Content uploaded by Theodore Lechterman
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Theodore Lechterman on Jun 03, 2024
Content may be subject to copyright.
Peer Review Version
Social Enterprises as Agents of Social Justice: A Rawlsian
Perspective on Institutional Capacity
Journal:
Organization Studies
Manuscript ID
OS-21-0716.R4
Manuscript Type:
Special Issue: Philosophy and Organization Studies: How Does Philosophy
Illuminate the Study of Organizations
Keywords:
Ethics < Theoretical Perspectives, Social enterprise < Topics, Institutional
theory < Theoretical Perspectives, Philosophy < Theoretical Perspectives,
Entrepreneurship < Topics
Abstract:
Many scholars of organizations see social enterprise as a promising
approach to advancing social justice but neglect to scrutinize the
normative foundations and limitations of this optimism. This article draws
on Rawlsian political philosophy to investigate whether and how social
enterprises can support social justice. We propose that this perspective
Organization Studies
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
assigns organizations a duty to foster institutional capacity, a concept we
define and elaborate. We investigate how this duty might apply
specifically to social enterprises, given their characteristic features. We
theorize six different mechanisms through which social enterprises might
successfully discharge this duty. These results affirm the value of
conversation between organizational studies and political philosophy and
shed new light on debates regarding social enterprise, institutional
theory, and several other topics.
Page 1 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
Social enterprises as agents of social justice: A Rawlsian perspective on institutional
capacity
Theodore M. Lechterman
IE University, Spain
Johanna Mair
Hertie School, Germany & Stanford University, USA
Abstract
Many scholars of organizations see social enterprise as a promising approach to advancing social
justice but neglect to scrutinize the normative foundations and limitations of this optimism. This
article draws on Rawlsian political philosophy to investigate whether and how social enterprises
can support social justice. We propose that this perspective assigns organizations a duty to foster
institutional capacity, a concept we define and elaborate. We investigate how this duty might
apply specifically to social enterprises, given their characteristic features. We theorize six
different mechanisms through which social enterprises might successfully discharge this duty.
These results affirm the value of conversation between organizational studies and political
philosophy and shed new light on debates regarding social enterprise, institutional theory, and
several other topics.
Keywords
social enterprise, social justice, institutional capacity, strong institutions, political philosophy,
John Rawls
Corresponding author
Theodore M. Lechterman, School of Humanities, IE University, IE Tower, Paseo de la
Castellana, 259E, 28046 Madrid, Spain. Email: tlechterman@faculty.ie.edu.
Both authors contributed equally to this project.
Page 2 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
1
Social enterprise is a form of organizing that leverages aspects of market-based activity
to address social problems and affect social change (Miller, Grimes, McMullen, & Vogus, 2012;
Mair & Martí, 2006). This mode of organizing can take many paths, from using sales revenue to
finance social programs or product donations, to recruiting labor exclusively from marginalized
groups, to developing products or business models with economic inclusion or environmental
sustainability as their primary goals. It has become an increasingly prevalent approach to
organizing, manifesting variously and in diverse contexts, and defining as many as 11 million
organizations worldwide (British Council & Social Enterprise UK, 2022). Social enterprises span
sectors and operate in a wide range of national settings, from liberal democracies to authoritarian
regimes and from developed to less developed economies (Kibler, Salmivaara, Stenholm, &
Terjesen, 2018; Kerlin, 2010). Observers note the wide variation in the problems that social
enterprises address, their competition and collaboration with other modes of organizing, their
appetite for pursuing policy and legal change, and the legal forms they adopt (Mair & Rathert,
2024; Mair, 2020; Defourny & Nyssens, 2017).
Social enterprise as a form of organizing has attracted scholarly interest in organizational
studies in part because it represents an instance of organizational hybridity that challenges
conventional analytic categories (Child, 2020) and combines organizing elements associated
with different and often incompatible logics, identities, and forms (Battilana & Lee, 2014).
Additionally, many researchers are attracted to studying social enterprise because they regard it
as a promising approach to addressing social problems, such as economic exclusion,
environmental degradation, and social inequalities (Katz & Page, 2010; Smith, Gonin, &
Besharov, 2013; Wry & York, 2017; Mair & Rathert, 2021b). It is associated with promoting the
public good (Vedula et al., 2021), catalyzing positive social change (Stephan, Patterson, Kelly, &
Page 3 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
2
Mair, 2016), and transforming social systems that give rise to or reproduce social problems (Mair
& Martí, 2006). However, the role ascribed to social enterprises in “solving” problems of public
interest is rarely defended on normative grounds. What makes a condition problematic, how it
should be solved, and whose responsibility it is to address it are controversial questions with
enormous practical consequences for those who operate, finance, regulate, benefit from, or
compete with social enterprises. Failing to articulate and defend assumptions about these
questions limits the reliability and precision of empirical research. It may also distort research
agendas, evaluation metrics, and strategic prescriptions (Chalmers, 2021). How can social
enterprises operate as agents of social justice, i.e., as entities capable of or responsible for
realizing justice in some way (Hickey, Meijers, Robeyns, & Timmer, 2021), despite
disagreements about justice and the allocation of responsibility? In turn, how can a normative
evaluation of social enterprise inform empirical investigation of this form of organizing and its
place in society?
These questions prompt us to revisit and advance how the literature treats the relationship
between social enterprises and their institutional contexts. Despite enduring scholarly interest in
the connection between social enterprises and institutions, researchers have tended to investigate
this connection in limited ways. Many organizational scholars regard social enterprises as
carriers of institutional logics, durable sets of assumptions and beliefs that prescribe thinking and
behavior (Pache & Santos, 2010; Battilana & Lee, 2014; Wry & York, 2017; Grimes, Williams,
& Zhao, 2019). Others treat institutions as influencing the prevalence, reception, and function of
social enterprises in different settings (Stephan, Uhlaner, & Stride, 2015; Kerlin, 2010; Kibler et
al., 2018; Santos, 2012; Galle, 2013; Thornton, Gonas, & Lohrke, 2015). A third stream of
Page 4 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
3
literature considers how social enterprises alter institutions at the local level (Cavotta & Mena,
2023; Venkataraman, Vermeulen, Raaijmakers, & Mair, 2016).
While these streams have traditionally paid limited attention to the effects of social
enterprises on macro-institutional contexts, recent efforts to explore macro-institutional questions
have run into ideological clashes when attempting to theorize the relationship between social
enterprise and capitalism. Recent studies envision social enterprises as catalyzing systemic
change or as an antidote to macro-institutional dysfunction. They see social enterprises as
rescuing capitalism from troubling trends toward inequality and environmental destruction,
either as a necessary supplement to capitalist arrangements or as a desirable replacement for
capitalist firms (Mair & Rathert, 2021a; Battilana, Obloj, Pache, & Sengul, 2022). However,
such views struggle against skeptical perspectives that regard social enterprise not as a redeemer
of capitalism but as the vanguard of neoliberalism (Eikenberry & Kluver, 2004; Dey & Steyaert,
2012; Giridharadas, 2018; Spicer, Kay, & Ganz, 2019). Social enterprises, according to these
views, offer false promises of institutional transformation; they ultimately hasten trends toward
privatization and commodification, which these authors deem unjust.
We contend that engaging explicitly with political philosophy is necessary to overcome
this impasse and advance beyond existing paradigms for conceiving the interaction between
social enterprises and institutions.
This article develops an institutional perspective on the relationship between social
enterprise and social justice by drawing on the work of John Rawls (1955; 1999 [1971]; 1993;
2001) and those influenced by him. This perspective regards justice first and foremost as a virtue
of major social institutions such as the tax system and property law and not of organizations
(e.g., charities, firms, churches, universities) or particular organizational forms. It warns that
Page 5 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
4
organizations assuming responsibility for tackling social problems may inadvertently reinforce
deeper structural inequalities or arrogate to themselves the power to define collective goals.
However, it also insists that duties of justice are not limited to institutions, although the form
such duties take may differ for organizations.
We pick up this idea and explore how social enterprises might satisfy duties of justice
within the bounds of Rawlsian theory. We propose that a Rawlsian view supplies organizations
with a duty of justice to contribute to institutional capacity, understood as the ability of
institutions to fairly distribute the benefits and burdens of social cooperation. As we argue,
discharging this duty requires fortifying just arrangements that already exist and facilitating
transitions to just arrangements in contexts where these arrangements are missing, unstable, or
compromised. We then show how the features of social enterprise generate six specific
mechanisms for building and maintaining institutional capacity.
This study demonstrates how political philosophy can help to derive a concept that can
clarify the role of social enterprise in society and anchor further research in organizational
scholarship. The focus on institutional capacity invites scholars of organizations to devote more
attention to the indirect effects of social enterprises on their institutional context, to study
conditions under which social enterprises might succeed or fail in fostering institutional capacity,
to identify and test alternative pathways through which social enterprises might advance justice
through institutional effects, and to consider the relationships between institutional capacity and
other forms of organizing.
Scholars of organizations have long appreciated the value of philosophical analysis for
organizational research, with particular attention to the insights available from metaphysics,
epistemology, and philosophy of language (e.g., Tsoukas & Chia, 2011; Ramoglou & McMullen,
Page 6 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
5
2023). This study illustrates the potential contributions of political philosophy and builds on
efforts to problematize conceptual and normative assumptions in empirical investigations of
organizational phenomena (Suddaby, 2015; Fayard, 2019). Although efforts to apply political
philosophy to organizational studies are not uncommon, efforts to self-consciously reflect on the
relationship between the two are rarer. We proceed in the next section by canvassing recent
studies that establish connections between political philosophy and social enterprise. As we
show, existing work on the relationship between social enterprise and political philosophy has
underexplored how responsibilities may be distributed between organizations and institutions.
Next, we introduce a central Rawlsian claim that appears to challenge much of the extant theory
and practice of social enterprise, the claim that principles of justice apply in the first instance to
institutions and not to organizations that operate within them. We go on to theorize how this
insight yields guidelines for organizations in general and social enterprises specifically. Our
account proposes that social enterprises can complement and supplement already reasonably just
institutions. Where just institutions are underdeveloped or malfunctioning, social enterprises can
demonstrate just alternatives and incentivize greater accountability. In the discussion section, we
reflect on the consequences of this account for theories of social enterprise and broader currents
in organizational theory. We show how institutional capacity supplies an essential concept for
organizational research and suggest several directions for further study. We conclude by
underlining how careful engagement with political philosophy can deepen the normative and
conceptual foundations of organizational research, challenge conventional paradigms, and
prompt new lines of inquiry.
Social Enterprise and Political Philosophy
Page 7 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
6
Ours is not the first attempt to leverage insights from political philosophy for application
to social enterprise or related phenomena. Below, we distill three ways that organizational and
management theory scholars have sought to leverage political philosophy to justify and appraise
social enterprise. We highlight these studies because they represent disparate approaches, appear
in leading journals, and are among the most cited articles in organizational theory that draw
heavily on political philosophy. (The first three columns of Table 1 summarize these
contributions, which we elaborate in the text below.)
------------------------------------
Insert Table 1 about here
------------------------------------
One prominent perspective suggests that social enterprise can be assessed against its
success in directly advancing human capabilities (Kroeger & Weber, 2014). It invites observers
to evaluate social enterprises according to their tendency to promote the subjective well-being of
disadvantaged beneficiaries. This perspective combines insights from Nussbaum and Sen (1993)
and the utilitarian tradition (e.g., Bentham, 1907). While not explicitly acknowledged, utilitarian
premises are a natural explanation for the authors’ focus on minimizing gaps in well-being.
Combining these traditions leads the authors to observe that reducing inequality in well-being
may be optimally achieved by blending social and market elements. They hold that observers
should assess the performance of any given social enterprise according to this yardstick. The
account is attractive not only because of its sophisticated combination of disparate philosophical
traditions but also because it supplies a simple quantitative metric for progress tracking and
drawing comparisons between diverse entities and strategies. Nonetheless, it also raises some
key challenges. Many entities commonly regarded as social enterprises do not make inequality
Page 8 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
7
reduction their primary mission. Plenty of social enterprises use market-based activities to
address problems or advance goals of other kinds, such as in the areas of the arts, science,
culture, and environmental preservation. The account under consideration leads to the radical
conclusion that such entities are either failed examples of social enterprise or must be omitted
from empirical samples. While this is a possible conclusion, it also creates an opportunity for
alternative views that can accommodate a broader range of causes.
An alternative normative perspective on social enterprise centers on pluralism and
suggests a broader potential role. Drawing on insights from Aristotle (2014) and Galston (2002),
among others, Mitchell, Weaver, Agle, Bailey, and Carlson (2016) argue that multi-objective
organizing (of which social enterprise represents a paradigmatic species) is normatively desirable
because of its ability to accommodate diverse perspectives on the nature of value. Disagreement
about value, they argue, recommends organizational forms and strategies that pursue plural
goals. Only by attending to the preferences of different stakeholders and adopting hybrid
organizational forms can organizations show sufficient respect for the diversity of viewpoints
throughout society. This pluralist perspective suggests that social enterprises should be assessed
not by independent notions of equality or well-being but simply by their success in
accommodating the diverse value judgments of their stakeholders. In other words, justice assigns
social enterprises a procedural duty to integrate the diversity of stakeholder values fairly. A
potential virtue of this account is that it can explain the tremendous variety of social enterprise
missions and strategies. Yet, a question left unanswered by this perspective is why incorporating
multiple objectives within organizations is superior to an ecosystem composed of diversely-
oriented organizations. Tasking organizations with multiple objectives would appear to
encourage conflicting interests and middling performance (Heath, 2014). By contrast,
Page 9 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
8
encouraging organizations to specialize according to particular aims would appear to minimize
internal conflict and unleash the benefits of comparative advantage.
A third way of assessing social enterprise normatively might draw on the deliberative
democratic approach to management, which originates in Habermas (1996) and sees democratic
deliberation as a valuable element in all settings of collective decision-making (Scherer &
Palazzo, 2007; Ferraro, 2018). Social enterprise is a likely form of a deliberative approach to
management, as this way of organizing allows for the pursuit of multiple goals and structural
flexibility that deliberation favors. Instead of adopting multiple goals to fit stakeholders’
preexisting preferences, the deliberative approach to management proposes that organizations
deliberate with their stakeholders to resolve disagreements and identify common goals. The
deliberative approach may be attractive because it goes beyond the pluralist’s concern for
acknowledging the perspectives of affected parties by seeking to hear them in their own voices.
Additionally, deliberative processes are credited with epistemic advantages by screening out
faulty reasons and locating justifications acceptable to all (Cohen, 2002). However, as critics
have noted, deliberative democratic theory was developed with the state, not the organization, as
its target (Sabadoz & Singer, 2017). The reasons for governing the state through deliberative
processes may not apply equally to organizations. Organizations, which lack universal
membership and may face pressure from market forces, may be unable to satisfy the
requirements needed to make deliberation successful (Hussain & Moriarty, 2018).
Despite their different philosophical motivations, these accounts share a common
methodological orientation, which is to apply political norms directly to organizational forms
and strategies. They take normative principles from political philosophy and consider how
organizations might satisfy these principles straightaway. The perspective advanced in this
Page 10 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
9
article explores an alternative possibility. For John Rawls and many influenced by him, political
norms do not apply to organizations directly. Rather, they apply in the first instance to the
institutions that compose “the basic structure of society.” One cannot answer what justice
requires of organizations without first attending to the question of what justice requires of
institutions at the societal level. As we show further below, this way of thinking ultimately offers
a more nuanced institutional view of how social enterprise can contribute to social justice.
Rawls and Agents of Justice
The work of political philosopher John Rawls (1955; 1999 [1971]; 1993; 2001) draws
increasing interest from researchers in business ethics (Brock, 1998; Wempe, 2008; Mäkinen &
Kourula, 2012; Blanc & Al-Moudi, 2013; Singer, 2015; Norman, 2015) and management
practice (Keeley, 1978, 1984; Margolis & Walsh, 2003). However, Rawls’s work has made
fewer inroads into other areas of organizational studies, such as institutional theory and social
enterprise. Like many philosophers, Rawls says little explicitly about organizations and
organizing, which might help explain organizational theorists’ limited uptake of his work.
Nonetheless, we claim that Rawlsian theory has powerful implications for how organizations can
be justified and appraised as well as the relationship between organizations and their institutional
contexts. As we seek to show, Rawlsian ideas can contribute much to theorizing social
enterprise.
Rawls remains best known for proposing a set of principles of justice that recognize
individuals as inherently free and equal and specify terms of social cooperation that individuals,
so conceived, can regard as fair (Rawls, 1999). The principles he proposes to perform this task
focus on (1) assuring an extensive set of equal basic liberties (2a) under conditions of fair
Page 11 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
10
equality of opportunity for differential rewards, and (2b) where any resulting inequalities work to
the benefit of a society’s least advantaged members. Our focus is not on the substance of the
principles themselves, whose derivation and interpretation continue to provoke extensive debate.
Rather, we focus on how Rawls’s views about the application of principles of justice can inform
theorizing about the role of social enterprise in society.
Throughout his work, Rawls insists that principles of justice are not meant to be universal
in scope or indifferent to the subject, applying everywhere and equally to the conduct of
individuals, organizations, and institutions. Crucially, justice does not apply in the first instance
to the conduct of individuals and organizations; it applies to the institutions that compose the
“basic structure of society.” The “basic structure of society” refers to the assembly of “major
social institutions,” which “distribute fundamental rights and duties and determine the division of
advantages from social cooperation” (Rawls, 1999: 6). Institutions composing the basic structure
combine to influence what individuals “can expect to be and how well they can expect to do”
(Rawls, 1999: 6). An institution, for Rawls, is any “public system of rules which defines offices
and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities, and the like” (Rawls, 1999:
47), and examples of institutions that compose the basic structure include the market, the family,
the system of property, the tax regime, and the political constitution. The principles of justice do
not apply directly to individuals or organizations, which Rawls refers to as “private persons”
(Rawls, 1993: 285) and “private associations” (Rawls, 1999: 7).
Why should justice be understood primarily as a virtue of major institutions and not of
organizations or individuals? Rawls and those influenced by him offer at least six different
arguments, concerning: (1) coordination, that dispersed independent agents may be ineffective at
coordinating efforts to achieve collective goals (Rawls, 1993: 268; Cordelli, 2012: 134–7); (2)
Page 12 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
11
nonvoluntariness, that basic structural institutions incur demands of justice because they alone
are imposed nonvoluntarily (Rawls, 1993: 41–2, 277; Rawls, 2001: 20, 40, 55; Julius, 2003;
Nagel, 2005); (3) pervasive impact, that only basic structural institutions pervasively impact the
life prospects of everyone subjected to them (Rawls, 1999: 7, 82); (4) fair burden-sharing, that
only basic structural institutions can ensure that responsibilities for contributing to justice are
fairly allocated (Beerbohm, 2016); (5) value pluralism, that institutions have no “final ends” of
their own, while organizations have their own goals and commitments (Rawls, 1993: 41;
Scheffler, 2005; Cordelli, 2012); and (6) civility, that assigning organizations the responsibility
for securing justice invites excessive polarization and conflict to permeate social and economic
life (Talisse, 2019).
Taken together, these arguments help to explain why Rawlsians regard justice as a
primary responsibility of institutions and not of organizations. Though organizations may indeed
have an important role to play in the pursuit and maintenance of social justice, how that role can
be specified in a way that respects the limitations just noted remains to be seen. In the next
section, we show how this way of thinking can generate a distinctive view of how social
enterprises can advance social justice.
Social Enterprises and Institutional Capacity
The previous section explored the idea that principles of justice apply primarily to
institutions rather than organizations. This section considers how social enterprises can
nonetheless contribute to social justice in ways that acknowledge the primacy of institutions.
Although principles of justice apply in the first instance to institutions of the basic structure,
Rawls holds that individuals and organizations possess a “natural duty of justice” (a duty that
Page 13 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
12
exists independently of any voluntary action or agreement) to contribute in various ways (Rawls,
1999: 98-99). In the abstract, we submit that the natural duty of justice can be understood as a
duty to foster institutional capacity, which we define as the ability of institutions to realize and
maintain fair terms of cooperation at the level of society.
The term “institutional capacity” does not appear in Rawls’s work and lacks a commonly
recognized definition. Healey (1998: 1541) treats institutional capacity as synonymous with
“institutional capital,” which refers to the resources that enable stakeholders to change conditions
in the territory where they live or work. Blomquist and Ostrom (1985: 389) understand
institutional capacity as shared infrastructure for solving collective action problems, which
includes access to information, a forum for communication, cost-sharing, enforcement, and
monitoring. The neighboring term “state capacity” has wider currency, especially in political
science, although definitions vary widely (Cingolani, 2013). Whereas state capacity refers
specifically to the abilities of states, entities that exercise coercive power over a defined territory,
not all the systems of rules comprehended by the term institutional capacity may be directly
under state control. We believe that institutional capacity is a helpful concept for organizational
theory, and a Rawlsian perspective helps us to derive and apply it. While a long tradition of
theorizing in organization studies has regarded institutions as a source of explanation and
constraint for the behavior of social enterprises and organizations more generally (Friedland &
Alford, 1991; Battilana & D’Aunno, 2009; Besharov & Smith, 2011), the concept of institutional
capacity that we derive from Rawls effectively inverts this relationship by indicating how social
enterprises can strengthen and reform institutions—and why this matters.
The duty to foster institutional capacity makes two kinds of demands. When and where
just institutions exist and are stable, organizations and individuals are expected to support and
Page 14 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
13
comply with them (Rawls, 1999: 99). When and where just institutions are undeveloped,
unstable, or corrupt, organizations and individuals must contribute to efforts to facilitate
transitions to just institutions when they can do so at moderate cost (Rawls, 1999: 99; Simmons,
2010). These two conditions are not necessarily mutually exclusive, and both just and unjust
institutions will likely coexist to some extent in every society. A society that is reasonably just
overall may still have many aspects of its institutional configuration that fall short of justice’s
demands. Likewise, a society that is particularly burdened or unstable may still have certain
institutions that satisfy justice’s demands.
The natural duty of justice to contribute to institutional capacity applies to all individuals
and organizations of all kinds (including commercial corporations). However, we claim that
precisely how and how much an agent can be expected to foster institutional capacity may
depend on various factors. These include, among others, the agent’s particular opportunities and
constraints imposed by other duties or legitimate commitments, such as fiduciary duties to
shareholders or owners and whether the agent caused or benefits from unjust institutions (Caney,
2015). Although the strength and direction of agents’ duties of justice depend partly on
contextual factors, focusing on opportunities and constraints shared by agents with similar
features can yield important insights about their potential contributions.
We are especially interested in the specific pathways for fulfilling natural duties of justice
that emerge from examining the opportunities and constraints that social enterprises typically
share. First, we consider how social enterprises might discharge the duty to support and comply
with just institutions. We observe that social enterprises that introduce novel options for work,
consumption, and affiliation can be understood as complementing and supplementing just
institutions by satisfying needs that institutions are categorically ill-equipped to meet. We then
Page 15 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
14
ask how social enterprises might fulfill the duty to facilitate transitions away from unjust
arrangements. Again, we look at the features that distinguish social enterprises from other
entities and consider how these features might create pathways for satisfying this additional
demand of justice. We observe that their flexible forms and use of market-based activity enable
social enterprises to demonstrate just alternatives and incentivize accountability of other actors.
(Figure 1 provides an illustration of the duties and mechanisms associated with this account.)
------------------------------------
Insert Figure 1 about here
------------------------------------
Duty 1: Fortifying Just Institutions
We propose that a Rawlsian perspective may, in fact, carve out distinct spaces for social
enterprises operating under institutional conditions that are reasonably just but imperfectly so. As
certain rights may go unfulfilled by governments and conventional organizations even under
favorable institutional conditions (Mair, 2010), social enterprises may enjoy unique capacities
for complementing just institutions by filling gaps in rights fulfillment. As social enterprises also
create new opportunities for affiliation, labor, and consumption, they may be seen additionally as
supplementing the work of just institutions. By complementing, we mean efforts that complete
the work that institutions already do. By supplementing, we mean efforts that introduce new
opportunities that institutions could not reasonably be expected to offer. We elaborate on these
different mechanisms in sequence.
Complementing just institutions. Work-integration initiatives provide a paradigmatic
example of how social enterprise might complement institutions that are already reasonably just
Page 16 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
15
(Battilana, Sengul, Pache, & Model, 2015; Santos, 2012). Many social enterprises provide
employment opportunities to individuals with challenges to competing in traditional labor
markets due to bodily conditions, educational limitations, or criminal history. Even if a well-
regulated labor market satisfied conditions of fair equality of opportunity (part of Rawls’s second
principle of justice, discussed above), these individuals would still experience substantial barriers
to labor market participation. Although some may benefit from direct assistance schemes that
assure economic security, such measures cannot fully compensate for the costs of labor market
exclusion to individual dignity (Rawls, 1999: 257). Work integration social enterprises (WISEs)
enter here to fill the gap, developing businesses that can achieve viability by drawing upon the
particular assets of these employees. Consider the example of Specialsterne, a social enterprise
that provides employment opportunities for individuals with Autism Spectrum Disorder (Austin
and Busquets, 2008). Even where labor markets are reasonably just, and governments provide
strong support for people with developmental disabilities (by, e.g., prosecuting discrimination,
funding special training, and incentivizing recruitment and accommodation of autistic
employees), individuals with Autism Spectrum Disorder may still lack opportunities for
employment that offer them comparable prospects of economic mobility and self-esteem.
Organizations like Specialsterne help to fill a persistent gap left by just institutions and widen
access to just conditions.
While this perspective suggests that WISEs can help to uphold just institutions under
certain conditions, it does not propose that WISEs are an all-purpose solution to poverty and
unemployment, as enthusiasm about this model may sometimes suggest. Many aspects of labor
market exclusion are consequences of institutional injustice and require institutional solutions.
Compelling people with disabilities to work as a condition of receiving the means of subsistence
Page 17 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
16
recalls the Elizabethan Poor Laws, which made poverty relief for many groups conditional on
laboring (McIntosh, 2005). This approach rejects the idea of a guaranteed social minimum,
which Rawls deems a central requirement of a just basic structure (Rawls, 2001: 126–30).
Nonetheless, a Rawlsian view indicates that WISE models and strategies are desirable in cases
where WISEs have a demonstrable advantage in satisfying rights claims that institutions struggle
to fulfill on their own.
This account also helps us to understand what distinguishes WISEs from other models
associated with social enterprise, such as the practice of buy-one-give-one (“BOGO”). BOGO
models donate a product unit (such as shoes or eyeglasses) to a disadvantaged individual (often
in the Global South) for each unit purchased by a consumer able to pay the retail price (often in
the Global North). These models face criticism for perpetuating social inequalities and
undermining apparel markets and self-governance in lower-income countries, by taking business
away from local apparel manufacturers, depressing job growth, subordinating beneficiaries, and
reducing tax revenue (Frazer, 2008; London, 2014; Jost, 2016). From a Rawlsian standpoint,
such practices are thoroughly questionable for both perpetuating unjust conditions and hindering
the development of just institutions. These observations remind us that social enterprise can
easily fail to satisfy duties of justice and is not justice-promoting simply by definition. And this
is as should be, in our view: to build normative criteria into an empirical definition of social
enterprise risks over-politicizing empirical research and inhibiting nuanced normative appraisal.
Supplementing just institutions. As just discussed, fortifying just institutions may
sometimes require creative combinations of social and market elements. Here, we note that this
understanding of the Rawlsian perspective can also support organizing that uses market means to
support more particularistic ethical commitments. Consider the Sundance Film Festival (Martin
Page 18 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
17
& Osberg, 2007), which seeks to expand opportunities for film production and consumption, and
SEKEM, a social enterprise focusing on biodynamic agriculture in Egypt that runs initiatives for
(e.g.) educational, scientific, and religious pursuits (Rimac, Mair, & Battilana, 2012). The
connection to justice here may at first seem obscure, as these efforts are not heavily
redistributive. Yet Rawls considers it a critical matter of justice for individuals to be able to
exercise their basic liberties and pursue their conceptions of the good under conditions of fair
equality of opportunity. Rawls is aware that the market, even when regulated by principles of
justice, may respond to some preferences better than others and may not provide all the goods
and opportunities that people desire to produce or consume (Rawls, 1999: 249-51). For instance,
conventional firms may not find it profitable to finance and display a large volume of
experimental films. At the same time, Rawls’s work highlights the challenges of using the
coercive power of the state to support the pursuit of different communities’ conceptions of the
good. Some people may prefer to produce or consume independent and experimental cinema;
others may not. As Rawls writes, “There is no more justification for using the state apparatus to
compel some citizens to pay for unwanted benefits that others desire than there is to force them
to reimburse others for their private expenses” (Rawls, 1999: 250). A natural solution, therefore,
is to encourage private organizations that provide those goods which traditional markets fail to
provide but are challenging for states to provide on a fair basis (Lechterman, 2022: 65-7). By
offering new ways of combining different forms and strategies of organizing, a social enterprise
like Sundance offers mechanisms for promoting this important dimension of fairness.
As discussed above, blending purposes and strategies is neither necessary nor appropriate
in all cases. However, the current discussion observes that ensuring fair equality of opportunity
may sometimes benefit from the forms and strategies of organizing that social enterprise offers.
Page 19 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
18
Our view suggests that, from a normative standpoint, blending business with a mission of
cultural, religious, or artistic enrichment is an entirely appropriate purpose of social enterprise.
This insight is relevant for theoretical and empirical research that insists that the enterprise must
be strongly redistributive to count as “social” (Kroeger & Weber, 2014).
Duty 2: Facilitating Transitions to Just Institutions
The foregoing subsection explored the role social enterprise might fill in helping to
realize principles of social justice against a background of favorable institutional conditions.
When and where such arrangements already exist, social enterprises can fill lingering gaps and
expand the supply of valuable options for affiliation, labor, and consumption. Another possibility
comes from contemplating the role social enterprise can assume where just institutions are
undeveloped, unstable, or compromised.
For Rawls, profound institutional injustice comes in two main varieties, which Simmons
classifies as deliberate and unfortunate (Simmons, 2010: 12–18). Deliberate institutional
injustice arises when those who select or administer policies do so in bad faith. Unfortunate
institutional injustice arises when a society lacks the resources to effectively regulate the basic
structure, due to (e.g.) poverty, war, natural disasters, or technological deficits. When institutions
lack the support or the capacity necessary for fully realizing the demands of justice, these
demands may fall partially upon private organizations and individuals. But the way these
demands fall is not direct. Organizations and individuals do not simply inherit institutional
responsibilities, full stop. Rawls is adamant that private attempts to compensate for institutional
injustice face a Sisyphean task (Rawls, 1993: 257–88). At the same time, directing all efforts at
institutional reform contains its own risks, as institutional reform is a long-term and uncertain
Page 20 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
19
project, whose benefits, if or when they materialize, offer little or nothing to people who are
suffering now (Cordelli, 2016; Berkey, 2018). Recent readings of Rawls address this dilemma by
proposing a transitional approach that balances efforts at relieving the symptoms of injustice
with the long-term aim of a just basic structure (Simmons, 2010; Hussain, 2012; Gilabert, 2017;
Barrett, 2020). This includes reforming institutional defects and fostering conditions in which
just institutions can take root. How might the specific features of social enterprise be leveraged
to navigate this tradeoff? We suggest that the organizational flexibility of social enterprise
enables it to demonstrate just alternatives in economic arrangements and market design, while its
ability to harness market forces enables it to incentivize accountability of governmental and
market actors.
Demonstrating just institutional alternatives: economic arrangements. When the
basic structure is unjust, individuals lack the bargaining power to demand fair treatment in the
labor market. Oppressive working conditions are a predictable consequence, where employment
is precarious, and steep inequalities in compensation and authority separate workers from senior
managers. Many social enterprises seek to redress this by piloting cooperative ownership and
management structures that flatten hierarchies, encourage deliberation, and share burdens and
profits more equitably (Rothschild, 2009). Fair trade initiatives—such as FLO International and
Fair Trade USA—respond to similar challenges in a different context. Pervasive inequities in
global supply chains can lead to oppressive conditions for agricultural producers and materials
manufacturers (Bartley & Child, 2014; Reinecke, Donaghey, Wilkinson, & Wood, 2018). Many
social enterprises seek to redress this by committing to paying suppliers above-market prices in
exchange for fairer treatment of their workers.
Social enterprises of both kinds face enduring criticisms. Arguably, the root causes of
Page 21 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
20
workplace injustice and unfair trade are not located at the organizational level but at the level of
institutions. Efforts to compensate for these failures are piecemeal and of limited efficacy. Worst
of all, as paying above-market prices reduces an organization’s capacity to hire more workers or
purchase more supplies, these initiatives may end up harming intended beneficiaries by putting
them out of work entirely (Haight, 2011).
A Rawlsian perspective suggests that social enterprises carrying out these initiatives can
nonetheless have an important role in fostering transitional justice. This perspective sees social
enterprises centered on workplace justice (such as worker-owned cooperatives) as enactments of
public protest that draw attention to the failure of basic structural institutions to create fair
working conditions, as well as proof-of-concept that fairness and productivity can be allies.
Taking a transitional justice lens suggests that the point of workplace justice initiatives is not
only to improve equity among a firm’s stakeholders but also to critique reigning economic
institutions and to demonstrate the viability of alternatives. Similarly, the transitional justice
perspective suggests that fair-trade initiatives cannot satisfy their duties of justice by the benefits
they bring to producers alone. Rather, justice is promoted when their work can be seen as
protesting the general unfairness in global trade and the need for institutional reform to set things
right. This perspective shifts attention from the direct and immediate effects of these initiatives
on individuals and towards their indirect and longer-term effects on the basic structure.
This argument only applies insofar as social enterprises in these areas engage in practices
that are consistent with the aim of reforming economic institutions. Most social enterprises
focused on workplace justice and fair trade do not generally treat justice in the workplace
fairness in international trade as matters of taste, like ice cream flavors. Rather, they seek a world
where all workplaces and all trade operate on fair terms. A social enterprise that acted otherwise
Page 22 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
21
in word or deed, such as by categorically opposing treaties to establish minimum standards for
labor or trade, would be failing to discharge its natural duty of justice, at least in this way.
Demonstrating just institutional alternatives: market design. While a Rawlsian
perspective does not suggest that markets are an appropriate mechanism for producing and
distributing all goods, it does suggest that markets are a reasonable mechanism for organizing
many areas of economic activity when suitably regulated by principles of justice (Rawls, 1999:
238–42). Another way that social enterprises might discharge duties of transitional justice is by
structuring and expanding access to markets for marginalized populations (Mair, Martí, &
Ventresca, 2012; Thornton, Gonas, & Lohrke, 2015). Conventional business firms often find it
disadvantageous to market products to impoverished regions despite latent demand. As a result,
these regions either depend on donations or forego important necessities or conveniences. Social
enterprises that deliver high-quality but low-profit consumer appliances in India (Bauer, 2011),
electricity in Sierra Leone (Munro et al., 2016), or waste management in Bangladesh (Seelos &
Mair, 2007) to individuals who lack reliable access to them foster the creation of sustainable
markets for these goods. Their efforts can pique consumer interest, erect initial infrastructure,
cultivate supply chains, and catch the eye of investors.
For instance, the EnviroFit cookstove was initially introduced in 2007 as an affordable
and healthier alternative to open-fire cooking in the Global South (Bauer, 2011). Within a few
years, it helped spur a competitive market for safe and affordable cooking appliances, which
includes global firms like Philips (Subramanian, 2014). Alternatively, consider the example of
Greyston Bakery, whose open hiring model seeks to make employment more accessible to
workers missing conventional markers of employability, such as educational degrees and
reference letters (Pirson and Livne-Tarandach, 2020). The virtues of this model caught the
Page 23 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
22
attention of major firms like the Body Shop, which have integrated it across their operations.
While these initiatives may have positive effects on their initial beneficiaries, what
ultimately promotes justice from a Rawlsian perspective is their indirect effects on broader
market conditions. In some cases, succeeding in this way may threaten the market position of the
social enterprise, forcing a change in strategy or even dissolution. As we discuss further below,
this perspective reveals that social enterprises’ tendencies toward mission drift and transience,
which are common sources of criticism in the literature, may sometimes be sources of strength
from the standpoint of justice. Once a competitive market matures, and the original need for
social enterprises like EnviroFit or Greystone disappears, a shift in strategy or dissolution might
better support the demands of justice.
Clearly, this argument will not apply to social enterprises that engage in behaviors that
are inconsistent with encouraging more equitable market institutions, such as by seeking an
endowment to operate indefinitely or taking steps to resist or discourage competition. Such
organizations would be failing to discharge their natural duty of justice, at least in this way
(though, conceivably, they might satisfy it in others).
Incentivizing just institutions: government accountability. A transitional justice
perspective also indicates a role for social enterprise in encouraging institutional reform through
indirect incentives. Consider microcreditors, which seek to respond to the lack of access to
capital in poor regions by offering individuals small loans. Once heralded as one of the most
promising solutions to global poverty (Banerjee et al., 2015), microfinance has since come under
scrutiny for its varied track record, exploitative tendencies, and unintended consequences (Butt,
2015). Evidence of the benefits of microfinance remains mixed, as such initiatives rarely reach
the poorest individuals, and default rates remain high. Initiatives that seek to profit from the
Page 24 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
23
satisfaction of individuals’ basic needs may often be exploitative by taking advantage of their
desperate circumstances to extract unfair contractual terms. Pressure to repay debts has led to
alarming stories of depression and suicide. Nonetheless, under the right conditions, such
initiatives may encourage transitional justice through more indirect mechanisms. Even if the
direct benefits of microcredit are limited to the lower-middle class, rather than the very poorest,
these benefits can positively affect the lives of the very poorest. As Ronzoni and Valentini argue,
the minority of individuals who do benefit from microcredit are likely to acquire an enhanced
position to mobilize politically and to hold institutions accountable (Ronzoni & Valentini, 2015).
To earn the support of this growing bloc, officials must rein in corruption and improve the
supply of public goods. But the value of increased institutional accountability also redounds to
the very poorest, who likewise stand to benefit from the rule of law and the expanded supply of
public goods. Thus, whether or not microfinance can be justified as a direct solution to poverty, a
transitional-justice perspective sees potential in microfinance as an indirect solution to injustice
that works through the basic structure.
This argument indicates that social enterprises can discharge their natural duty of justice
when strengthening government accountability is a foreseeable byproduct of their activities.
Where strengthening government accountability is not a foreseeable byproduct, social enterprises
may be failing to discharge their natural duty of justice in this way (though some may be able to
satisfy it in other ways).
Incentivizing just institutions: market accountability. Finally, competition from social
enterprises might perform an important disciplining effect on conventional markets. Traditional
firms that encounter competition from social enterprises offering higher quality or lower price
goods face pressure to justify their profit margins and to reconsider business practices that result
Page 25 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
24
in obvious injustices (Galle, 2013). The introduction of cooperatives into the funeral industry in
Québec offering affordable funeral services led commercial providers to cut prices and helped to
reduce inequalities in access to funeral services (Audebrand & Barros, 2018: 9). Similarly, the
emergence of social enterprise models into a field dominated by charities might threaten
incumbents who have made a business out of convincing donors that a valuable service is not
sustainable through sales revenue. Competition from social enterprise rivals may pressure
underperforming incumbents to seek improvements in quality or access.
To be sure, the competitive pressure that social enterprises place on traditional firms and
charities also has its drawbacks. While some charities may certainly benefit from pressure to
adopt alternative revenue streams, profitable goals and strategies may be inappropriate or
inefficacious for the provision of certain goods. Pressure on healthcare charities in Scotland from
social enterprise rivals has resulted in reductions of care quality and access (Henderson, Reilly,
Moyes, & Whittam, 2018). For-profit firms under pressure from social enterprises may be
tempted to respond by ethics washing, i.e., by conveying the impression of serving social justice
without actually investing in it (Voinea & Uszkai, 2020); or they may parachute cavalierly into
sensitive domains where their efforts do more harm than good (MacAskill, 2015). Thus, social
enterprises that seek to compete with conventional firms or charities may not always succeed in
satisfying their natural duty of justice through this mechanism.
Discussion
This article seeks to clarify the possible contributions of social enterprise to social justice
by leveraging insights from Rawls’s political philosophy. We introduced institutional capacity as
a construct implicit in Rawls that indicates pathways for organizations to serve as agents of
Page 26 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
25
social justice. Institutional capacity refers to the ability of institutional arrangements to realize
and maintain fair terms of cooperation at the societal level. Examining social enterprises through
this lens led us to explore how social enterprises can contribute to social justice in different
institutional contexts—and why this might be normatively desirable. They can fortify existing
just institutions and facilitate transitions to just institutions when and where they are missing,
unstable, or compromised. We proposed complementing and supplementing as two mechanisms
that allow social enterprises to fulfill the role of fortifying just institutions. We proposed that
social enterprises can facilitate transitions to just institutions through mechanisms of
demonstration and incentivization. They can demonstrate alternatives to economic arrangements
and market design, and they can act in ways that incentivize greater accountability for
governments and markets alike. See again Figure 1 for a summary of these claims.
Clarifying the Role of Social Enterprise in Society
A central objective of this article is to highlight the relevance of political philosophy for
organizational research. Although aspects of our theory apply to organizations more broadly, we
deliberately focused on the study of social enterprise as a phenomenon in further need of
theorizing and as a research area and field of practice characterized by conceptual ambiguity
(Chliova, Mair & Vernis, 2020) and empirical variety (Mair, 2020). Our view helps scholars to
bring society back into theorizing and to reconcile competing ideological frames. Political
philosophy helps to justify and appraise the work of social enterprise, but, as we have suggested,
it is equally helpful for reflecting on how social enterprises work and with what consequences. In
our case, the duties and mechanisms we identify explain how social enterprise can contribute to
social justice and deepen our understanding of how it directly and indirectly affects macro-
Page 27 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
26
institutional arrangements. This social justice lens allows debate to advance beyond
overworked—and normatively charged—arguments about the role of social enterprise as fixes
for market and government “failure” (Weisbrod, 1975). It sees social enterprises as occupying a
nuanced and multifaceted role in relation to institutions: filling temporary voids and weaknesses
in institutional arrangements (Mair & Martí, 2009), as well as serving as institutional reformers
and partners. Thus, normative theory complements and extends attempts to theorize social
enterprise from positive perspectives (Santos, 2012; Galle, 2013; Thornton, Gonas, & Lohrke,
2015).
Additionally, the normative arguments advanced in this article provide a basis for
reconciling enthusiasm about social enterprise with persistent challenges. Organizational
theorists have long worried that the blending of disparate goals leads to a clash of institutional
logics (Thornton, Ocasio & Lounsbury, 2012; Besharov & Smith, 2014), resulting in internal
conflict (Pache & Santos, 2010), mission drift (Ebrahim, Battilana, & Mair, 2014), or
organizational collapse (Tracey, Phillips, & Jarvis 2011). However, warnings about
organizational instability make the most sense if organizational constancy and survival can be
defended as worthwhile goals. One implication of our argument is that an important role of
social enterprises is transitional, rather than indefinite. As a result, mission drift or organizational
failure may sometimes be innocuous or even beneficial consequences for society. This insight
responds to the recent call from organizational scholars for “upstream” research on
organizational missions by offering a macro-level account of organizational roles (Varendh-
Mansson, Wry, & Szafarz, 2020; Grimes, Williams, & Zhao, 2020).
Another source of apprehension comes from critical social theorists, who denounce social
enterprise for privatizing essential matters of public concern and commodifying goods—like
Page 28 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
27
education and care-giving—that demand non-market modes of provision (Dey & Steyaert, 2012;
Giridharadas, 2018; Spicer, Kay, & Ganz, 2019). A puzzle for this line of critique is that support
for social enterprise is not limited to neoliberal apologists: varieties of social enterprise have long
occupied a central role in social-democratic reform blueprints (Rothschild, 2009; Wright, 2010;
Unger, 2015). By proposing a more nuanced conception of the role of social enterprise, our
argument supplies a way to reconcile these contradictory viewpoints. Our account portrays
privatization and commodification as objectionable when they are inconsistent with fortifying
just institutions and fostering transitions to just institutions. However, in the context of social
enterprise, private measures and profitable activity can also be normatively desirable when they
complement, supplement, or facilitate progress toward just institutional arrangements.
Advancing Institutional Perspectives on Social Enterprise
Our article and the Rawlsian perspective we adopt informs organizational research that
specifically applies an institutional lens to study social enterprise, hybrid organizing, and
innovative organizing more generally (Padgett & Powell, 2012) and to assess the role of
organizations in society. First, our framework encourages scholars to complement the focus on
combinations of organizing elements and hybridity at the organizational level (Pache & Santos,
2010; Battilana & Lee, 2014) with a focus on just institutions at the societal level. Future studies
could expand the scope of research on social enterprise as hybrid organizing and explore, for
example, how tradeoffs and conflicts resulting from incompatible logics entrenched in
organizational structures and practices facilitate or hinder institutional capacity as portrayed in
this article. Second, our findings inform organizational research that investigates how formal and
informal institutions affect the prevalence and legitimacy of social enterprise. Researchers have
Page 29 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
28
built on institutional economics, cultural theory, and varieties-of-capitalism theory to examine
how institutional context affects social enterprise (Stephan, Uhlaner, & Stride, 2015; Kerlin,
2010; Kibler et al., 2018). The framework we put forward in this article, which distinguishes
between just and unjust conditions, helps to diagnose different manifestations of injustice and
adds nuance to existing understandings of the relationship between social enterprise and its
institutional contexts. Our findings provide impetus for research on how social enterprise affects
institutions at multiple levels. Research in this tradition has shown that addressing social
problems that are often deeply embedded in local institutional arrangements results in altering
local institutional conditions (Mair, Martí, & Venstresca, 2012; Venkataraman et al., 2016). The
framework introduced here can help to expand inquiry to include how transformation efforts at
the local level effect change at the level of the basic structure of a society.
The arguments and conceptual framework introduced in this article also inform and
contribute to institutional perspectives in organizational studies more broadly. Dominant
institutional perspectives in organizational and management theory view organizations as caught
in traps of embedded agency (Battilana & D’Aunno, 2009), institutional complexity (Pache &
Santos, 2010; Greenwood, Raynard, Kodeih, Micelotta, & Lounsbury, 2011; Pache & Santos,
2021), and competing logics (Besharov & Smith, 2014). Studies associated with these
perspectives have highlighted how the plurality of institutional logics and values in society
complicate organizational life, shape organizational identity, and hamper organizational
effectiveness (e.g., Lounsbury, Steele, Wang, & Toubiana, 2021). By contrast, the perspective
we articulate provides a basis for assessing competing institutional logics, by helping to prioritize
amongst competing institutional demands and evaluating the normative force of those demands.
It treats value pluralism not as a regrettable contingency that organizations must suffer grimly
Page 30 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
29
but as a normative ideal that creates the very conditions for organizational flourishing. As
alluded in the previous section, our perspective also questions implicit commitments in
organization studies to mission persistence and organizational survival as overriding goals. This
account thus enables a shift from the current focus on organizations as victims of institutional
pressures toward questions of how organizations might actively support a just institutional
ecosystem.
Our framework can guide future research interested in how social justice is enhanced or
compromised by different pathways of institutional change or by the emergence, crossing, and
transition of organizational forms. In addition, considering social justice as a primary
responsibility of institutions can help to expose unintended or undesired consequences of
organizational activity directed at changing systems (Mair & Seelos, 2021) or positive social
change (Stephan et al., 2016) and encourage empirical studies engaging literatures on
institutional entrepreneurship (Battilana, Leca & Boxenbaum, 2009), institutional work (Suddaby
& Lawrence, 2006), and institutional change (Micelotta, Lounsbury & Greenwood, 2017) to
more explicitly examine unintended and undesired consequences.
The concept of institutional capacity we introduced is relevant to future research both
theoretically and analytically. While the term itself does not appear in Rawls and has no
commonly accepted or predominant definition, from a Rawlsian perspective, institutional
capacity can be conceptualized as the ability of institutions to realize and maintain fair terms of
cooperation. Our study helps to theorize and empirically assess how organizations can both
strengthen and weaken institutional capacity. Although we specifically focus on social
enterprises in this article, future work might examine and compare the contributions to
institutional capacity from other forms of organizing, including hybrids, innovative
Page 31 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
30
organizations, nonprofits, and firms (e.g., Brakman Reiser, 2010; Rawhouser, Cummings &
Newbert, 2019), and how conventional firms and nonprofits respond to pressure from social
enterprise rivals through the mechanisms we have theorized.
Finally, our study offers insights for practice. Practitioners have long struggled with how
to conceptualize and measure performance and impact. Our study invites funders, investors,
regulators, managers, and beneficiaries to consider, and further operationalize, institutional
capacity as an object of performance assessment. This approach would direct assessment to place
greater emphasis on the indirect, longer-term, and wider effects of organizing activities on
institutions and their abilities to promote and maintain conditions of social justice. Such an
approach would also speak directly to growing interest among social entrepreneurs, investors,
and funders in notions of system change as a replacement for or complement to improvements in
individual wellbeing (Mair & Seelos, 2021; Seelos, 2020).
Conclusion
Organizing that combines social and market elements in different ways and degrees
continues to generate excitement among theorists and professionals. Whether and how these
trends can be justified and appraised remains an urgent topic of research. Many have seen social
enterprise as a promising response to social injustice, but a failure to interrogate and defend
normative assumptions limits further progress on this and related topics. We have sought to meet
this challenge head-on by extending ideas from the Rawlsian tradition, which offers particular
insight into the relationship between organizing and its institutional setting. Seen through this
lens, social enterprises can be graded against their success in promoting institutional capacity by
fortifying existing just institutions and fostering transitions to just institutions in contexts where
Page 32 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
31
they are missing, weak, or compromised. We have explored how this account connects to
ongoing debates in positive theory and broadens discussions on a range of topics.
Our account comes with certain limitations. It represents an original interpretation of a
Rawlsian perspective that draws on major themes in Rawls and several developments in work by
others influenced by his views. Yet, Rawls’s work is expansive and can give rise to numerous
conflicting interpretations depending on the elements one chooses to highlight and how one fills
in gaps and resolves conflicting ideas. Alternative ways of assembling Rawlsian ideas may find a
different role for social enterprise—or none at all. Interpretations aside, some readers may also
reject core premises of Rawlsian theory that make institutions central to justice. Prominent critics
allege that Rawls’s institutional division of labor offers a utopian blueprint that makes the best
the enemy of the good (Williams, 2005; Sen, 2009). From this standpoint, persistent injustice
requires entities of all kinds to seek feasible improvements wherever they can. Such a view
would assign social enterprises a duty to promote justice directly rather than self-consciously
work with and through institutions, as we have proposed. Nonetheless, the most feasible paths
are those that least offend the rich and powerful, which may leave the most pernicious sources of
inequality in place (Giridharadas, 2018). A search for feasible local improvements may easily
undermine broader or longer-term gains, as when local development projects succeed at the cost
of decimating fledgling public health and education ministries (Deaton, 2015; Wenar, 2011).
Abandoning ideals, therefore, risks throwing away the compass that guides us through the
inevitable tensions and tradeoffs between different reform objectives. The interpretation of the
natural duty of justice that we develop in this article seeks to acknowledge the demands of
feasibility without forsaking the ideal of just societies undergirded by just institutions. This
position is not without its challenges. But we think it at least deserves further consideration.
Page 33 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
32
Acknowledgements
The authors are pleased to acknowledge financial support from the Fritz-Thyssen Foundation
(project 40.19.0.037PH). We thank Josefa Kindt for research assistance and audience members at
the 2020 Society for Business Ethics annual conference for helpful feedback. We are extremely
grateful to the guest editors and anonymous reviewers for extensive guidance.
References
Aristotle (2014). Nicomachean ethics. (C.D.C. Reeve, Trans.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing
Co.
Audebrand, Luc K., & Barros, Marcelo (2018). All equal in death? Fighting inequality in the
contemporary funeral industry. Organization Studies, 39, 1323–1343.
Banerjee, Abhijit, Duflo, Esther, Goldberg, Nathaniel, Karlan, Dean, Osei, Robert, et al. (2015).
A multifaceted program causes lasting progress for the very poor: Evidence from six
countries. Science, 348, 1260799–1260799.
Barrett, Jacob (2020). Social reform in a complex world. Journal of Ethics and Social
Philosophy, 17, 103–32.
Bartley, Tim, & Child, Curtis (2014). Shaming the corporation: The social production of targets
and the anti-sweatshop movement. American Sociological Review, 79, 653–679.
Battilana, Julie, & D’Aunno, Thomas (2009). Institutional work and the paradox of embedded
agency. In Thomas B. Lawrence, Roy Suddaby, & Bernard Leca (Eds.), Institutional
work (1st ed., pp. 31–58). Cambridge University Press.
Page 34 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
33
Battilana, Julie, Leca, Bernard, & Boxenbaum, Eva (2009). How actors change institutions:
Towards a theory of institutional entrepreneurship. Academy of Management Annals, 3,
65-107.
Battilana, Julie, & Lee, Matthew (2014). Advancing research on hybrid organizing: Insights from
the study of social enterprises. Academy of Management Annals, 8, 397–441.
Battilana, Julie, Obloj, Tomasz, Pache, Anne-Claire, & Sengul, Metin (2022). Beyond
shareholder value maximization: Accounting for financial/social trade-offs in dual-
purpose companies. Academy of Management Review, 47, 237–258.
Battilana, Julie, Sengul, Metin, Pache, Anne-Claire, & Model, Jacob (2015). Harnessing
productive tensions in hybrid organizations: The case of work integration social
enterprises. Academy of Management Journal, 58, 1658–1685.
Bauer, Tim (2011). Enabling market-driven technology (Innovations case narrative: Envirofit
International). Innovations: Technology, Governance, Globalization, 6(3), 93–102.
Beerbohm, Eric (2016). The free-provider problem: Private provision of public responsibilities.
In Rob Reich, Lucy Bernholz, & Chiara Cordelli (Eds.), Philanthropy in democratic
societies: History, institutions, values (pp. 207–25). Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Bentham, Jeremy (1907). An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Berkey, Brian (2018). The institutional critique of effective altruism. Utilitas, 30, 143–171.
Besharov, Marya L., & Smith, Wendy K. (2014). Multiple institutional logics in organizations:
Explaining their varied nature and implications. Academy of Management Review, 39,
364–381.
Page 35 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
34
Blanc, Sandrine, & Al-Amoudi, Ismael (2013). Corporate institutions in a weakened welfare
state: A Rawlsian perspective. Business Ethics Quarterly, 23, 497–525.
Blomquist, William, & Ostrom, Elinor (1985). Institutional capacity and the resolution of a
commons dilemma. Review of Policy Research, 5, 383–394.
Bornstein, David (2007). How to change the world: Social entrepreneurs and the power of new
ideas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Brakman Reiser, Dana (2010). Governing and financing blended enterprise. Chicago-Kent Law
Review, 85, 619–655.
British Council, & Social Enterprise UK. (2022). More in common: The global state of social
enterprise. Retrieved from
https://www.britishcouncil.org/sites/default/files/more_in_common_global_state_of_soci
al_enterprise.pdf.
Brock, Gillian (1998). Are corporations morally defensible? Business Ethics Quarterly, 8, 703–
721.
Butt, Daniel (2015). Microfinance, non-ideal theory, and global distributive justice. In Tom
Sorrell & Luis Cabrera (Eds.), Microfinance, rights, and global justice (pp. 63–83).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Caney, Simon (2015). Two kinds of climate justice: Avoiding harm and sharing burdens. In
Robert E. Goodin & James S. Fishkin (Eds.), Political theory without borders (pp. 18–
45). Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons, Inc.
Cavotta, Valeria, & Mena, Sebastián (2023). Prosocial organizing and the distance between core
and community work. Organization Studies, 44, 637–657.
Page 36 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
35
Chalmers, Dominic (2021). Social entrepreneurship’s solutionism problem. Journal of
Management Studies, 58, 1363–1370.
Child, Curtis (2020). Whence paradox? Framing away the potential challenges of doing well by
doing good in social enterprise organizations. Organization Studies, 41, 1147–1167.
Chliova, Myrto, Mair, Johanna, & Vernis, Alfred (2020). Persistent category ambiguity: The
case of social entrepreneurship. Organization Studies, 41, 1019–1042.
Cingolani, Luciana (2013). The state of state capacity: A review of concepts, evidence and
measures. UNU-MERIT Working Paper Series on Institutions and Economic Growth.
Cordelli, Chiara (2012). The institutional division of labor and the egalitarian obligations of
nonprofits. Journal of Political Philosophy, 20, 131–155.
Cordelli, Chiara (2016). Reparative justice and the moral limits of discretionary philanthropy. In
Rob Reich, Chiara Cordelli, & Lucy Bernholz (Eds.), philanthropy in democratic
societies: History, institutions, values (pp. 244–266). Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Cornelius, Nelarine, Todres, Matthew, Janjuha-Jivraj, Shaheena, Woods, Adrian, & Wallace,
James (2008). Corporate social responsibility and the social enterprise. Journal of
Business Ethics, 81, 355–370.
Deaton, Angus (2015). The great escape: Health, wealth, and the origins of inequality.
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Defourny, Jacques, & Nyssens, Marthe (2017). Fundamentals for an international typology of
social enterprise models. VOLUNTAS: International Journal of Voluntary and Nonprofit
Organizations, 28, 2469–2497.
Page 37 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
36
Dey, Pascal, & Steyaert, Chris (2012). Social entrepreneurship: Critique and the radical
enactment of the social. Social Enterprise Journal, 8, 90–107.
Ebrahim, Alnoor, Battilana, Julie, & Mair, Johanna (2014). The governance of social enterprises:
Mission drift and accountability challenges in hybrid organizations. Research in
Organizational Behavior, 34, 81–100.
Eikenberry, Angela M., & Kluver, Jody D. (2004). The marketization of the nonprofit sector:
Civil society at risk? Public Administration Review, 64, 132–140.
Fayard, Anne-Laure (2021). Notes on the meaning of work: labor, work, and action in the 21st
century. Journal of Management Inquiry, 30, 207–220.
Ferraro, Fabrizio (2018). Going political? Towards deliberative corporate governance. Journal of
Management and Governance, 23, 3–20.
Frazer, Garth (2008). Used‐clothing donations and apparel production in Africa. The Economic
Journal, 118(532), 1764–1784.
Friedland, Roger, and Alford, Robert R. (1991). Bringing society back in: Symbols, practices,
and institutional contradictions. In Walter W. Powell & Paul J. DiMaggio (Eds), The new
institutionalism in organizational analysis (pp. 232–66). Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Galle, Brian D. (2013). Social enterprise: Who needs it? Boston College Law Review, 54, 2025–
2045.
Galston, William A. (2002). Liberal pluralism: The implications of value pluralism for political
theory and practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Page 38 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
37
Gilabert, Pablo (2017). Justice and feasibility: A dynamic approach. In Kevin Vallier & Michael
Weber (Eds.), Political utopias: Contemporary debates (pp. 95–126). New York: Oxford
University Press.
Giridharadas, Anand (2018). Winners take all: The elite charade of changing the world. New
York: Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group.
Greenwood, Royston, Raynard, Mia, Kodeih, Farah, Micelotta, Evelyn R., & Lounsbury,
Michael (2011). Institutional complexity and organizational responses. Academy of
Management Annals, 5, 317–371.
Grimes, Matthew G., Williams, Trenton A., & Zhao, Eric Yanfei (2019). Anchors aweigh: The
sources, variety, and challenges of mission drift. Academy of Management Review, 44,
819–845.
Grimes, Matthew G., Williams, Trenton A., & Zhao, Eric Yanfei (2020). Beyond hybridity:
Accounting for the values complexity of all organizations in the study of mission and
mission drift. Academy of Management Review, 45, 234–238.
Habermas, Jürgen (1996). Between facts and norms. (W. Rehg, Trans.). Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
Healey, Patsy (1998). Building institutional capacity through collaborative approaches to urban
planning. Environment and Planning A: Economy and Space, 30, 1531–1546.
Heath, Joseph (2014). Morality, competition, and the firm. New York: Oxford University Press.
Henderson, Fiona, Reilly, Christine, Moyes, David, & Whittam, Geoffrey (2018). From charity
to social enterprise: The marketization of social care. International Journal of
Entrepreneurial Behavior & Research, 24, 651–666.
Page 39 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
38
Hickey, Colin, Meijers, Tim, Robeyns, Ingrid, & Timmer, Dick (2021). The agents of justice.
Philosophy Compass, 16(10).
Hussain, Waheed (2012). Is ethical consumerism an impermissible form of vigilantism?
Philosophy & Public Affairs, 40, 111–143.
Hussain, Waheed, & Moriarty, Jeffrey (2018). Accountable to whom? Rethinking the role of
corporations in political CSR. Journal of Business Ethics, 149, 519–534.
Jost, Joshua (2016, April 22). Cause capitalism part 2: Giving with one hand. Reuters Events.
Retrieved from https://www.reutersevents.com/sustainability/cause-capitalism-part-2-
giving-one-hand.
Julius, A. J. (2003). Basic structure and the value of equality. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 31,
321–355.
Katz, Robert A., & Page, Antony (2010). The role of social enterprise. Vermont Law Review, 35,
59–103.
Keeley, Michael (1978). A social-justice approach to organizational evaluation. Administrative
Science Quarterly, 23, 272–292.
Keeley, Michael (1984). Impartiality and participant-interest theories of organizational
effectiveness. Administrative Science Quarterly, 29, 1–25.
Kerlin, Janelle A. (2010). A comparative analysis of the global emergence of social enterprise.
VOLUNTAS: International Journal of Voluntary and Nonprofit Organizations, 21, 162–
179.
Kibler, Ewald, Salmivaara, Virva, Stenholm, Pekka, & Terjesen, Siri (2018). The evaluative
legitimacy of social entrepreneurship in capitalist welfare systems. Journal of World
Business, 53, 944–957.
Page 40 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
39
Kroeger, Arne, & Weber, Christiana (2014). Developing a conceptual framework for comparing
social value creation. Academy of Management Review, 39, 513–540.
Lawrence, Thomas B., & Suddaby, Roy (2006). Institutions and institutional work. In Stewart
Clegg, Walter R. Nord & Thomas B. Lawrence (Eds.), The SAGE handbook of
organization studies (pp. 215-254). London: Sage.
Lechterman, Theodore M. (2022). The tyranny of generosity: Why philanthropy corrupts our
politics and how we can fix it. New York: Oxford University Press.
London, C. W. (2014, October 27). Putting the boot in development. The Economist. Retrieved
from https://www.economist.com/free-exchange/2014/10/27/putting-the-boot-in-
development
Lounsbury, Michael, Steele, Christopher W. J., Wang, Milo Shaoqing, & Toubiana, Madeline
(2021). New directions in the study of institutional logics: From tools to phenomena.
Annual Review of Sociology, 47, 261–280.
MacAskill, William (2015). Doing good better: How effective altruism can help you make a
difference. New York: Gotham Books.
Mair, Johanna (2010). Social entrepreneurship: taking stock and looking ahead. In Alain Fayolle
& Harry Matlay (Eds.), Handbook of research on social entrepreneurship (pp. 15–28).
Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Mair, Johanna (2020). Social entrepreneurship: Research as disciplined exploration. In Walter
W. Powell, & Patricia Bromley (Eds.), The nonprofit sector: A research handbook (3rd
ed., pp. 333–57). Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Mair, Johanna, & Martí, Ignasi. (2006). Social entrepreneurship research: A source of
explanation, prediction, and delight. Journal of World Business, 41, 36–44.
Page 41 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
40
Mair, Johanna, Martí, Ignasi, & Ventresca, Marc J. (2012). Building inclusive markets in rural
Bangladesh: How intermediaries work institutional voids. Academy of Management
Journal, 55, 819–850.
Mair, Johanna, & Rathert, Nikolas (2021a). Alternative organizing with social purpose:
Revisiting institutional analysis of market-based activity. Socio-Economic Review, 19,
817–836.
Mair, Johanna, & Rathert, Nikolas (2021b). Let’s talk about problems: Advancing research on
hybrid organizing, social enterprises, and institutional context. Research in the Sociology
of Organizations, 69, 189-208.
Mair, Johanna, & Rathert, Nikolas (2024). A phenomenon-based inquiry of advocacy
engagement of social enterprises. Working paper under review.
Mair, Johanna, & Seelos, Christian (2021). Organizations, social problems, and system change:
Invigorating the third mandate of organizational research. Organization Theory, 2, 1–22.
Mäkinen, Jukka, & Kourula, Arno (2012). Pluralism in political corporate social responsibility.
Business Ethics Quarterly, 22, 649–678.
Margolis, Joshua D., & Walsh, James P. (2003). Misery loves companies: Rethinking social
initiatives by business. Administrative Science Quarterly, 48, 268–305.
Martin, Roger L., & Osberg, Sally (2007). Social entrepreneurship: The case for definition.
Stanford Social Innovation Review, Spring, 29–39.
McIntosh, Marjorie K. (2005). Poverty, charity, and coercion in Elizabethan England. The
Journal of Interdisciplinary History, 35, 457–479.
Page 42 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
41
Micelotta, Evelyn, Lounsbury, Michael, & Greenwood, Royston (2017). Pathways of
institutional change: An integrative review and research agenda. Journal of Management,
43,1885-1910.
Mill, John Stuart (1977). On Liberty (1859). In J. M. Robson (Ed.), The collected works of John
Stuart Mill, volume XVIII: Essays on politics and society part I (pp. 213–310). Toronto:
University of Toronto Press and Kegan Paul.
Miller, Toyah L., Grimes, Matthew G., McMullen, Jeffery S., & Vogus, Timothy J. (2012).
Venturing for others with heart and head: How compassion encourages social
entrepreneurship. Academy of Management Review, 37, 616–640.
Mitchell, Ronald K., Weaver, Gary R., Agle, Bradley R., Bailey, Adam D., & Carlson, James
(2016). Stakeholder agency and social welfare: Pluralism and decision making in the
multi-objective corporation. Academy of Management Review, 41, 252–275.
Munro, Paul, van der Horst, Greg, Willans, Simon, Kemeny, Preston, Christiansen, Ame, et al.
(2016). Social enterprise development and renewable energy dissemination in Africa:
The experience of the community charging station model in Sierra Leone. Progress in
Development Studies, 16, 24–38.
Nagel, Thomas (2005). The problem of global justice. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 33, 113–147.
Norman, Wayne (2015). Rawls on markets and corporate governance. Business Ethics Quarterly,
25, 29–64.
Nussbaum, Martha C., & Sen, Amartya (Eds.) (1993). The quality of life. Oxford: Clarendon
Press.
Page 43 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
42
Pache, Anne-Claire, & Santos, Filipe (2010). When worlds collide: The internal dynamics of
organizational responses to conflicting institutional demands. Academy of Management
Review, 35, 455–476.
Pache, Anne-Claire, & Santos, Filipe (2021). When worlds keep on colliding: Exploring the
consequences of organizational responses to conflicting institutional demands. Academy
of Management Review, 46, 640–659.
Padgett, John F., & Powell, Walter W. (Eds.). (2012). The emergence of organizations and
markets. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Pirson, Michael, & Livne-Tarandach, Reut (2020). Restoring dignity with open hiring: Greyston
Bakery and the recognition of value. Rutgers Business Review, 5, 236–247.
Ramoglou, Stratos, & McMullen, Jeffery S. (2023). ‘Clipping an angel’s wings’: On the value
and limitations of philosophy in management research. Academy of Management Review,
amr.2023.0228.
Rawhouser, Hans, Cummings, Michael, & Newbert, Scott L. (2019). Social impact
measurement: Current approaches and future directions for social entrepreneurship
research. Entrepreneurship Theory and Practice, 43, 82–115.
Rawls, John (1955). Two concepts of rules. Philosophical Review, 64, 3–32.
Rawls, John (1993). Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.
Rawls, John (1999). A theory of justice. Rev. edn. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of
Harvard University Press.
Rawls, John (2001). Justice as fairness: A restatement. (E. I. Kelly, Ed.). Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Page 44 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
43
Reinecke, Juliane, Donaghey, Jimmy, Wilkinson, Adrian, & Wood, Geoffrey (2018). Global
supply chains and social relations at work: Brokering across boundaries. Human
Relations, 71, 459–480.
Rimac, Tomislav, Mair, Johanna, & Battilana, Julie (2012). Social entrepreneurs, socialization
processes, and social change: The case of SEKEM. In Karen Golden-Biddle & Jane E.
Dutton (Eds.), Using a positive lens to explore social change and organizations (pp. 71–
89). New York: Routledge.
Ronzoni, Miriam, & Valentini, Laura (2015). Microfinance, poverty relief, and political justice.
In Tom Sorrell & Luis Cabrera (Eds.), Microfinance, rights, and global justice (pp. 84–
104). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rothschild, Joyce (2009). Workers’ cooperatives and social enterprise. American Behavioral
Scientist, 52, 1023–1041.
Santos, Filipe M. (2012). A positive theory of social entrepreneurship. Journal of Business
Ethics, 111, 335–351.
Scheffler, Samuel (2005). The division of institutional labour. Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society, Supplementary Volumes, 79, 229–253.
Scherer, Andreas G., & Palazzo, Guido (2007). Toward a political conception of corporate
responsibility: Business and society seen from a Habermasian perspective. Academy of
Management Review, 32, 1096–1120.
Saebi, Tina, Foss, Nicolai J., & Linder, Stefan (2019). Social entrepreneurship research: Past
achievements and future promises. Journal of Management, 45, 70-95.
Seelos, Christian (2020). Changing systems? Welcome to the slow movement. Stanford Social
Innovation Review (Winter), 40-47.
Page 45 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
44
Seelos, Christian, & Mair, Johanna (2007). Profitable business models and market creation in the
context of deep poverty: A strategic view. Academy of Management Perspectives, 21(4),
49-63.
Sen, Amartya (2009). The idea of justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University
Press.
Simmons, A. John (2010). Ideal and nonideal theory. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 38, 5–36.
Singer, Abraham (2015). There is no Rawlsian theory of corporate governance. Business Ethics
Quarterly, 25, 65–92.
Smith, Wendy K., Gonin, Michael, & Besharov, Marya L. (2013). Managing social-business
tensions: A review and research agenda for social enterprise. Business Ethics Quarterly,
23, 407–442.
Spicer, Jeremy, Kay, Tamara, & Ganz, Marshall (2019). Social entrepreneurship as field
encroachment: How a neoliberal social movement constructed a new field. Socio-
Economic Review, 17, 195–227.
Stephan, Ute, Uhlaner, Lorraine M., & Stride, Christopher (2015). Institutions and social
entrepreneurship: The role of institutional voids, institutional support, and institutional
configurations. Journal of International Business Studies, 46, 308-331.
Stephan, Ute, Patterson, Malcolm, Kelly, Ciara, & Mair, Johanna (2016). Organizations driving
positive social change: A review and an integrative framework of change processes.
Journal of Management, 42, 1250–1281.
Subramanian, Meera (2014). Global health: Deadly dinners. Nature, 509(7502), 548–551.
Suddaby, Roy (2015). Can institutional theory be critical? Journal of Management Inquiry, 24,
93–95.
Page 46 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
45
Talisse, Robert B. (2019). Overdoing democracy: Why we must put politics in its place. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Thornton, Jeremy P., Gonas, John, & Lohrke, Franz T. T. (2015). The social entrepreneur as
trailblazer: A non-normative role for social enterprise in a market economy. ACRN
Oxford Journal of Finance and Risk Perspectives, 4(4), 145–167.
Thornton, Patricia H., Ocasio, William, & Lounsbury, Michael (2012). The institutional logics
perspective: A new approach to culture, structure, and process. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Tracey, Paul, Phillips, Nelson, & Jarvis, Owen (2011). Bridging institutional entrepreneurship
and the creation of new organizational forms: A multilevel model. Organization Science,
22, 60–80.
Tsoukas, Haridimos K., & Chia, Robert (Eds.). (2011). Philosophy and Organization Theory.
Bingley: Emerald.
Unger, Roberto Mangabeira (2015). The task of the social innovation movement. In Alex
Nicholls, Julie Simon, & Madeleine Gabriel (Eds.), New frontiers in social innovation
research (pp. 233–251). London: Palgrave Macmillan UK.
Varendh-Mansson, Cecelia, Wry, Tyler, & Szafarz, Ariane (2020). Anchors aweigh? Then time
to head upstream: Why we need to theorize ‘mission’ before ‘drift’. Academy of
Management Review, 45, 230–233.
Vedula, Siddharth, Doblinger, Claudia, Pacheco, Desirée, York, Jeffrey G., Bacq, Sophie, Russo,
Michael V., & Dean, Thomas J. (2022). Entrepreneurship for the public good: A review,
critique, and path forward for social and environmental entrepreneurship research.
Academy of Management Annals, 16(1), 391–425.
Page 47 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
46
Venkataraman, Hemalatha, Vermeulen, Patrick, Raaijmakers, Aafke, & Mair, Johanna (2016).
Market meets community: Institutional logics as strategic resources for development
work. Organization Studies, 37, 709–733.
Voinea, Cristina, & Uszkai, Radu (2020). Do companies engage in moral grandstanding?
Presented at the Proceedings of the 14th International Management Conference,
Bucharest. https://doi.org/10.24818/IMC/2020/05.13
Wempe, Ben (2008). Contractarian business ethics: Credentials and design criteria. Organization
Studies, 29(10), 1337–1355.
Wenar, Leif, (2011). Poverty is no pond. In Patricia Illingworth, Thomas Pogge, & Leif Wenar
(Eds.), Giving well: The ethics of philanthropy (pp. 105–131). Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Williams, Bernard (2005). In the beginning was the deed: Realism and moralism in political
argument. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Wright, Erik Olin (2010). Envisioning real utopias. London; New York: Verso.
Wry, Tyler, & York, Jeffrey G. (2017). An identity-based approach to social enterprise. Academy
of Management Review, 42, 437–460.
Author biographies
Theodore Lechterman is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at IE University, where he holds the
UNESCO Chair in AI Ethics & Governance. His research focuses on political philosophy and
applied ethics, with particular interests in economic and technological developments. He is the
Page 48 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
47
author of The tyranny of generosity: Why philanthropy corrupts our politics and how we can fix
it (OUP, 2022), an honorable mention for the ECPR Political Theory Prize.
Johanna Mair is Professor of Organization, Strategy and Leadership at the Hertie School. Her
research focuses on how novel organizational and institutional arrangements generate economic
and social development. Mair is also a Distinguished Fellow at the Stanford Center on
Philanthropy and Civil Society, and Co-Director of the Global Innovation for Impact Lab.
Page 49 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
48
TABLES & FIGURES
Table 1: Perspectives on the duties of social enterprises
Primary value
Capabilities
Pluralism
Deliberation
Institutional
Capacity
Duty
Social enterprise
should close
gaps in
individual
wellbeing
Social enterprise
should pursue
multiple goals to
respect diverse
ethical viewpoints
of stakeholders
Social enterprise
should deliberate
with stakeholders
to identify
common aims
Social enterprise
should advance
institutional capacity
by fortifying just
institutions and
fostering transitions
to just institutions
Level of
analysis
Organization
Organization
Organization
Society
Associated
organizational
theorists
Cornelius et al.,
2008; Kroeger
& Weber, 2014
Mitchell et al.,
2016
Scherer &
Palazzo, 2007;
Ferraro, 2018
Current article
Philosophical
inspirations
Nussbaum &
Sen, 1993
Aristotle, 2014;
Galston, 2002
Habermas, 1996
Rawls, 1993, 1999,
2001
Page 50 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
0
Figure 1. How Social Enterprises Can Foster Institutional Capacity
Page 51 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript
Peer Review Version
Institutional Context Institutional Conditions Social Enterprise
Mechanisms Empirical Referents Roles for
Organizations
Imperfect justice
Gaps in rights
fulfillment for hard-to-
serve populations
Complementing Certain WISEs
Fortify just institutions
Limited options for art,
culture, religion,
research
Supplementing
Religiously-affiliated
businesses;
arts/culture social
enterprises
Severe injustice
Injustice in labor
relations or trade rules
Demonstrating
alternative economic
arrangements
Fair trade collectives;
worker-owned
cooperatives
Facilitate transitions
to just institutions
Underdeveloped
markets for essential
private goods
Demonstrating
alternative market
designs
EnviroFit cook stoves
Public corruption;
political exclusion;
undersupply of public
goods
Incentivizing
government
accountability
Certain microcreditors
Consumer exploitation;
negative externalities
Incentivizing market
accountability
Cooperative funeral
services
Institutional
Capacity
Page 52 of 51
Organization Studies
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
DOI: 10.1177/01708406241261435
Author Accepted Manuscript