ArticlePDF Available

Reimaging Talent: How genetic enhancement could shape the future of sports

Authors:

Abstract

2024 McNamee Essay Prize - Commendation Winner This paper explores the evolving relationship between technological advancements and sports, focusing on the controversial topic of genetic modification in athletes. Drawing parallels from various forms of technological enhancement in sports, such as robot combat and SlamBall, the paper questions whether genetic modification undermines the core values of sportsmanship, including talent, fairness, and competition. The World Anti-Doping Agency (WADA) currently prohibits genetic modifications, citing concerns about the dehumanization of athletic performance. However, this paper argues that genetic enhancement, like other performance aids, can democratize sports by leveling the natural genetic playing field and enabling athletes to better showcase their true talents. Through comparisons between naturally gifted athletes and those benefiting from genetic or technological enhancements, the paper challenges the notion that enhancements distort the essence of sports. Instead, it proposes that the ethical framework of sports should adapt to embrace genetic technologies while maintaining fairness and transparency. By fostering an open dialogue on these technologies, this paper contends that the true spirit of sportsmanship — rooted in effort, excellence, and fairness — can be preserved and even enhanced.
Reimaging talent:
how genetic enhancement could shape the future of sports
Introduction
In recent decades, the boundaries of human potential and technological advancement have been
explored and pushed through various forms of media and competition. In the late 1990s, the
television show Robot Wars introduced audiences to a new type of combat sport, one that seemed
to belong to the realm of science fiction: remote-controlled machines equipped with hammers,
rotating blades, spurs, and flamethrowers replacing gloves and muscles, creating a spectacle of
engineering and design prowess. Fast forward a few years, and the speculative future of sporting
competition has taken again an embodied form with the emergence of The Enhanced Games, a
"faster, higher, stronger" alternative to the traditional Olympic Games, notable for its lack of drug
testing and, in the words of its president Aron Ping D'Souza, for its goal «to evolve humanity, by
demonstrating what the human body is truly capable of» (see Enhanced Games: The mind behind
the 'Doped Games', 2024)
By examining the implications of such advancements, in particular the controversial topic of
genetic modification through somatic intervention (Semenova, 2023), this paper addresses
questions about the nature of sports and the concept of protection of natural talent. Does the
objection to performance-enhancing modifications, viewed as a “dehumanization” of athletic
performance, hold when considering genetically modified super-athletes? Does the protection of
natural talent, aimed at ensuring a level playing field, serve as a moral framework to shape public
attitudes toward sportsmanship (Erler, 2018)? To address these questions, the author considers
public perception, especially suspicion, as a crucial criterion for revising sports categories such as
"the extraordinary performances".
"Who said Jordan?" - Being the best dunker at just 6’1’
«Thirty teams and their ferocious fighting machines battle it out in a bulletproof arena for the chance
to be crowned Champion»: nearly 30 years ago, the TV show Robot Wars served as a precursor to
the concept that competition could be drastically transformed by the introduction of technologically
and engineeringly advanced participants. The show's success lay in its appeal to both the
technological enthusiasts and the public, who were fascinated by the innovative strategies and
mechanisms involved in robot combat. I was very young at the time of this program, but I
remember another rather innovative one well: SlamBall, a kind of combination between football
and basketball made more spectacular using trampolines that allowed for a series of beautiful
dunks and stoppages. My favourite player was Stan Fletcher: he was unanimously considered the
strongest of them all, especially for the spectacularity of his dunks. Yet even though it was a
sport very similar to basketball, he was not "that" tall (his height is 6’1’’, about 185 cm). What
made Fletcher the best of all was his responsiveness and his ability to change pace. Indeed, if he
had been the tallest of them all, that probably would have negatively affected the qualities that
made him exceptional. At the same time, however, if there had been no trampolines, Stan
Fletcher probably would never have been known as one of the greatest dunkers ever. I think I
liked the sport for that very reason: trampolines allowed a much wider audience of athletes to
jump high. Since I have been interested in human genetic enhancement I am often reminded of
Fletcher’s example. I compare his figure to that of another athlete who plays the same sport as
Fletcher, but in its more "traditional", non- technologically mediated form: Boban Marjanovic,
the current tallest player in the NBA. Despite being an often-decisive player thanks to his
"biological endowment", Marjanovic will certainly not be remembered as one of the most
talented and brilliant basketball’s dunkers.
This paper contends that enhancing athletic performancewhether through
technological, pharmacological, or genetic meansdoes not compromise core elements
deemed essential to sports and athleticism: talent, competitiveness, transparency, and even the
possibility of failure . On the contrary, it posits that such enhancements, especially genetic ones,
can augment these elements. Specifically, they enable a clearer distinction between natural
talent, exemplified by athletes like Fletcher, and what is largely based on biological luck, as seen
in Marjanovic.
The Dehumanization Argument
In 2003, the World Anti-Doping Agency (WADA), the international authority on drug use in
sports, preemptively banned athletes who have undergone genetic modification, labeling such
procedures as "gene doping" (see WADA 2004 Prohibited List). In 2017, WADA extended this
prohibition to include technologies like CRISPR. WADA's rationale for the ban is the "protection
of natural talent": «WADA strives to establish a level playing field, to allow athletes to
concentrate on the pursuit of athletic excellence through their natural talent […] The use of
genetic transfer technology to dramatically enhance sport performance is contrary to the spirit
of sport» (see WORLD ANTI- DOPING CODE 4.3.2, 2003). We can refer to WADA’s critique of
genetic enhancement technologies, which is widespread, especially in broader non-sporting
literature (see, for example, Habermas, 2003), as the "dehumanization argument". This
perspective argues that enhancing athletes would undermine the intrinsic human qualities of
effort and perseverance, through which natural talent must be honoured and nurtured (Murray,
2018). Thus, it posits that genetic enhancement leads to an unfair advantage, eroding the level
playing field essential to fair competition.
This objection to genetically enhanced athletes can be challenged from various
perspectives. First, throughout sports history, athletes who excel often benefit from natural
genetic advantages (Georgiades et al., 2017). For example, a predisposition for higher lung
capacity is already a genetic differentiator among athletes. Genetic modification could therefore
be seen as a regulator of the natural lottery (as trampolines were in the case of Stan Fletcher),
levelling the playing field by providing opportunities to those who may not possess such natural
advantages. This could democratize access to high-level sports performance, allowing more
individuals to compete based on a broader definition of talent.
Secondly, humans have always utilized technology to enhance their capabilities, from primitive
tools to modern sports equipment. Genetic enhancement can be considered a continuation of
this trend, not a deviation from it (Barfield, 2019). The point, if anything, might be that since
technology would be embodied, it becomes more difficult to decipher when an "upgrade gear"
is unfair. This leads to the importance of the category of suspicion in the viewer's perception,
which will be discussed later.
It can also be argued that genetic enhancement might compromise the ethics of sports.
However, technology and ethics are not mutually exclusive. Instead of outright rejecting genetic
modification, it would be more constructive to develop an ethics of genetic enhancement that
values integrity and transparency as central (Murray, 2017).
Finally, genetic enhancement can be viewed as an opportunity to expand the boundaries of
human performance. Each generation of athletes strives to surpass the achievements of their
predecessors. Genetic modification could represent the next significant leap in this ongoing
quest for excellence. This advancement does not diminish the importance of effort or
perseverance; rather, it recontextualizes them within a new paradigm where athletes must still
work hard to optimize and manage their enhanced abilities, emphasizing the importance of
strategy and mental fortitude.
For these reasons, this paper contends that a more significant argument than the critique
of dehumanization is that of "levelling of performance", which posits that one of the
fundamental
elements of sportthe unexpected, resulting from the "extraordinary performance"would be
lost.
"Can you believe this?" On Wonder and Sport
As a twenty-six-year-old football fan, watching Lionel Messi play has always evoked a mix of
admiration, a longing to emulate his skills (quickly dampened by the realization of its
impossibility), and a deep fear of facing his Barcelona in the Champions League. One story that
has always fascinated me is how Como, a team that just reached Serie A for the first time this
year, reportedly turned down a young Messi due to his frail physical structure, which they
deemed unsuitable for professional football. It was then Dr. Diego Schwarzstein who
administered hormonal treatment to Messi, allowing him to reach a height of 5'5'', merely
adequate for competition. In contrast, Messi's great rival, Cristiano Ronaldo, is known not just
for his unique talent and statuesque physique, but especially for his exceptional mentality. It is
his relentless dedication to training that have propelled him to be the greatest alongside Messi.
Thus, while many can achieve a comparable physique, replicating Ronaldo's psychological
resilience and determination is far more challenging. Both players exemplify that there is a core
that cannot be reproduced through biological manipulation. As the public recognizes and
appreciates that significant differences in sports could arise from something which cannot be
artificially replicated, and since the acceptance of difference in terms of pure talent is the basis
of what we call sports competition, we should first identify what we mean by pure talent,
distinguishing it from purely performative biological endowments, before opening a discussion
on what is the correct degree of distribution of the latter by means of genetic enhancement
interventions.
To understand what I mean, I'll provide an example (staying within the realm of sports, of
course!). In Formula 1 both the driver's skills, his pure talent, and the car's technical
specifications, its performative potential, contribute to victory. But which of the two carries
more weight in crossing the finish line first? We could surely agree that within set limits for
engine power, safety systems, and chassis weight, each racing team can design and upgrade the
parts of the car that assumes to be the most important to win. We can also safely assume that if
there were no driver, and all cars were equipped with the same autonomous driving system, the
best-designed car in terms of overall output would probably win the race. The same could be
said when imagining the opposite scenario: if all racing teams used the exact same car, no one
would have a definitive advantage in winning, but if behind the wheel of one of these machines
there is a pilot with pure talent superior to the others,
the likelihood of them crossing the finish line first is high. He could even lead to win a less
performative car!
Here we arrive at the importance of suspicion as a method to disentangle what
constitutes pure talent, in the case of our pilot an exceptional hand-eye coordination, reflexes,
decision-making under pressure, capacity to adapt swiftly to changing conditions, strategic
overtaking manoeuvres, and the ability to maintain focus throughout a race duration, from the
underlying biological structures that enable its emergence. Once the latter are defined for each
sport (through a process of public discussion and policymaking, the investigation of which is
beyond the scope of this paper; see S. Polcz, A. Lewis, 2018), I argue that modern genetic
screening technologies would make it relatively straightforward to identify those who have used
genetic enhancements enabling precise and transparent regulation. Take the example of Eero
Antero Mäntyranta, a Finnish cross-country skier who competed in the 1960s. «He was one of
the greatest Olympians ever in his sport: he won seven Olympic and five World Championship
medals. He was found to have an abnormally high red blood cell count, which allowed his blood
to carry more oxygen, in turn giving him a competitive edge. This abnormality led to accusations
of cheating, and his victories were viewed with suspicion. His name was only cleared two
decades later when his family was selected for a genetic study that revealed that his elevated
red blood cell count - 500% above average - was due to a rare genetic variant» (S. Polcz, A.
Lewis, cit.). It seems quite straightforward to think that if everyone had possessed his biological
endowment, or another considered fundamental for competing in this sport, and if Mäntyranta
had still won all those medals, no one would have doubted his immense pure talent. Allowing
genetic enhancement through public and transparent regulation would therefore enable greater
accountability for the actual sporting achievements of athletes. In this regard, what we need to
focus on is how to achieve a new balance in the "sporting hermeneutic circle" (F. Frias, 2016)
composed of maintaining competitive levels among athletes, ensuring the fascination and trust
of the public towards the game itself, and respecting the given rules. Since the first two show
themselves to be inherently susceptible to and mouldable by technological mediation and
enhancements in terms of overall level of sports performance (George Best was one of the most
talented footballers in history, but if he were playing today, with the average level of physicality
that players and audiences have become accustomed to, he might not have the same
opportunity to showcase his skills), our focus must remain on adjusting and setting rules and
limits to ensure fairness and transparency.
Think of the classic example of sport’s inequality, that of athletes who use doping in a
situation where not all competitors have access (or are willing to break the rules of the
competition to gain access) to it. Let’s ignore both the fact that athletes are usually already
better equipped genetically and physically than most of us: the “inequality” to which we refer
here is the additional advantage gained by illicit drug use. Thus, «doping is unethical not so
much because it creates inequality per sé, but because it is necessarily clandestine as nobody
knows who is or is not using drugs, and this breaches the rules of the sport and is unfair to those
who obey the rules» (J. Harris, S. Chan, 2008).
In contrast, what we consider legitimate and open to all, training, is often less accessible than
doping or genetic enhancement would be in practice. To approach the level of Mäntyranta «an
athlete would need to increase the level of EPO in their blood, thereby achieving a higher
oxygen-carrying potential. However, several methods can increase EPO levels: training at high
altitude, sleeping in a hyperbaric tent, extracting your own blood at an earlier date and injecting
it later, or injecting synthetic EPO» (S. Polcz, A. Lewis, cit.). The first two methods, which involve
training, are not prohibited, whereas the latter two, considered enhancement interventions, are
banned. Unless effort is rewarded as virtuous simply because it is effortful (an effort, moreover,
that is superfluous given that Mäntyranta will have an initially insurmountable biological
advantage), I believe the reasoning here suffers from elitism. Training is considered equitable
because it adheres to established rules and, theoretically, all athletes are permitted to pursue it.
The same, however, could be done with enhancement interventions, ensuring even greater
effectiveness in terms of transparency and increasing the likelihood of democratizing and
rewarding pure talent.
Conclusion
The issue of enhancement interventions, particularly in sports, centers on distributive justice.
WADA's implicit endorsement of natural advantage is clearly at odds with its stance on the
necessity of a level playing field for fair competition. According to Ronald Dworkin, a just system
ensures equal opportunity, separates endowments from ambitions, and justifies distributive
inequalities based on choices rather than uncontrollable factors (Dworkin, 2000). Therefore,
advancing athletic performance through genetic and technological means should be viewed not
as a divergence from sportsmanship but as a natural evolution. Historically, sports have
embraced technological aids, from training equipment to performance gear, indicating a
progression toward accepting genetic enhancements. Establishing an ethical framework
emphasizing transparency and fairness is crucialfor integrating genetic technology into sports
without compromising the essential elements of what we call sportsmanship: «a rule-governed
activity that is about fairness, excellence, an understanding of how to play the game, and, in
competitive sports, winning» (D. Abad, 2010). An open and non-prejudicial discussion on the
possibilities offered by enhancement technologies is consistent with the promotion of all these
elements. Not only would sportsmanship not be compromised, but also, since the will to win has
always been in systematic conflict with the other elements, leading to rule-breaking behaviours,
and since this peril is increased by a not properly regulated use of enhancement technologies,
an unprecedented opportunity to develop an updated ethical and legal balance centred on
integrity and transparency opens for all stakeholders involved in the sports community.
References
Abad D., Sportsmanship, Sport, Ethics and Philosophy, 4(1), 2741, 2010.
Barfield W., The Process of Evolution, Human Enhancement Technology, and Cyborgs,
Philosophies, 4(1):10, 2019.
Dworkin R., Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality, Harvard University Press,
2000.
Erler A., “Natural” Athletic Performance or a Level Playing Field? You Can't Have Both, American
Journal of Bioethics 18 (6):30-31, 2018.
Frias, F. J., The hermeneutics of sport: limits and conditions of possibility of our understandings
of sport, Sport, Ethics and Philosophy, 10(4), 375391, 2016.
Georgiades, E:, et al., Why nature prevails over nurture in the making of the elite athlete, BMC
Genomics 18 (Suppl 8), 835, 2017.
Habermas J., The Future of Human Nature, Cambridge, Polity, 2003.
Harris J., Chan S., Enhancement is good for you!: Understanding the ethics of genetic
enhancement, Gene Ther 15, 338339, 2008.
Murray T. H., The Ethics of Sports Technologies and Human Enhancement, London, Routledge,
2017.
Murray T. H., “Natural” Talents and Dedication—Meanings and Values in Sport, The American
Journal of Bioethics, 18(6), 13, 2018.
Polcz S., Lewis A., Regulating Genetic Advantage, 32 HARV. J. L. & TECH. 265, 2018.
Semenova E., et al., Genes and Athletic Performance: The 2023 Update, Genes 2023, 14(6),
1235.
ResearchGate has not been able to resolve any citations for this publication.
Article
Full-text available
Phenotypes of athletic performance and exercise capacity are complex traits influenced by both genetic and environmental factors. This update on the panel of genetic markers (DNA polymorphisms) associated with athlete status summarises recent advances in sports genomics research, including findings from candidate gene and genome-wide association (GWAS) studies, meta-analyses, and findings involving larger-scale initiatives such as the UK Biobank. As of the end of May 2023, a total of 251 DNA polymorphisms have been associated with athlete status, of which 128 genetic markers were positively associated with athlete status in at least two studies (41 endurance-related, 45 power-related, and 42 strength-related). The most promising genetic markers include the AMPD1 rs17602729 C, CDKN1A rs236448 A, HFE rs1799945 G, MYBPC3 rs1052373 G, NFIA-AS2 rs1572312 C, PPARA rs4253778 G, and PPARGC1A rs8192678 G alleles for endurance; ACTN3 rs1815739 C, AMPD1 rs17602729 C, CDKN1A rs236448 C, CPNE5 rs3213537 G, GALNTL6 rs558129 T, IGF2 rs680 G, IGSF3 rs699785 A, NOS3 rs2070744 T, and TRHR rs7832552 T alleles for power; and ACTN3 rs1815739 C, AR ≥21 CAG repeats, LRPPRC rs10186876 A, MMS22L rs9320823 T, PHACTR1 rs6905419 C, and PPARG rs1801282 G alleles for strength. It should be appreciated, however, that elite performance still cannot be predicted well using only genetic testing.
Article
Full-text available
At the forefront of medicine, Gene Therapy brings you the latest research into genetic and cell-based technologies to treat disease. It also publishes Progress & Prospects reviews and News and Commentary articles, which highlight the cutting edge of the field.
Article
In this paper, linguistic-analytic philosophy has been identified as the dominant methodology in the philosophy of sport. The hermeneutics of sport is contrasted with linguistic-analytic philosophy by analyzing Heidegger’s view of Truth. In doing so, two views of philosophy are compared: ontology or description. Sport hermeneutics’ task has to do with description. Hermeneutical explanations of sport attempt to describe the facticity of sport. Such a facticity is formed by three moments: embodiment, capabilities, and tradition. They are not components of sport that can be identified as essential components but rather, they are identifiable only for analytic purposes. These three above-mentioned elements cannot be identified as elements, because they are intrinsically intertwined forming a unitary network of meaning. The task of sport hermeneutics is to describe the different relationships that compose such a network of meaning. In doing so, sport is a humane activity linked to the constitutive human task of making sense of reality by projecting meaning into it.
  • D Abad
  • Sportsmanship
  • Sport
Abad D., Sportsmanship, Sport, Ethics and Philosophy, 4(1), 27-41, 2010.
The Process of Evolution
  • W Barfield
Barfield W., The Process of Evolution, Human Enhancement Technology, and Cyborgs, Philosophies, 4(1):10, 2019.
The Future of Human Nature
  • J Habermas
Habermas J., The Future of Human Nature, Cambridge, Polity, 2003.