://doi.org/10.1177/25152459241267902
Moshontz, H., Campbell, L., Ebersole, C. R., IJzerman, H., Urry,
H. L., Forscher, P. S., Grahe, J. E., McCarthy, R. J., Musser,
E. D., Antfolk, J., Castille, C. M., Evans, T. R., Fiedler, S.,
Flake, J. K., Forero, D. A., Janssen, S. M. J., Keene, J. R.,
Protzko, J., Aczel, B., . . . Chartier, C. R. (2018). The
Psychological Science Accelerator: Advancing psychology
through a distributed collaborative network. Advances
in Methods and Practices in Psychological Science, 1(4),
501–515. https://doi.org/10.1177/2515245918797607
Nagel, J., San Juan, V., & Mar, R. A. (2013). Lay denial of
knowledge for justified true beliefs. Cognition, 12(3),
652–661. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2013.02.008
Nosek, B. A., Ebersole, C. R., DeHaven, A. C., & Mellor, D. T.
(2018). The preregistration revolution. Proceedings of the
National Academy of Sciences, USA, 115(11), 2600–2606.
https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1708274114
Popper, K. R. (1959). The logic of scientific discovery. Basic Books.
Turri, J., Buckwalter, W., & Blouw, P. (2015). Knowledge
and luck. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 22(2), 378–390.
https://doi.org/10.3758/s13423-014-0683-5
Wagge, J. R., Brandt, M. J., Lazarevic, L. B., Legate, N.,
Christopherson, C., Wiggins, B., & Grahe, J. E. (2019).
Publishing research with undergraduate students via repli-
cation work: The Collaborative Replications and Education
Project. Frontiers in Psychology, 10, Article 439232. https://
doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2019.00247
Weinberg, J. M., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2001). Normativity and
epistemic intuitions. Philosophical Topics, 29(1), 429–460.
https://doi.org/10.5840/philtopics2001291/217
Wicherts, J. M., Veldkamp, C. L. S., Augusteijn, H. E. M.,
Bakker, M., van Aert, R. C. M., & van Assen, M. A. L. M.
(2016). Degrees of freedom in planning, running, analyz-
ing, and reporting psychological studies: A checklist to
avoid p-hacking. Frontiers in Psychology, 7, Article 1832.
https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2016.01832