Content uploaded by Katarina Sklutova Marcincinova
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Katarina Sklutova Marcincinova on May 24, 2024
Content may be subject to copyright.
566
In Memoriam Daniel Dennett (1942 – 2024)
The influential American philosopher and
cognitive scientist, Daniel Clement Dennett,
passed away on 19 April 2024 at the age of 82.1
Daniel C. Dennett was born in Boston,
Massachusetts, in 1942 and came from an
academic background. Dennett’s mother,
Ruth Marjorie (neé Leck), was an English
teacher, and his father, Daniel C. Dennett Jr.,
was a historian of early Islam and a covert
intelligence agent in the Office of Strategic
Services and then the Central Intelligence
Group, the forerunner of CIA (Dennett 2023,
3). Dennett spent part of his childhood in
Beirut, Lebanon, where his father posed as
a cultural attaché to the American Embassy.
However, when his father was killed on
a mission in a plane crash in Ethiopia in 1947,
Dennett moved with his family back to America. In his younger years, he
lived in Winchester, Massachusetts. Dennett described himself as a curious
child who was interested in how things worked, and in his youth, he was
interested in building things – from tree houses to model sailboats. However,
his interests were wide-ranging, and at a young age, he was introduced to
sailing, canoeing, and art studies, which led him to consider becoming
a sculptor. Music also played an important part in his life; he could play the
piano and was especially fond of jazz music.2
Dennett first studied at the Philips Exeter Academy, a preparatory
private, coeducational university, and graduated in 1959. After that, he
studied first at Wesleyan University. However, after reading Willard V. O.
Quine’s From a Logical Point of View (1953), he wanted to confront the famous
1 See Kendall (2024, April 19).
2 In his memoir, Dennett dedicated a chapter to his passion for music, which he pursued
as a hobby during college. See Dennett (2023, Chapter two).
FILOZOFIA
Volume 79, Number 5, 2024
OBITUARY
Foto: Wikimedia Commons
FILOZOFIA 79, 5 567
American philosopher about the philosophical problems raised in the book.3
Therefore, after one academic year, he transferred to Harvard University,
where he was a student of Quine and received his BA in philosophy in 1963.
His honors thesis was called “Quine and Ordinary Language,” in which he
criticized Quine’s attempt to “regiment” ordinary language (Dennett 2023, 43).
However, Quine heavily influenced Dennett’s philosophy. Dennett wrote:
Years later I think I have finally figured out what it was about Quine that
inspired me: he wanted to fix what was broken in the way philosophical
problems were being explored. He didn’t believe in “real magic” and
thought he could diagnose a major misstep that was taken for granted by
almost all philosophers (Dennett 2023, 29).
After Harvard, Dennett studied at Hertford College, Oxford, and he received
a DPhil in philosophy in 1965. Oxford was then the “epicenter” of ordinary-
language philosophy,4 and Dennett wrote his dissertation under the super-
vision of the influential British philosopher Gilbert Ryle. The title of
Dennett’s dissertation was The Mind and the Brain: Introspective Description in
the Light of Neurological Findings: Intentionality, he later published the work as
one of his first and most important books, Content and Consciousness (1969).
Many philosophers and scholars inspired his dissertation, but one of the most
influential was Ryle. As Dennett acknowledges, he was particularly inspired
by Ryle’s writings, which gave many examples and analogies “to unsettle
readers’ lazy imaginations” (Dennett 2023, 67). Dennett, thus, talks about the
influence of Quine and Ryle: “I’m what you get when you cross a Quine with
a Ryle” (Dennett 2023, 67).
It was during his Oxford studies that Dennett’s fascination with the
sciences was sparked, particularly with neurophysiology and neuroanatomy.
He describes the moment when his friend, John Graham, first introduced to
him what neurons were and how they were connected to networks. This
experience led him to the hypothesis that such networks could learn by a kind
of evolutionary process within the brain, the core idea that he further
developed in his dissertation and later works (Dennett 2023, 45 – 46, 64).
During his Harvard Studies, Dennett met his wife, Susan Bell Dennett,
whom he married in 1962. They had two children together, a son and
a daughter. Dennett’s first position was as an assistant and then associate
3 See Dennett (2023, 29 – 30).
4 Dennett notes that Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations were the bibles for students,
including partially himself. See Dennett (2023, 52 – 53).
568
professor in the philosophy department at the University of California, Irvine,
from 1965 to 1971. Dennett and his wife then moved back to the East Coast,
where he took a tenure position at Tufts University in Massachusetts, where
he taught almost his entire career. At Tufts, he was a director for the Center
for Cognitive Studies and was recently granted the honorary title of emeritus
professor. He was also a visiting professor at Harvard University, the University
of Pittsburg, Oxford University, and more. In recent years, he has lived with
his wife in Cape Elizabeth, Maine, until his passing.
Dennett wrote hundreds of articles5 and dozens of influential books,
including Content and Consciousness (1969), Consciousness Explained (1991),
Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life (1995), Freedom
Evolves (2003), Sweet Dreams: Philosophical Obstacles to a Science of Consciousness
(2005), Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon (2006), From Bacteria
to Bach and Back: The Evolution of Minds (2017), and many more. In his books,
Dennett formulated naturalistic views on intentionality, consciousness, free
will, religion, and morality. He was also interested in the theory and science
behind artificial intelligence and participated in evolutionary debates. Dennett
is known for avoiding the use of traditional philosophical terms, preferring to
formulate his own, such as “intentional stance,” “hetero-phenomenology,”
“intuition pumps,” etc. Dennett received several honors for his work, the most
notable of which was the Erasmus Prize, the Netherlands’ highest honor, which
he received in 2012.6
Dennett’s philosophy (or philosophical method) can be characterized by
one of his favorite quotes from Lee Siegel’s book, where Siegel made a
distinction between “real magic” and real magic:
“I’m writing a book on magic,” I explain, and I’m asked, “Real magic?” By
real magic people mean miracles, thaumaturgical acts, and supernatural
powers. “No,” I answer: “Conjuring tricks, not real magic.” Real magic, in
other words, refers to the magic that is not real, while the magic that is real,
that can actually be done, is not real magic (Siegel 1991, 425).
Dennett pointed out in his writings that in contemporary philosophy,
philosophers want to preserve “real magic” instead of explaining how tricks
are done, as in stage magic, in which magicians show us a set of tricks that
achieve an apparent magical effect. In his memoir, Dennett (2023, xx) said that
5 See the whole list: https://sites.tufts.edu/cogstud/dan-dennett-recent-work/ (Accessed 7.
5. 2024).
6 See https://erasmusprijs.org/en/laureates/daniel-dennett/ (Accessed 7. 5. 2024).
FILOZOFIA 79, 5 569
his guides and heroes were precisely the scientists and philosophers who
wanted to explain the tricks behind magic; he named them the “anti-
philosophers,” who were “not just skeptics and debunkers but constructive
explainers, groping for models or theories to replace the armchair verities of the
philosophers with testable ideas” (Dennett 2023, xx).
I think that Dennett can also be characterized as a “philosophers’
antiphilosopher.” His philosophy can be understood as a project of
demystifying phenomena that, even today, are considered magical and
beyond the grasp of scientific research. He criticized traditional thinking
about the “big” philosophical problems, such as the “mind-body problem” or
the so-called “hard problem of consciousness.” He considered them pseudo-
problems by pointing to persistent intuitions, which he called “intuition
pumps,” still present in philosophical and scientific discussions.7 For
example, in his book Consciousness Explained (1991), Dennett introduced
“Cartesian Materialism” – a persistent view that there is a central place in the
brain (“Cartesian Theatre”) where the contents of experience are presented
for the subject (Dennett 1991, 107). While no one currently subscribes to this
view, Dennett argued that even today, many theorists – philosophers and
scientists – start from its assumptions and intuitions.
Dennett, therefore, knew the importance of asking good philosophical
questions and, hence, the important part philosophy plays in scientific
inquiry. In the book Darwin’s Dangerous Idea (1995), he wrote:
Scientists sometimes deceive themselves into thinking that philosophical ideas
are only, at best, decorations or parasitic commentaries on the hard, objective
triumphs of science, and that they themselves are immune to the confusions
that philosophers devote their lives to dissolving. But there is no such thing as
philosophy-free science; there is only science whose philosophical baggage is
taken on board without examination (Dennett 1995, 21).
This was, however, often ignored by Dennett’s critics. Because he criticized
traditional philosophical approaches about the mind, consciousness, or free
will, Dennett was often called an eliminativist, behaviorist, or even a proponent
7 “Intuition pump” is Dennett’s term for philosophical thought experiments that support
intuitions or common understanding of certain phenomena. He includes Frank Jackson’s
“Knowledge argument” or John Searle’s “China Room” among such intuitions. However,
Dennett considered some “intuition pumps” useful thinking tools, but not these ones. See
Dennett (2013).
570
of “scientism,” the idea that hard science (i.e., physics, chemistry) and the
scientific method are the only way to render truth about the reality.
However, this would be a misinterpretation of Dennett’s philosophy.
His main aim was not to eliminate but to demystify these phenomena by
formulating a naturalistic account of them. In other words, Dennett was not
just a skeptic and debunker, but most importantly, he was a naturalist. This is
particularly evident in Dennett’s philosophy of mind, characterized by an
interdisciplinary approach to explaining the mind and consciousness,
drawing on work from philosophy, cognitive sciences, neurosciences, and
evolutionary biology.
In his most important book, Content and Consciousness (1969), he formu-
lated an account of intentionality, an “intentional stance,” the idea that we
automatically adopt the strategy of treating another complicated object (i.e.,
a human, an animal, or a machine) as a rational agent that possesses mental
states such as beliefs and whose actions and behavior can be predicted based
on the content of these states. The “intentional stance” or “intentional strategy”
is one of the key elements of Dennett’s philosophy, and his understanding of
intentionality is closely related to his understanding of consciousness.
In his famous book Consciousness Explained (1991), Dennett formulated
his naturalistic theory of consciousness. Here Dennett proposed the “Multiple
Drafts Model” as an alternative to Cartesian Materialism, and which he later
renamed the “Fame in the Brain.” At the heart of this model is the hypothesis
that the brain does not have a single, coherent stream of consciousness (there
is no “Cartesian Theatre”); rather, the brain generates multiple, parallel
“drafts” or interpretations of experiences. These drafts are continuously
revised and updated as new information is processed. A key feature of this
model is that this unconscious process is competitive in nature, and only some
information becomes famous, and therefore conscious enough to be available
to other cognitive functions (“Fame in the brain”). Dennett’s model bears
many similarities with the so-called “global workspace theories,” which are
now considered among of the leading theories of consciousness.
In Consciousness Explained, Dennett also proposed a method to study
consciousness called “heterophenomenology.”8 Heterophenomenology consists
of the scientist recording the subjects’ introspective beliefs to create a pre-
theoretical description of conscious experience as it appears to the subject
(sometimes referred to as “phenomenology of the other, not oneself”).
8 Dennett first coined this term in 1982. See Dennett (2023, 136 – 137).
FILOZOFIA 79, 5 571
However, we should treat these beliefs as data to be explained by further
empirical research, not necessarily as true accounts of mental reality (Dennett
2023, 136). It should be pointed out, that even though Dennett presented the
term “heterophenomenology,” it is not a new method but a standard
procedure in cognitive sciences and neurosciences (Dennett 2005, 36).
Dennett wrote many influential papers; one of the most well-known is
“Quining Qualia” (1988). In “Quining Qualia,” Dennett rejected the so-called
“qualia,” which refers to the qualitative properties of experience, by
presenting several intuition pumps designed to show that it is an ill-defined
philosophical concept. He elaborated this critique in his other works, pointing
out that neither consciousness nor some of its properties (qualia, “what-it-is-
likeness,” “phenomenal character”) pose the “hard problem” for contem-
porary scientific research. Rather, the “hard problem” lies in the persistent
intuitions that still shape how we think about consciousness. Dennett’s
rejection of the “hard problem” subsequently led Keith Frankish (2016) to
introduce so-called “illusionism,” and Dennett (2016) considered illusionism to
be the “default theory of consciousness.”
Dennett was a proponent of compatibilism regarding free will –
the approach that free will is compatible with determinism. He said,
I believe in free will, in a nonmagical sense that really matters.… I also believe
that this kind of free will is not threatened by determinism…. Determinism
is not a puppeteer controlling you. If you’re a normal adult, you have enough
self-control to maintain autonomy, and hence responsibility, in a world full
of seductions and distractions” (Dennett 2023, xxii).
Dennett thus criticized deniers of free will and recognized the importance of
free will in society, especially in the context of moral responsibility.
In later works, Dennett returned to the ideas he proposed during his
academic career but focused mainly on the evolutionary story behind them.
In one of his latest books, From Bacteria to Bach and Back (2017), Dennett
summarized his evolutionary theory about the mind and consciousness,
drawing on biological and cultural evolution. Regarding evolution, Dennett
was an adaptationist and, therefore, believed that natural selection was a key
element in evolution, for which evolutionary biologist Stephen Jay Gould
criticized him (see Dennett 2023, 363 – 372). In cultural evolution, he was
inspired by memetics theory, first presented by evolutionary biologist
Richard Dawkins in his book The Selfish Gene (1976). In From Bacteria to Bach
572
and Back, Dennett argues that consciousness is a “user illusion,”9 a digested
version of complex cognitive processes that have evolved as a process of
biological (genetic) and cultural (memetic) evolution to play an important
role in monitoring ourselves as well as in communication (Dennett 2017,
Chapter fourteen).
Dennett is also known as one of the “Four Horsemen of New Atheism”
alongside Richard Dawkins, Sam Harris, and Christopher Hitchens. He stayed
an atheist his whole life and criticized religious institutions and practices.
However, even though Dennett was an atheist, he appreciated “goodness” in
the secular world, especially through human action and practices, i.e., through
scientific studies that help improve society (such as curing human diseases), art,
charity, and other ways which humans can contribute to improving the life.
To him, praying for the better was not enough, and he preferred the real over
the symbolic good (Dennett 2023, xviii).
Although Dennett often aroused controversy with his philosophical
ideas, he knew he might be wrong and was a modest and kind human being.
Thanks to philosopher Keith Frankish, I had the privilege to discuss with him
online last year. He made time for me even though it was his birthday, and
we discussed the ethical issues concerning artificial intelligence, especially
language-generating systems, such as ChatGPT.
Dennett’s legacy teaches us to find beauty in the natural world rather
than in supernatural beliefs. I think that this idea can be summarized in one
of my favorite passages: “When we understand consciousness — when there
is no more mystery — consciousness will be different, but there will still be
beauty, and more room than ever for awe” (Dennett 1991, 25).
Katarína Marcinčinová
Bibliography
DAWKINS, R. (1976): The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
DENNETT, D. C. (1969): Content and Consciousness. London: Routledge.
DENNETT, D. C. (1988): Quining Qualia. In: Marcel, A. J. – Bisiach, E. (eds.): Consciousness
in Contemporary Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 42 – 77.
DENNETT, D. C. (1991): Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown and Co.
DENNETT, D. C. (1995): Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meaning of Life. New York:
Simon & Schuster.
DENNETT, D. C. (2003): Freedom Evolves. New York: Viking.
9 Dennett first developed the idea of consciousness as a “user illusion” in Consciousness
Explained (1991).
FILOZOFIA 79, 5 573
DENNETT, D. C. (2005): Sweet Dreams: Philosophical Obstacles to a Science of Consciousness.
Cambridge (MA): MIT Press.
DENNETT D. C. (2006): Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon. New York:
Viking.
DENNETT, D. C. (2013): Intuition Pumps and Other Tools for Thinking. New York: Norton.
DENNETT, D. C. (2016): Illusionism as the Obvious Default Theory of Consciousness.
Journal of Consciousness Studies, 23 (11 – 12), 65 – 70.
DENNETT, D. C. (2017): From Bacteria to Bach and Back: The Evolution of Minds. New York:
W. W. Norton.
DENNETT, D. C. (2023): I’ve Been Thinking. New York: W. W. Norton.
FRANKISH, K. (2016): Illusionism as a Theory of Consciousness. Journal of Consciousness
Studies, 23 (11 – 12), 11 – 39.
KENDALL, J. (2024, April 19): Daniel C. Dennett, Widely Read and Fiercely Debated
Philosopher, 82, Dies. New York Times. [online] Available at:
https://www.nytimes.com/2024/04/19/books/daniel-dennett-dead.html
(Accessed: 7. 5. 2024)
QUINE, W. V. O. (1953): From a Logical Point of View. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University
Press.
SIEGEL, L. (1991). Net of Magic: Wonders and Deceptions in India. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
List of Dennett's work [online]. Available at: https://sites.tufts.edu/cogstud/dan-dennett-
recent-work/ (Accessed 7. 5. 2024).
Erasmus Price [online]. Available at: https://erasmusprijs.org/en/laureates/daniel-dennett/
(Accessed 7. 5. 2024).
This work was supported by the Slovak Research and Development Agency under the
Contract no. APVV-22-0397.
Katarína Marcinčinová
Comenius University
Faculty of Arts
Department of Philosophy and History of Philosophy
Gondova 2 811 02 Bratislava
Slovak Republic
e-mail: sklutova2@uniba.sk
ORCID ID: https://orcid.org/0000-0001-9272-2091