ArticlePDF Available

Ungovernable Counter-Conduct: Ivan Illich's Critique of Governmentality

Authors:

Abstract

Within Michel Foucault's own conceptualization of governmentality, there is little room for something like 'ungovernable life'. The latter seems to hint at a form of social conduct beyond power-relations, which would offend Foucault's basic philosophical postulates. I argue that this identification between governmentality and power as such demonstrates a one-sided focus on the history of Western power-relations. By opposing Foucault's genealogy of governmentality to Ivan Illich's critical history of government, I delineate indigenous struggles against governmentalization as a form of ungovernable counter-conduct. Throughout his books from the 1970s to 1990s, Illich wrote a critical history of government surprisingly similar to Foucault's, from the pastorate to modern political economy. However, rather than merely describing this history, Illich argued governmentalization alienated human beings from their autonomy. As a former missionary priest, he criticized the Church's and modern governments' attempts to subsume populations under a conduct of conducts. He advocated anticolonial resistance to subsumption under Western governmental regimes. In Illich's appreciation of decolonized life, an ungovernable form of life can be discovered, which I defend with the example of Zapatismo and indigenous self-government through mandar obedeciendo.
© Tim Christiaens
ISSN: 1832-5203
DOI:
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51, September 2023
Article reuse guidelines:
https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/
ARTICLE
Ungovernable Counter-Conduct: Ivan Illich’s Critique of
Governmentality
TIM CHRISTIAENS
Tilburg University, Netherlands
ABSTRACT. Within Michel Foucault’s own conceptualization of governmentality, there is little
room for something like ‘ungovernable life’. The latter seems to hint at a form of social conduct
beyond power-relations, which would offend Foucault’s basic philosophical postulates. I argue
that this identification between governmentality and power as such demonstrates a one-sided
focus on the history of Western power-relations. By opposing Foucault’s genealogy of
governmentality to Ivan Illich’s critical history of government, I delineate indigenous struggles
against governmentalization as a form of ungovernable counter-conduct. Throughout his books
from the 1970s to 1990s, Illich wrote a critical history of government surprisingly similar to
Foucault’s, from the pastorate to modern political economy. However, rather than merely
describing this history, Illich argued governmentalization alienated human beings from their
autonomy. As a former missionary priest, he criticized the Church’s and modern governments’
attempts to subsume populations under a conduct of conducts. He advocated anticolonial
resistance to subsumption under Western governmental regimes. In Illich’s appreciation of
decolonized life, an ungovernable form of life can be discovered, which I defend with the example
of Zapatismo and indigenous self-government through mandar obedeciendo.
Keywords: Governmentality, Counter-conducts, Ivan Illich, Decolonization, Zapatismo
INTRODUCTION
The US way of life has become a religion which must be
accepted by all those who do not want to die by the sword
or napalm.
Ivan Illich
Ungovernable Counter-Conduct
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 26
The uptake of Michel Foucault’s legacy in the post-colonial tradition has been somewhat
mixed.
1
On the one hand, Foucault is one of the most-cited Western authors and has
greatly influenced the methodology of post-colonial thought. On the other hand,
Foucault’s own work is remarkably silent about the intersections of power, knowledge,
and subjectivity beyond Europe, and the philosopher has often overlooked the role of the
colonies in shaping Western modernity.
2
One area of Foucault’s philosophy where this
omission of non-Western territories is eye-catching, though rarely acknowledged, is the
treatment of governmentality. While Foucault develops the concept through a detailed
study of European and American discourses about government, he presents
governmentality, or the conduct of conducts, as the main prism for the study of power as
such in his 1982 essay Le sujet et le pouvoir. From a post-colonial perspective, this rhetorical
artifice represents the West’ as a universal telos for the rest of the world. Foucault has
extrapolated his analytics of power from a particularly Western genealogy that moves
within the Judeo-Christian pastorate and the modern State apparatus. However, a sense
for the ‘plural history of power’ beyond ‘the West’ is missing.
3
Other regions in the world
have their own genealogies of power and knowledge which are more diverse than what
fits into the framework of governmentality studies.
4
Is it then necessary to ‘provincialize
Foucault’?
In this paper, I focus on one particular area where Foucault’s privileging of Western
histories might lead him astray: resistance as counter-conduct. Foucault defines the
motivating force behind counter-conducts as a will “not to be governed like that”.
5
This
description assumes that governmental power-relations are an ineluctable given, which
has been true of most Western contexts, but it says little about the territories where the
hold of governmentality might be less firm. How should we conceptualize counter-
conducts that struggle against their subsumption under Western governmental regimes?
Some of Foucault’s followers, like Giorgio Agamben, have attempted to conceptualise an
‘ungovernable’ beyond governmental power.
6
However, since these attempts mostly lack
grounding in concrete practices of resistance, they are often highly abstract and politically
1
For an overview of the post-colonial reception of Foucault, see Stephen Legg, Beyond the European
Province: Foucault and Postcolonialism, in Space, Knowledge and Power, ed. Stuart Elden and Jeremy
Crampton (2007), 26589; Ranabir Samaddar, Michel Foucault and Our Postcolonial Time, in The Biopolitics
of Development: Reading Michel Foucault in the Postcolonial Present, ed. Sandro Mezzadra, Julian Reid, and
Ranabir Samaddar (2013), 2544.
2
Edward Said, Michel Foucault, 1927-1984, Raritan Quarterly 4:2 (1984), 10; Ann Laura Stoler, Race and the
Education of Desire (1995), 51; Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, In Other Worlds: Essays in Cultural Politics (2006),
288.
3
Dipesh Chakrabarty, Provincializing Europe: Postcolonial Thought and Historical Difference (2007), 15. See also,
Stoler, Race and the Education of Desire, 207.
4
See, for example, Partha Chatterjee, More on Modes of Power and the Peasantry, in Selected Subaltern
Studies, ed. Ranajit Guha and Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak (1988), 35190.
5
Michel Foucault, “Qu’est-ce que la critique?, [1978], in Qu’est-ce que la critique? Suivie de La culture de soi
(2015), 37. Translation from Michel Foucault, What Is Critique?," [1978], in The Politics of Truth, ed. Sylvère
Lotringer (2007), 44.
6
Giorgio Agamben, The Kingdom and the Glory (2011), 65.
TIM CHRISTIAENS
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 27
uninformative.
7
In Agamben’s case, the quest for the ungovernable is pursued firmly
within the Western Canon, and it comes eerily close to a messianism that would move
humankind beyond all forms of power. Agamben deviates sharply from a Foucauldian
approach to power-relations as ubiquitous and inevitable. He does not help in exploring
how non-governmentalised forms of power operate beyond the borders of Western
governmentality. In this paper, I approach the issue of ‘ungovernable counter-conducts’
via Ivan Illich’s critique of modern governmental power and his advocacy for indigenous
peoples to resist their subsumption under Western development programmes.
Illich might be a surprising vantage point for ‘provincializing Foucault’. He was a
Catholic missionary-turned-critic who read and admired Foucault’s work and criticised
some of the same institutions that were on Foucault’s research agenda.
8
But he never
wrote about ‘governmentality’ he lived in Mexico during most of Foucault’s career at
the Collège de France and he is generally not considered a post-colonial thinker. However,
those who scan the footnotes of Latin-American post-colonial authors, like Boaventura de
Sousa Santos and Arturo Escobar, find frequent references to Illich. Sousa Santos credits
Illich as one of the main inspirations for the ‘epistemologies of the South’-paradigm and
Illich, in turn, credits a young Sousa Santos as a helpful collaborator in the
acknowledgements to Tools for Conviviality.
9
Illich was also personally involved with
major figures in liberation theology, like Paulo Freire and Helder Camara, even if his
appreciation of liberation theology was ambiguous.
10
From a Latin-American perspective,
Illich is one of the key inspirations of post-colonial thought. Moreover, his own genealogy
of modern government runs surprisingly parallel to Foucault’s. For both thinkers, modern
government derives from Christian pastoral regimes and both view it as a series of
rationalities forged to increase the economic productivity of populations with the help of
statistics and political economy.
I will develop how Illich’s critical history of governmentality leads him to a position
that explicitly delimits the reach of governmentality and supports the claims of
indigenous peoples to resist their governmentalisation. To that purpose, Illich uncovers a
reality of ‘ungovernable counter-conducts’ underexplored by Foucault. I start, in section
1, by highlighting how Illich takes a different stance than Foucault in describing the
medieval struggle between the pastorate and antipastoral counter-conducts. While
Foucault merely describes these antagonisms, Illich actively sides with the antipastoral
7
Arne De Boever, Plastic Sovereignties: Agamben and the Politics of Aesthetics (2016), 189; Tim Christiaens,
Destituent Potential and Camus’ Politics of Rebellion," in Agamben and the Existentialists, ed. Marcus Antonio
Norris and Colby Dickinson (2021), 181.
8
For a biographical overview of Illich’s work, see Todd Hartch, The Prophet of Cuernavaca: Ivan Illich and the
Crisis of the West (2015); David Cayley, Ivan Illich: An Intellectual Journey (2021).
9
Boaventura De Sousa Santos and Steve Brett, A Process of Learning and Unlearning: A Dialogue with
Boaventura de Sousa Santos, 3rd Space. https://3rd-space.org/a-process-of-learning-and-unlearning-a-
dialogue-with-boaventura-de-sousa-santos/?utm_source=rss&utm_medium=rss&utm_campaign=a-
process-of-learning-and-unlearning-a-dialogue-with-boaventura-de-sousa-santos (accessed March 28,
2023).
10
Cayley, Ivan Illich, 57.
Ungovernable Counter-Conduct
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 28
movements and argues that the institutionalised pastorate constitutes a betrayal of
Christianity’s original ungovernable ethos of care for the other.
11
In section 2, I discuss
how Illich’s opposition to pastoral power informs his critique of modern governmentality
and how that differs from Foucault’s. Whereas Foucault seems not to imagine social life
beyond the government/governed-divide, Illich explicitly attempts to differentiate
between different regimes of power, of which governmentality is just one that can
subsequently be negated in favour of other power regimes. With this theoretical
manoeuvre, Illich carves out a space for post-colonial, anti-governmental practices.
As I continue in section 3, Illich deems modern governmentality alienating for human
populations. By surreptitiously steering human conducts in a ‘conduct of conducts’,
governmental elites pursue their own aims by manipulating the desires of the governed.
Individual conducts become vehicles for superimposed governmental projects. People are
thereby nominally free, but their free choices are always already inserted in government
programmes beyond their control. In section 4, I argue that this critique of
governmentality leads Illich to endorse indigenous counter-conducts that resist
subsumption under governmental development programmes. From his experience as an
educator for Catholic missionaries in Latin America, Illich observed the downsides of
well-intentioned development programmes from the global North imposed on
indigenous communities. Indigenous forms of resistance are ‘ungovernable’ in the sense
that they reject Western governmentality in favour of more egalitarian forms of self-
government where power flows more fluidly throughout the community. Rather than
accepting the government/governed-divide and demanding to be governed differently,
they strive for a withdrawal from governmental oversight.
1. PASTORAL POWER AS BETRAYAL
Before we move to the impact of the disagreement between Foucault and Illich on post-
colonial conduct, it is best to closely study the source of this disagreement: their different
stances toward the pastorate. According to Foucault, modern governmentality derives
primarily from the Christian pastorate.
12
Pastoral power in the Church assumes a dividing
line between clergy and laity explained as pastors leading their flock.
13
Pastors are
benevolent guides helping sinful souls to find salvation in God. This task requires intricate
knowledge about the inner conscience of all followers omnes et singulatim and extensive
yet caring power to intervene in the economy of their desires. Christianity consequently
establishes between clergy and laity “the shepherd-sheep relationship as one of individual
11
Ivan Illich, 29.
12
See Sverre Raffnsøe, Marius Gudmand-Høyer, and Morten S. Thaning, Michel Foucault: A Research
Companion (2016), 25865; Stuart Elden, Foucault’s Last Decade (2016), 95100.
13
Michel Foucault, Sécurité, territoire, population: cours au Collège de France, 1977-1978 (2004), 128.
TIM CHRISTIAENS
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 29
and complete dependence”.
14
Believers are suspected of being too morally corrupted to
adequately evaluate the moral worth of their own thoughts.
15
The pastorate subsequently
necessitates rituals of veridiction, like the confession, to make believers speak the truth
about themselves. Thusly, pastors can judge the conformity of believers’ conducts to the
will of God.
16
The pastor thereby ensures the alignment of the believer’s will to the will of
God. He guarantees the ‘mortification of the will’ as an independent force.
17
Foucault does
not mean that pastors actually “kill off” the human will, but they attempt to denude it of
its autonomy. God rather than the sinful individual should determine the will’s impulses.
Pastoral practices continually undermine the innate yet corrupt individual will so that the
believer can openly receive the will of God. The goal is to make the will of God operative
on Earth. God himself stays in the heavens, but His will can realize itself in world-history
if believers voluntarily put aside their own petty desires in favour of enacting the will of
God. People govern their personal conduct on God’s behalf, thereby becoming the
instruments through which God achieves the world’s salvation.
18
As Lorenzini highlights, this configuration of power, subjectivity, and truth grants a
pivotal role to the human will: “the field of [the subject’s] freedom is defined and
structured by his/her acceptance or refusal to be conducted by this particular mechanism, to
let him/herself be conducted in this specific way”.
19
The pastorate requires believers’ wilful
submission to rituals of veridiction and pastoral authority. In Lorenzini’s reading, the will
also lies at the source of pastoral counter-conducts.
20
When individuals choose to suspend
their acceptance of pastoral authority, their conduct becomes recalcitrant and resistant.
21
Counter-conducts arise from a wilful refusal to submit to the pastorate, which is a form
14
Michel Foucault, Omnes et singulatim: vers une critique de la raison politique [1979], in Dits et écrits II.
1976-1988, n. 291 (2001), 964. Translation from Michel Foucault, “Omnes et Singulatim: Towards a Criticism
of Political Reason [1979], in The Tanner Lectures on Human Values (1981), 237.
15
Daniele Lorenzini, The Emergence of Desire: Notes Toward a Political History of the Will, Critical Inquiry
45:2 (2019), 468.
16
Michel Foucault, Du gouvernement des vivants: cours au Collège de France 1979-1980 (2012), 29899; Michel
Foucault, Les aveux de la chair (2018), 138.
17
Foucault, Sécurité, territoire, population, 181; Foucault, Les aveux de La chair, 368.
18
This instrumentalisation as part of God’s government of the world is central to Agamben’s genealogy of
oikonomia. See Giorgio Agamben, Opus Dei: An Archaeology of Duty [2012] (2013), 2122..
19
Daniele Lorenzini, From Counter-Conduct to Critical Attitude: Michel Foucault and the Art of Not Being
Governed Quite So Much, Foucault Studies 21 (2016), 10. See also, Foucault, “Qu’est-ce que la critique?, 66.
20
Lorenzini, The Emergence of Desire, 468.
21
For Foucault’s theory of counter-conducts, see Carl Death, Counter-Conducts: A Foucauldian Analytics
of Protest, Social Movement Studies 9:3 (2010), 23551; Arnold Davidson, In Praise of Counter-Conduct,
History of the Human Sciences 24:4 (2011), 2541; Matthew Chrulew, Pastoral Counter-Conducts: Religious
Resistance in Foucault’s Genealogy of Christianity,” Critical Research on Religion 2:1 (2014), 5565; Lorenzini,
From Counter-Conduct to Critical Attitude,; Martina Tazzioli, Revisiting the Omnes et Singulatim Bond:
The Production of Irregular Conducts and the Biopolitics of the Governed, Foucault Studies 21 (2016), 98
116.
Ungovernable Counter-Conduct
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 30
of ‘voluntary inservitude’.
22
This approach to resistance, which defines it primarily as a
“will to be against”,
23
still leaves ample room for diversity among counter-conducts.
Foucault hence discusses multiple, mutually divergent anti-pastoral counter-conducts in
Sécurité Territoire Population.
24
He deliberately leaves its scope broad to describe a wide
array of practices from mysticism to millenarian popular movements. What these
medieval counter-conducts have in common, for Foucault, is a wilful rejection of
ecclesiastic dimorphism.
25
The power-relations between clergy and laity had, by the late
Middle Ages, become so rigid that parts of the community suspended their wilful
submission to the Church hierarchy. Agamben adds to Foucault’s diagnosis of ecclesiastic
government that the institutionalisation of the Church implied the eclipse of its messianic
promises.
26
The early Church was founded on the belief that the end of times was
imminent. The Church’s duty to govern the Christian community would merely be a
temporary regime for “the time that time takes to come to an end”.
27
During the Middle
Ages, however, the pastorate kept postponing the end of times to the indefinite future and
shifted its focus toward a providential theology that authorised the priesthood as a quasi-
permanent representative of God governing the community in His name. The antipastoral
movements of counter-conducts were, from this perspective, varied attempts to
disestablish the power of the clergy as the sole mediator between God and the community.
Illich’s critical history of pastoral power resonates with these late-medieval
insurgencies, which hints at a difference between his and Foucault’s genealogical projects.
For Foucault, the task of critical philosophy is to write the genealogy of particular
configurations of knowledge, power, and subjectivity, in order to defamiliarize readers
from today’s status quo.
28
By showing the history of the present in all its complexity and
contingency with its struggles, discontinuities, and roads not taken Foucault’s
approach shows that people could be governed differently. For every regime of power
and knowledge, there are resistant counterpowers and counterknowledges.
29
Foucault
himself, however, only delivers the instruments for upsetting the status quo.
30
The goal of
22
Saul Newman, 'Critique Will Be the Art of Voluntary Inservitude': Foucault, La Boétie and the Problem
of Freedom, in Foucault and the History of Our Present, ed. Sophie Fuggle, Yari Lanci, and Martina Tazzioli
(2015), 59.
23
See also Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, Empire (2000), 215.
24
See Foucault, Sécurité, territoire, population, 195232.
25
Sécurité, territoire, population, 206.
26
See especially Giorgio Agamben, The Church and the Kingdom [2010] (2018).
27
Giorgio Agamben, The Time That Remains: A Commentary on the Letter to the Romans [2000] (2005), 67.
28
Michel Foucault, “L’intellectuel et le pouvoir [1981], in Dits et écrits II. 1976-1988, n. 359 (2001), 1569. For
more on Foucault’s approach to critique, see Ben Golder, Foucault and the Politics of Rights (2015), 3337;
Thomas Lemke, Foucault’s Analysis of Modern Governmentality: A Critique of Political Reason [2010] (2019), 363
88.
29
Mitchell Dean, Governmentality: Power and Rule in Modern Society (2010), 21.
30
Golder, Foucault and the Politics of Rights, 37. Admittedly, Foucault did take sides in, for instance, the
struggles of some social movements, like the gay rights movement or the Groupe d’Information sur les Prisons.
He was, however, careful to keep his political activism out of his academic research, even if they concerned
the same topics.
TIM CHRISTIAENS
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 31
genealogical research is to destabilise the present and allow subjects to develop an
‘experimental attitude’ toward the government of themselves.
31
If there is any direct
denunciation of the Christian pastorate in Foucault’s work, it is in L’usage des plaisirs in
1982, where Foucault specifies that Christianity tends to emphasise an ethics based on
moral codes rather than an experimental care of the self.
32
It is an ethics built around
conformity to pre-established laws and rules of conduct expounded and policed by the
clergy. By writing the history of the Church’s conduct of conducts, Foucault wants to
empower his readers to let go of their morally encoded selves (se déprendre de soi-même) to
elaborate new forms of life.
33
His concern is hence not with taking sides in struggles of
conduct like those of the late Middle Ages but with showing the potential variability of
conducts showcased in these struggles. Foucault remains agnostic about which side in the
pastoral struggles represents ‘true Christianity’ because he merely wants to show the
contingency and contestability of the pastorate.
Illich’s interest in the antipastoral struggles is very different from Foucault’s. He sides
with the antipastoral movements and argues that the strict division between clergy and
laity betrayed the founding ethos of Christianity, which is why he pleads for a full
declericalisation of the Church.
34
Illich is not interested in destabilising the present or
fostering experimental subjectivities. He claims a religious potential has been lost and
needs to be re-activated.
35
Although Illich also opposes the Church’s predilection for
moral codes, his focus is not on an experimental ethics of the self but on a salvific ethics
of the other. According to Illich, Christianity stands for an ethics of care and radical
freedom rather than institutionalised submission to the priesthood or libertine self-
stylisation. He illustrates this claim with the parable of the good Samaritan from the
Gospel of Luke.
36
A vulnerable Jew, left for dead by the side of the road, directly calls
upon a Samaritan to come to his aid. This ethical encounter is a visceral experience that
puts the Samaritan before a radically free choice.
37
The Samaritan does not act
automatically through some form of abstract duty legislated by the Church as a moral
code. Nor can the Jew force him to care. Nonetheless, the Samaritan feels the other’s
appeal in his ‘gut’ (splagkhnon). For Illich, “this ‘ought’ is not, and cannot be reduced to a
norm. It has a telos. It aims at somebody, some body; but not according to a rule”.
38
By
affirming the encounter with the other, a visceral community, or mystical body, emerges
31
Michel Foucault, “Qu’est-ce que les Lumières?, [1984], in Dits et écrits II. 1976-1988, n. 339 (2001), 1393. For
a recent discussion of the limits of Foucault’s ethics of the self, see Mitchell Dean and Daniel Zamora, The
Last Man Takes LSD: Foucault and the End of Revolution (2021).
32
Michel Foucault, Histoire de la sexualité II: L’usage des plaisirs (1982), 42. See also Lemke, Foucault’s Analysis
of Modern Governmentality, 287.
33
Foucault, L’usage des plaisirs, 15.
34
Ivan Illich and David Cayley, The Rivers North of the Future: The Testament of Ivan Illich (2005), 84; Ivan Illich,
Powerless Church and Other Selected Writings, 1955-1985 (2018), 108.
35
Cayley, Ivan Illich, 272.
36
Illich and Cayley, Rivers North of the Future, 50.
37
Cayley, Ivan Illich, 263.
38
Illich and Cayley, Rivers North of the Future, 52.
Ungovernable Counter-Conduct
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 32
between both individuals. Two porous and permeable beings let their guard down to
establish a relation with each other. According to Illich, the Church is originally the
community of everyone who has responded to the call for ethical freedom in the care for
the vulnerable other. It is a community of care-relations, independent of ethnic bonds or
moral laws.
39
The believers form a relational web of interdependencies and mutual care.
This is a Church that has neither a strict hierarchy between governing priests and a
governed flock nor a pre-established moral code to legislate the conduct of conducts.
Illich presents a 20th-century insider’s critique of pastoral dimorphism more akin to the
medieval critiques Foucault researched than to Foucault’s own approach. They write
about the same pastoral regimes but from a different standpoint with different aims. A
hierarchical Church institutionalises care with pastoral professionals but destroys the
Samaritan ethos at its own foundation, according to Illich.
40
It grants undue powers to
pastoral elites. The clergy/laity-divide corrupts the priesthood by putting priests into
positions of power that hinder their commitment to self-weakening. They acquire a
monopoly on the allocation of divine grace insofar as all believers have to go through
them to access God’s salvation. Rather than aligning the flock’s conducts to the will of
God, Illich claims that the pastorate aligns conducts with the will of God as interpreted by
the clergy. Ecclesiastic dimorphism thus also turns believers responsible for care-relations
into passive recipients of sacramental services. One attains salvation not by committing
oneself to the presence of God in the vulnerable other but by wilfully submitting oneself
to the rules and guidelines of institutionally sanctioned clergymen. Instead of, for
instance, providing shelter to a pilgrim at the door, one can refuse this embodied
encounter and point the pilgrim to the nearest Church-managed hostel.
41
Sin, in this perspective, is not a transgression of God’s will laid down in Church dogma
or expressed in pastoral moral codes but a failure to live up to one’s commitment to the
ethos of care.
42
For Illich, faith does not depend on the obedient submission to a pastor
but on freely chosen loyalty to the human web of dependencies into which one is thrown.
If the Christian mystical body is born out of care-relations, then a failure to commit to
care-relations signals a breakdown of the mystical body. Belonging to this community
depends not on sacramental rituals of veridiction but on persistently enacting a self-
weakening that opens up the borders of the self for the call of vulnerable others. There is
here a notion of equality missing in the pastorate: everyone is simultaneously a committed
caretaker and vulnerable subject embedded in the same web of care-relations. As in
Foucault’s rendition of pastoral power, Christianity necessitates an ethics of self-
renunciation but by submitting to vulnerable others rather than a pastor.
43
Rather than
39
Rivers North of the Future, 178.
40
Rivers North of the Future, 4748.
41
Rivers North of the Future, 5455.
42
Rivers North of the Future, 82.
43
Illich, Powerless Church, 160.
TIM CHRISTIAENS
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 33
mortifying the will, this requires the activation of the will to actively choose to care for the
other. No one but the individual can make this choice.
2. THE CRITIQUE OF MODERN GOVERNMENTALITY
The notion of modern governmentality plays an ambiguous role in Foucault’s intellectual
development.
44
In his governmentality lectures, Foucault clearly distinguishes
governmentality, or security dispositifs, from other power regimes, such as disciplinary
power or sovereign power. The genealogy is squarely focused on Western Europe and the
United States. Governmentality constitutes just one among many different power regimes
with each their own particular histories and scope. The concept of ‘government’, however,
becomes broader as time progresses and starts to overtake Foucault’s overall depiction of
modern power. In Le sujet et le pouvoir from 1982, for instance, Foucault criticizes his own
earlier war model of power by writing that “basically power is less a confrontation
between two adversaries or the linking of one to the other than a question of
government”.
45
Foucault here takes his description of governmentality as the paradigm
for power as such, without any clear distinction.
46
Power and governmentality
terminologically slide into each other with governmentality and the ‘conduct of conducts’
operating as a theoretical prism for power-relations as such.
47
This terminological shift
also impact Foucault’s understanding of counter-conducts. The focus turns to the
emergence of the modern ‘critical attitude’, which is more than a mere will to be against.
48
The critical attitude is not just a refusal that leaves the scope of alternative conducts open.
Foucault attributes to the critical attitude the search for alternative sources of truth to
criticize governmental practices and propose new governmental rationalities. If
governmentality is the horizon of power as such, then any form of resistance can only be
resistance against one kind of governmentality in favour of another.
44
I leave aside the discussion about the historical affinities between pastoral and state government. Foucault
himself argues for a strict break between medieval and modern government (see Foucault, Sécurité, territoire,
population, 23842.). Governmental rationality becomes detached from its theological context, which locates
the normative source of government in the nature of the universe and the goal of otherworldly salvation.
The aims of modern governmentality are more secular, focusing on economic prosperity and the well-being
of populations. However, there are grounds to doubt Foucault’s plea for discontinuity. Foucault-inspired
researchers in the field of economic theology in particular have suggested that there might be more
continuity between theological and statist notions of government (see Agamben, The Kingdom and the Glory;
Mitchell Dean, The Signature of Power: Sovereignty, Governmentality and Biopolitics (2013); Stefan Schwarzkopf,
ed., The Routledge Handbook of Economic Theology (2021); Tim Christiaens, “Agamben’s Theories of the State of
Exception: From Political to Economic Theology," Cultural Critique 110:1 (2021), 4974.).
45
Michel Foucault, Le sujet et le pouvoir [1982], in Dits et écrits II. 1976-1988, n. 306 (2001), 1056. Translation
from Michel Foucault, The Subject and Power [1982], Critical Inquiry 8:4 (1982), 789.
46
Lemke, Foucault’s Analysis of Modern Governmentality, 323.
47
Foucault, Le sujet et le pouvoir, 1056. Foucault conflates governmentality and power as such also
elsewhere. See, for instance, Foucault, “L’intellectuel et le pouvoir, 1570.
48
Foucault, “Qu’est-ce que la critique?, 60; Lorenzini, From Counter-Conduct to Critical Attitude, 8.
Ungovernable Counter-Conduct
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 34
This approach works very well for European history but not necessarily for struggles
to governmentalize non-European peoples. When Foucault, for instance, provides
European liberalism as an example of the critical attitude, it does not oppose the
hierarchical divide between government and governed but elaborates an alternative,
critical governmental rationality.
49
There is no disagreement on whether the population
should be governed at all (like there was in the colonies). The liberal attitude finds a space
of veridiction in the free market from which it can produce knowledge to criticize
governments’ counterproductive economic interventionism and articulate a better
governmental strategy.
50
Liberalism does not question the government/governed-
hierarchy as such but the actions of this or that specific government. It does not reject
governmentality as such.
51
Taking the ‘critical attitude’ as his vantage point, Foucault’s
attention thus shifts from resistance to government per se to quarrels within the
governmental paradigm itself.
52
By the end of Naissance de la biopolitique, Foucault presents
the political as an internal affair between rivalling governmental rationalities: “What is
politics, in the end, if not both the interplay of these different arts of government with
their different reference points and the debate to which these different arts of government
give rise? It seems to me that it is here that politics is born”.
53
Foucault’s critical philosophy
primarily shows this space of contestation and potentialities for new governmental
rationalities.
Once governmentality defines modern power-relations and counter-conducts become
a competition among opposing governmental rationalities, the notion of ‘the
ungovernable’ or resistance to governmentality as such becomes difficult to imagine. At
the end of his lecture on Qu’est-ce que la critique?, Foucault briefly acknowledges the
possibility of resistance against governmentalisation as such, but he immediately breaks
off the lecture after mentioning this option.
54
If these forms of resistance were to be
interpreted as a revolt against governmentality in general, they could easily be
misunderstood to oppose power itself. In this reading, counter-conducts would aim to
organise a power-free society, which is absurd in Foucault’s philosophy.
55
If
‘ungovernability’ means ‘beyond power’, then ungovernable counter-conducts are
unimaginable. The hypothesis of anti-colonial resistance does not come up. It
consequently would make more sense to view resistance as the will not to be governed
thusly; the will for an alternative government:
49
Mitchell Dean and Kaspar Villadsen, State Phobia and Civil Society: The Political Legacy of Michel Foucault
(2016), 149; Daniele Lorenzini, Governmentality, Subjectivity, and the Neoliberal Form of Life, Journal for
Cultural Research 22:2 (2018), 6.
50
Michel Foucault, Naissance de la biopolitique: cours au Collège de France, 1978-1979 (2004), 3334.
51
Death, Counter-Conducts, 240.
52
Foucault, “Qu’est-ce que la critique?, 65.
53
Foucault, Naissance de la biopolitique, 317. Translation from Michel Foucault, The Birth of Biopolitics: Lectures
at the Collège de France, 1978-79 (2010), 313.
54
Foucault, “Qu’est-ce que la critique?, 65.
55
Lemke, Foucault’s Analysis of Modern Governmentality, 319.
TIM CHRISTIAENS
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 35
I do not think that the will not to be governed at all is something that one could consider
an originary aspiration. I think that, in fact, the will not to be governed is always the will
not to be governed thusly, like that, by these people, at this price. As for the expression
of not being governed at all, I believe it is the philosophical and theoretical paroxysm of
something that would be this will not to be relatively governed.
56
Illich stays relatively closer to the will to be against of medieval counter-conducts and the
aspiration of a society not subsumed under the governmental regime of a priesthood or
its secular descendants.
57
This attitude reflects his divergent critical project. Illich wishes
to uncover an ethics of care lost under institutionalised governmentality rather than
facilitate a struggle between competing arts of government. Though Illich breaks with the
Vatican by the end of the 1960s, his criticisms of modern governmental institutions mirror
his anti-pastoral concerns. He argues that modern government is the secularised offspring
of the sinful, institutionalised Church.
58
On the one hand, modern institutions move the
focus from salvation to the provision of this-worldly goods. Illich’s references to salvation
hence disappear in his critique of modern government. On the other hand, the nefarious
clergy/laity-dimorphism recurs in the division between governmental professionals and
the governed population. Illich subsequently rephrases his concern for Christian freedom
and community into a critique of the destruction of the ‘vernacular domain’, a term less
laden with salvific baggage and more easily applicable to non-Christian or non-Western
contexts.
59
The latter concept derives from the Latin vernaculus’, which means ‘homebred’
and ‘produced for proper rather than market use’.
60
In everyday life, people produce use-
values through directly embodied social cooperation. Individuals need the support and
feedback of others to attain their own ends, but this does not necessarily require top-down
service provision or governmental steering from official institutions. Workers can directly
coordinate their labour with each other, households can manage their affairs largely
without governmental interference, and friends can give each other advice without
mediation by government experts. There are obviously power-relations present in all
these scenarios, so Illich is not pleading for a messianic salvation from government like
Agamben, but they are not governmental power-relations.
61
Government regulations do
not exhaustively determine interpersonal conducts. People immanently calibrate their
interactions, mediated by power-relations. But they affect each other’s conducts without
the mediations of external institutions. Co-workers might, for instance, exercise power
56
Foucault, “Qu’est-ce que la critique?, 65. Translation from Foucault, "What Is Critique?, 75.
57
Cayley, Ivan Illich, 65.
58
Ivan Illich, Gender (1982), 151; Ivan Illich, Disabling Professions (1987), 15; Ivan Illich, Deschooling Society
(2002), 24.
59
See, Ivan Illich, Shadow Work (1981), 9 & 29.
60
Illich, Gender, 68.
61
Admittedly, Illich himself tends to describe the vernacular domain without any mention of power-
relations. This can, however, mean two things: he thinks it is genuinely power-free or he focuses on other
dimensions of the vernacular domain while remaining agnostic about the non-governmental power-relations
at play. I opt for the second reading.
Ungovernable Counter-Conduct
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 36
over each other, but these actions are not necessarily part of some governmental
programme. People form and readjust their conducts in constant negotiation with their
peers. Through their embodied co-presence, they gradually learn to adapt to each other
mimetically. Illich refers to the example of everyday language to illustrate this point:
Language was drawn by each one from the cultural environment, learned from the
encounter with people whom the learner could smell and touch, love or hate. The
vernacular spread just as most things and services were shared, namely, by multiple
forms of mutual reciprocity, rather than clientage [sic] to the appointed teacher or
professional.
62
Especially when people sustain their interactions for extended periods, they develop
tailored tactics and procedures to expertly influence each other’s conducts without
recourse to professional mediators. Long-standing co-workers instantly know how to
work together, old lovers instinctively know how to express their affection or annoyance
even without saying a word and life-long friends know the thin boundary between
funny and inappropriate teasing. Over time, people develop vernacular practices through
which they understand how others encounter the world and how to influence their
conduct.
Illich calls this skill to judge the appropriateness of conducts in immanent human
relations ‘probity’.
63
Social cooperation based on vernacular probity fosters communities
that immanently and spontaneously coordinate their conducts through porous
interpenetration. Probity is the skill to adapt one’s conducts to a particular relation with
its own unique quality and history without having recourse to a conduct of conducts.
Rather than relying on expert guidance, people often develop their own intuitions about
how to relate to others. One does not interact with everyone in the same way, and probity
is the capacity to judge how to cultivate these human relationships. One optimises use-
values for all participants in the relation by carefully probing what everyone wants to get
out of the relationship. The vernacular’ names the web of these localised and personal
interdependencies, while ‘probity’ is the skill to navigate this web.
According to Illich, modern governmentality corrupts vernacular culture by
subsuming vernacular interactions under governmental steering. An example Illich often
mentions is the governmentalisation of everyday language in early modernity.
64
Until the
16th century, people commonly communicated in ‘vernacular languages’, i.e., languages
that possessed no certified grammar nor even a clear demarcation between different
tongues. In Columbus’ times, there were no clear boundaries between Portuguese and
Genovese as separate linguistic entities. People often spoke mixtures of multiple
languages depending on the circumstances and their conversation partners. Speech and
62
Illich, Shadow Work, 66.
63
Illich, Gender, 112.
64
Illich, Shadow Work, 3351; Ivan Illich and Barry Sanders, ABC: The Alphabetization of the Popular Mind (1989),
6570.
TIM CHRISTIAENS
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 37
writing were determined by probity not policy. They used languages as toolboxes to
pursue their personal goals in whatever way worked within specific human relations.
Languages were consequently created and recreated through the immanent interactions
between different language users through an incessant play of words and phrases. People
easily switched registers depending on circumstances. Language was a fluid repertoire of
stock phrases and words that could be deployed and modified to fit the particular web of
conducts in which they were used. Successful speech did not depend on obedience to
State-sanctioned rules but to the probity of adequately judging which speech acts fitted
best in particular settings.
Governmental agencies were, however, worried that ‘wild, untaught vernacular
reading’ beyond the State’s purview would lead to popular insubordination.
65
‘Ungoverned speech’
66
was allegedly speech conducive to anti-governmental sentiment.
To tame the spread of ungoverned speech, intellectuals, like the Spaniard Antonio de
Nebrija, developed official grammars that put language under government regulation.
Nebrija proposed a grammar of Spanish to Queen Isabella in order to stop the
dangerously ungoverned proliferation of language beyond the State’s managing efforts.
To make language governable and foster national unity, one had to impose a single State-
sanctioned grammar that individuals had to learn and obey to ‘speak properly’. The
governmentalisation of language standardised speech across national territories with
significant governmental advantages; not only in terms of economic productivity and
efficiency but also of governability. It was a building block for the rise of the modern
economic governmentality. The cost was, however, an introduction of governmentalised
dimorphism in language learning. A class of State-sanctioned professional educators
emerged that taught people to speak ‘proper language’. Vernacular, ungoverned speech
was, on the other hand, discredited. One no longer learned language by directly speaking
to others but by submitting to the education programmes of language instructors. The
human subject was redesigned as a speechless individual in need of professional service-
provision to become a communicative (and governable) agent. One had to memorise and
repeat programmatic rules of spelling and grammar to render one’s speech efficacious.
The immanent calibration of conducts among individuals was thusly subsumed under
the top-down conduct of conducts where State-sanctioned professionals determine the
scope and modalities within which individuals are allowed to speak freely.
3. GOVERNMENTALISATION AS ALIENATION
Though Illich does not deny the benefits of governmentalisation, he emphasises the
concomitant collateral damage.
67
Not only language but also education, public medicine,
technology, and the economy have purportedly been put under professional management
65
Illich, Shadow Work, 40.
66
Shadow Work, 39.
67
Shadow Work, 1516.
Ungovernable Counter-Conduct
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 38
over the last centuries. Especially in (post-)colonial territories, the outcome has been a
dimorphic split between experts and laypeople that, according to Illich, is detrimental to
both groups. He writes, for example, about Latin-American villages visited by North-
American health professionals that
In many a village in Mexico I have seen what happens when social security arrives. For
a generation people continue in their traditional beliefs; they know how to deal with
death, dying, and grief. The new nurse and the doctor, thinking they know better, teach
them about an evil pantheon of clinical deaths each one of which can be banned, at a
price. Instead of modernising people’s skills for self-care, they preach the ideal of
hospital death. By their ministration they urge the peasants to an unending search for
the good death of international description, a search that will keep them consumers
forever.
68
The incoming professionals discredited vernacular health practices to then defectively
impose governmentally standardised health services. Illich does not deny the benefits of
public medicine but argues that these projected benefits often carry hidden side-effects
that skew human relationality toward a dimorphic split between government and the
governed.
Modern dimorphism grants governmental professionals a ‘radical monopoly’ over
social goods, similarly to how the clergy monopolised access to divine grace. It puts
professional elites in charge of securing goods essential to social life, leaving citizens no
alternative but to submit to expert-run governmentality.
69
People subsequently lose the
ability to acquire these social goods on their own through vernacular relations without
professional mediation. Like the medieval clergy hoarded access to divine grace, the
modern governmental class concentrates access to education, language, or public health.
In the pastorate, this division led to undue gatekeeping competences for the clergy. The
latter aligned the conducts of believers with the will of God as they understood it. Similarly,
the professional class in modern governmentality imposes its own ‘hidden curriculum’
on the population under the guise of governmental care.
70
“Professionals tell you what
you need and claim the power to prescribe. They not only recommend what is good, but
actually ordain what is right”.
71
According to Illich, the education system, for example, provides access to social
positions of status through its accreditation system. This makes the education system
inevitable for individual citizens and grants educators a radical monopoly on the
acquisition of diplomas and certificates. Educators use this monopoly to align pupils’
conducts with governmental norms. Governments make projections about what
knowledge and skills the population is supposed to acquire, while educators are the
middlemen tasked with modifying the conducts of citizens to steer the latter toward the
68
Ivan Illich, Medical Nemesis: The Expropriation of Health (1982), 2045.
69
Medical Nemesis, 42.
70
Illich, Deschooling Society, 11.
71
Illich, Disabling Professions, 17.
TIM CHRISTIAENS
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 39
fulfilment of these governmental aspirations. Just like the clergy ultimately imposed the
will of God as they understood it, the schooling system implements the will of the
government as understood through the mediation of professional educators. To that purpose,
educators claim ‘secret knowledge’ to scrutinize students’ minds omnes et singulatim to
discriminate ‘right’ from wrong’ thoughts and judge who has the ‘proper attitude’ to
merit high grades or access to higher education.
72
“The teacher-as-therapist feels
authorized to delve into the personal life of his pupil in order to help him grow as a
person. […] He persuades the pupil to submit to a domestication of his vision of truth and
his sense of what is right”.
73
School thereby provides a secular rendition of the pastoral
rituals of veridiction that submit student populations to procedures that reveal the truth
about themselves. Educators enact a secular variant of the pastoral mortification of the
will: pupils have to voluntarily submit to teachers to acquire the right kind of thoughts
and attitudes such that their conduct becomes the vehicle for governmental education
programmes. Only students that willingly align their conduct with the conduction of
conducts mediated by professional educators are allowed to progress; the others fail and
drop out. Social inequalities subsequently persist but are given governmental sanction.
Governments decide what pupils are supposed to know, and educators modify the will
of their students such that the latter come to spontaneously enact these governmental
projections.
The same applies to other governmental institutions. Economic experts, for example,
establish economic government by aligning people’s conducts to economic governmental
norms as they understand these norms. This entails a mortification of the will, i.e., an
instrumentalization of individual conducts to fit governmental projects, and an
implementation of governmental projects through professional middlemen who use their
radical monopoly to impose their own hidden curriculum. Neoliberal governmentality,
for instance, promotes economic growth by, first, rendering individuals ‘eminently
governable’,
74
i.e., ensuring that their individual wills align to the will of the government
to encourage growth through entrepreneurial free market competition. Neoliberal
governmentality, secondly, empowers economic experts to implement governmental
policies according to their own understanding of neoliberal governmentality.
75
The
strenuous implementation of the Washington Consensus in non-Western territories
showcases this issue.
76
Institutions like the IMF and the World Bank mobilise neoliberal
economic experts to redraw the economic policies of impoverished post-colonial States.
They rely on nations’ dependency on foreign creditors to impose their own views on how
to enhance the economic productivity of the population. By introducing measures to
72
Disabling Professions, 19.
73
Illich, Deschooling Society, 31.
74
Foucault, Naissance de la biopolitique, 274.
75
Naissance de la biopolitique, 249.
76
On the contested history of the Washington Consensus, see Narcís Serra and Joseph Stiglitz, eds., The
Washington Consensus Reconsidered: Towards a New Global Governance (2008); Noam Chomsky, Profit Over
People (2011); Naomi Klein, The Shock Doctrine: The Rise of Disaster Capitalism (2014).
Ungovernable Counter-Conduct
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 40
promote international free trade, free market competition, and individual
entrepreneurship, they re-align the conduct of people to their own governmental
projections. Programmes issuing from the Washington Consensus are not meant to render
post-colonial nations independent but to leverage this dependency in order to restructure
their markets in a way more fitting to neoliberal governmentality.
Illich believes this governmentalisation of human conduct leads to the alienation of the
governed.
77
This accusation entails a rejection of governmentality itself in favour of
human conducts not conducted by governmental institutions. For Illich, the subsumption
of conducts under governmental steering suppresses the potential of vernacular relations.
He relies on Marx’ argument that workers are alienated by losing control to capital over
the labour process. By claiming ownership over the means and products of living labour,
capital allegedly takes control over the conduction of the labour process. Illich generalises
this schema to the conduct of life itself.
78
All members of a governed population are
allegedly alienated insofar as governmental professionals take control over the
conduction of people’s everyday conducts. The secularised mortification of the will
practiced under modern governmentality incites individuals to enact the will of an alien
force. Even if they make free choices, the latter are always already embedded in
governmental programmes that mobilise these free choices to enact governmental
projects. Once modern governmentality claims authority over the conduct of conducts, an
alien force coordinates the interaction of human conducts. Just like capital mediates
between cooperating workers in the capitalist factory in the service of capital
accumulation, modern governmentality has the professional class mediating between free
individuals and the government in the service of promoting government projects. The
immanent social collaboration characteristic of the vernacular domain is subsumed under
government regulation.
Foucault might have objected that reintroducing the discourse of alienation obliges
Illich to anthropological essentialism.
79
Marxist theories of alienation often postulate an
ahistorical notion of human nature as homo faber to subsequently argue that capitalism
hinders the actualisation of human nature.
80
But, for Foucault, human subjectivity is the
contingent product of historically variable power-relations and discursive regimes. It
cannot be fixed in a transhistorical metaphysical essence. Subjectivity is the outcome of
laborious processes of subjectification. A closer reading of Illich’s work, however, shows
that he does not diagnose a perversion of human nature but of the human will. When
77
Ivan Illich, An Expansion of the Concept of Alienation, Journal of Social Philosophy 4:1 (1973), 1; Ivan Illich,
Toward a History of Needs (1978), 71; Illich, Deschooling Society, 46.
78
Harry Cleaver, The Inversion of Class Perspective in Marxian Theory: From Valorisation to Self-
Valorisation, in Open Marxism, Volume 2; Theory and Practice, ed. John Holloway, Werner Bonefeld, and
Kosmas Psychopedis (1992), 119; Cayley, Ivan Illich, 142.
79
See Foucault’s debate with Noam Chomsky: Noam Chomsky and Michel Foucault, Human Nature: Justice
vs Power; The Chomsky-Foucault Debate, ed. Fons Elders (2011).
80
David Cayley, Illich’s principal biographer, also interprets Illich along essentialist lines (Cayley, Ivan Illich,
129).
TIM CHRISTIAENS
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 41
Illich, for instance, praises Queen Isabella’s rejection of Nebrija’s proposal to govern the
Spanish language, he links her decision not to respect for human nature but for human
autonomy.
81
Some forms of conduct should be left ungoverned, according to the Spanish
sovereign, not because human nature commands it so but because this carves out a space
for individuals to determine their own conduct. Illich’s theory of alienation questions the
government of human conducts insofar as it displaces the moving force of conduct from
the level of vernacular human relations to the level of government. This mortifies the will
and subsumes it under governmental programmes, even if it is still notionally free. By
conducting people’s conducts, governmentality pursues its own goals through the wills of
the subjects it governs. Individual wills are aligned to the governmental will through the
mediation of governmental experts that steer popular conducts toward the enactment of
government programmes.
In the new era, the characteristic person […] is someone who has been gathered by one
of the tentacles of the social system and swallowed. For him the possibility of sharing in
the bringing about of something hoped for is gone. Having been swallowed by the
system, he conceives himself as a subsystem.
82
Individuals become absent in their own conduct as if steered by an alien power. They
become passive conduits for the enactment of governmental projects. The governmental
will expresses itself through the conduct of individuals’ conducts, who are thereby
reduced to the status of subsystem to an all-encompassing system.
4. RESISTING GOVERNMENTALISATION: THE DECOLONIAL OPTION
Despite his criticism of modern governmentality as a total subsumption of human
conduct under governmental schemata, Illich does not deem the governmentalisation of
life an inescapable fate. For that purpose, he highlights the arduous diffusion of
governmentality in post-colonial territories, a topic on which Foucault remains silent.
83
While for Foucault the critical attitude advocates alternative governmental rationalities
without questioning the governmental paradigm itself, Illich praises indigenous
movements that resist governmentalisation as such.
84
Just like some medieval counter-
conducts attacked the clergy/laity-hierarchy itself, Illich emphasises the indigenous
struggles that question the expert/laypeople-divide without proposing new
governmentalities with new classes of experts. Illich does not thereby reject experts’ skills
or competences but their radical monopoly on the conduct of conducts. He questions
governmental experts’ authority when they organise the conduct of conducts at the cost
81
Illich, Shadow Work, 50.
82
Illich and Cayley, Rivers North of the Future, 16263.
83
Stoler, Race and the Education of Desire, 2; Partha Chatterjee, The Disciplines in Colonial Bengal, in Texts
of Power, ed. Partha Chatterjee (1995), 8; Samaddar, "The Biopolitics of Development, 26.
84
Ivan Illich, Development as Planned Poverty, in The Post-Development Reader, ed. Majid Rahnema and
Victoria Bawtree (1997), 96.
Ungovernable Counter-Conduct
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 42
of vernacular human relations. This project leads Illich to support movements that render
human conducts ungovernable. Illich does not claim society could ever be free from all
power-relations but pleads for the cultivation of power-relations more fluid and
horizontal than the hierarchical divide between government and the governed. As Illich
writes, “while no men are completely free, some are freer than others”.
85
The defence of
vernacular practices in indigenous movements is one such example of protecting enclaves
of non-governmentalised counter-conducts.
Illich stresses that modern governmentality has a Western history foreign to and
incompatible with other parts of the globe. This makes non-Western communities ideally
positioned to withhold the global diffusion of governmentality. However, just like the
pastorate reduced the foreign other to pagans awaiting conversion to Christianity,
modern governmentality reduces non-Western nations to the status of underdeveloped
countries in need of Western development aid.
86
Though international organisations like
the IMF or the World Bank claim to offer underdeveloped countries economic aid, they
also purportedly act as governmental mediators to export Western governmentality to
foreign nations. Illich argues that communities can and should resist their
developmentalisation.
87
Illich thereby agrees with decolonial post-development theory.
88
For both, indigenous peoples cultivate their own vernacular subsistence practices that are
unduly ignored or undermined by development experts. Colonisation and post-colonial
development programmes undermine vernacular subsistence practices in favour of
governmentally mediated economic activity that favours “development as defined by the
rich”.
89
The production of wealth through immanent self-coordination of local
communities is undermined in favour of governmentally increasing economic
productivity as understood by development experts. Communities that had previously
ensured their own survival through self-organized activities are made dependent on
global markets and governmental services.
90
Illich and decolonial thinkers like Arturo Escobar question the alienating dimorphism
of the development dispositif.
91
Indigenous peoples are dispossessed from the vernacular
85
Illich, Development as Planned Poverty, 101.
86
Illich, Shadow Work, 1819. For an application to pastoral power, see Dotan Leshem, Embedding
Agamben’s Critique of Foucault: The Theological and Pastoral Origins of Governmentality,” Theory, Culture
& Society 32:3 (2015), 93113.
87
Illich, Shadow Work, 9.
88
This agreement is not surprising given Illich’s direct influence on post-development’s theory. See Serge
Latouche, La planète des naufragés (1991); Arturo Escobar, Encountering Development: The Making and Unmaking
of the Third World (2012); Arturo Escobar, Degrowth, Postdevelopment, and Transitions: A Preliminary
Conversation, Sustainability Science 10:3 (2015), 45162; Wolfgang Sachs, ed., The Development Dictionary: A
Guide to Knowledge as Power (2019).
89
Illich, Development as Planned Poverty, 95. (My emphasis)
90
David Scott, Colonial Governmentality, Social Text 43 (1995), 193; Arturo Escobar, Imagining a Post-
Development Era? Critical Thought, Development and Social Movements, in Power of Development, ed.
Jonathan Crush (1995), 24; Silvia Federici, Revolution at Point Zero: Housework, Reproduction, and Feminist
Struggle (2012), 77.
91
See Arturo Escobar, Pluriversal Politics: The Real and the Possible (2020), 7072.
TIM CHRISTIAENS
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 43
customs they use to immanently determine their conducts in negotiation with each other.
Local knowledges, or ‘epistemologies of the South’,
92
are silenced in favour of
governmental rationalities from the global North.
93
Developmentalisation recruits the
conducts of indigenous peoples into governmental projects that pursue their own aims
and integrate populations as subordinate subsystems in the accomplishment of those
aims. Human conduct becomes the conduit for fostering governmental projects imagined
elsewhere. Subsistence practices and subjectivities are reconfigured to fit these
governmental projects. Escobar quotes a critic of the World Bank saying,
How narrow the World Bank’s vision is, if it can be a radically new idea to understand
what happens at the local level. Thus I learned something very important about the
World Bank in Nepal. To work there you cannot set foot in the real Nepal. Literally.
Being in the World Bank office assumes you live in a house with running water and that
you have a driver to take you from door to door.
94
Even with the best intentions, the governmental hierarchy of experts and laypeople
produces counterproductive outcomes. Through their radical monopoly on government,
development experts impose governmental norms inapt for local circumstances. They
discredit and replace vernacular practices and probity that have emerged over centuries
of close social coordination and with ill-fitting projects that make populations dependent
on foreign influxes of money.
95
To combat governmentalisation, decolonial thinkers call for ‘the art of not being
governed’, ‘becoming-indigenous’, ‘resurgence’, or what I would like to call
‘ungovernable counter-conducts’.
96
It names indigenous peoples’ wilful refusal to align
their conducts with a governmental will to reach its own goals through a conduct of
conducts. By suspending one’s will to be governed, one affirms vernacular traditions as
an alternative form to coordinate popular conducts against the developmentalised
conduct of conducts. I do not have the space here to fully explore all forms of indigenous
resistance, but one illustration might show a glimpse of what the Illichian approach to
alienation and disalienation depicts: the Zapatista principle of mandar obedeciendo among
the indigenous peoples of Chiapas in Mexico.
97
In 1994, an alliance of Marxist guerilleros
and indigenous communities revolted against the Mexican State and its attempt to
subsume the local population under a neoliberal trade regime legislated under the new
92
Boaventura De Sousa Santos, Epistemologies of the South: Justice against Epistemicide (2016).
93
Escobar, Pluriversal Politics, 67.
94
Escobar, Encountering Development, 164.
95
Federici, Revolution at Point Zero, 74.
96
See James C. Scott, The Art of Not Being Governed: An Anarchist History of Upland Southeast Asia (2009);
Déborah Danowski and Eduardo Batalha Viveiros de Castro, The Ends of the World (2017), 122; Glenn Sean
Coulthard, Red Skin, White Masks: Rejecting the Colonial Politics of Recognition (2014), 157.
97
For a history of Zapatismo, see Neil Harvey, Rebellion in Chiapas: Rural Reforms and Popular Struggle,
Third World Quarterly 16:1 (1995), 3973; Neil Harvey, The Chiapas Rebellion: The Struggle for Land and
Democracy (1998); Alex Khasnabish, Zapatistas: Rebellion from the Grassroots to the Global (2013).
Ungovernable Counter-Conduct
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 44
NAFTA agreement with the United States.
98
Vernacular subsistence practices would have
to adapt to neoliberal incentives for competitiveness to assure the continued subsistence
of these communities. If the latter would have failed to adapt, they would have been
outcompeted by foreign industrial farming corporations. According to the Zapatistas, this
reform was the outcome of centuries of indigenous peoples being discursively framed as
underdeveloped yet obedient workforces.
99
With NAFTA, the not yet civilised would
purportedly be introduced into global civilisation. The trade agreement concerned hence
not only the acquisition of governmental economic growth targets but also the
reconfiguration of subjectivity to fit into a neoliberal system of governability.
After the 1994 insurgency, the Chiapas communities cut ties to the government and
affirmed their own capacity for self-government. The Zapatistas even rejected
government aid.
100
They carved out a decolonial autonomous space where the State would
be deprived of its authority to determine the conduct of conducts.
101
Zapatista self-
government would be a form of direct democracy without a hierarchical divide between
government and governed, experts and laypeople. Vernacular coordination of conducts
would form the basis of government or ‘kuxlejal politics’:
Kuxlejal as a term is but a mere point of anchor granted meaning when used as part of
term for the concept of expressing living as a collective, stalel kuxlejaltik, a way of being
in the world as a people, and as part of the term for a daily aspiration to live in a
dignified manner, lekil kuxlejal. The horizon of struggle for lekil kuxlejal […] as a good
way of living refers not only to an individual being but to that being in relation to a
communal connection to the earth, to the natural and supernatural world that envelops
and nurtures social beings.
102
These traditional practices are cultivated over centuries of close collaboration among each
other and with the environment. Indigenous communities have thereby developed the
probity to determine how to autonomously adjust their conduct to local circumstances
without any need for governmental interference.
In opposition to governmental dimorphism, the Zapatistas plead for ‘command
through obedience’ (mandar obedeciendo).
103
Rather than the population owing obedience
to purportedly benevolent governing classes, Zapatismo institutes a social order where
98
See Neil Harvey, Globalisation and Resistance in Post-Cold War Mexico: Difference, Citizenship and
Biodiversity Conflicts in Chiapas, Third World Quarterly 22:6 (2001), 104561; Richard Stahler-Sholk,
Resisting Neoliberal Homogenization: The Zapatista Autonomy Movement, Latin American Perspectives
34:2 (2007), 4863; Leandro Vergara-Camus, Land and Freedom: The MST, the Zapatistas and Peasant Alternatives
to Neoliberalism (2014), 6391.
99
Zapatista National Liberation Army, Voices of Fire (1994), 53.
100
Neil Harvey, Practicing Autonomy: Zapatismo and Decolonial Liberation, Latin American and Caribbean
Ethnic Studies 11:1 (2015), 17.
101
Walter Mignolo, The Darker Side of Western Modernity: Global Futures, Decolonial Options (2011), 217.
102
Mariana Mora Bayo, Kuxlejal Politics: Indigenous Autonomy, Race, and Decolonizing Research in Zapatista
Communities (2017), 19.
103
Mora Bayo, Kuxlejal Politics, 189.
TIM CHRISTIAENS
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 45
governing elites owe obedience to their constituents. Leaders would be elected on
imperative mandate, which entails that the local community could, at any time, revoke
leaders’ mandates.
104
Rather than the population readjusting its conducts to fit
governmental projects, the government is forced to enact the people’s will. I am not saying
that Zapatismo heralds a future of power-free utopianism but rather that it allows for a
politics of disalienation in which power-relations are less hierarchically fixed.
105
Mandar
obedeciendo facilitates the cultivation of power-relations in a more flexible arrangement in
which individuals are not dispossessed from the ability to determine their own conduct.
Every leadership decision is supposed to emanate from the vernacular coordination
within the collective itself. Governing elites ‘walk while asking’ (caminar preguntando) in
the sense that their political decisions are the ephemeral effects of asking the collective
what should be decided.
106
This makes government a collective learning process in which
horizontally calibrating conducts immanently produce government decisions that are
then represented by governing leaders without the latter being able to conduct the
conducts of their so-called subjects.
107
Politics is, for the Zapatistas, not a struggle among
governmental rationalities that equally subject populations to the conduct of conducts but
an immanent deliberative process that lets power circulate horizontally within the
collective to determine the group’s self-government.
Pre-programmed governmental projects to which popular conducts have to conform
are actively discouraged through multiple tactics. Political representatives are often
deliberately disempowered to ensure they do not stabilise their power-position vis-à-vis
the collective. The aforementioned imperative mandate system, which enables
communities to divest anyone whose governing decisions they believe misrepresents the
community’s deliberations, is one example. Most famously, however, is the Zapatista
practice of obliging leaders to wear ski masks in public appearances.
108
Leaders have to
remain anonymous to the general public so that they cannot claim sole ownership over
the representation of the group. They are the merely temporary representative
emanations of the collective’s effort at self-government. Levelling practices like the
wearing of ski masks ensures leaders are unable to transcend the community. Zapatismo
thereby installs a non-alienating form of self-government: by divesting governing elites
from their authority to determine political projects and impose these on the population,
Zapatismo carves out a space for local communities to establish their own conducts
through vernacular interaction.
104
Marta Duran de Huerta, An Interview with Subcomandante Insurgente Marcos, International Affairs 75:2
(1999), 269.
105
John Holloway, We Are the Crisis of Capital: A John Holloway Reader (2017), 128.
106
Khasnabish, Zapatistas, 84.
107
Holloway, We Are the Crisis of Capital, 122.
108
Zapatista National Liberation Army, Voices of Fire, 47.
Ungovernable Counter-Conduct
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 46
5. CONCLUSION
Foucault’s genealogy of governmentality and counter-conducts is firmly based in Western
history, yet, around the year 1980, Foucault starts presenting it as the main framework for
all power and resistance. Because he sometimes conflates governmentality with power as
such, the scope of modern counter-conducts gets unduly restricted to a ‘critical attitude’
that undermines specific governmental rationalities in order to establish alternative
governmentalities. What is missing is a clear view on struggles against the imposition of
governmental power as such, which Foucault himself found in antipastoral struggles and
we today observe in indigenous struggles. By the end of Naissance de la biopolitique, the
realm of the political is identified with only a struggle among different governmentalities.
To unravel a sphere of ungovernable counter-conducts helpful for the study of post-
colonial politics, I have turned to Illich’s critique of modern governmental institutions.
Though Illich is engaged in a form of social critique that is very different from Foucault’s,
his perspective allows us to render the dynamics of governmentalisation and
ungovernability visible that remain obscure in Foucault’s project. As a sympathiser of
medieval counter-conducts, Illich attacks pastoral power-relations directly as a sinful
betrayal of the Christian ethics of self-renunciation and care for the vulnerable other. Illich
tries to recover a form of human relationality antithetical to governmental steering
though still infused with its own unique power-relations. He mostly found it in non-
Western forms of local self-government, but he expanded this idea into a defence of
vernacular practices against governmental steering by professional classes. He argues that
the latter alienate populations from control over their own conducts. By manipulating the
choice architecture of individual subjects through governmental interventions,
professional experts pursue their own goals through the steering of human wills. The latter
are voided of their own force and moved, as it were, by an alien power. This wilful refusal
to be governed is clear in Illich’s rejection of international development and the resistance
practices of indigenous communities against their developmentalisation. The Zapatista
counter-conduct of mandar obedeciendo, in particular, provides a prism for thinking
differently about power-relations and self-government. Rather than criticizing one form
of governmentality in favour of another, the local communities of Chiapas rely on
indigenous traditions to establish a form of self-government that rejects the
government/governed-hierarchy. Government decisions are not projects imposed on
populations and pushed through via a conduct of conducts. They are rather the
emanations of communal deliberations to which governing elites are subjected. Through
the imperative mandate and practices that hinder the stabilisation of their decision-
making power, governing elites have to listen to their communities and enact nothing
more than what was established through their vernacular deliberations.
References
TIM CHRISTIAENS
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 47
Agamben, Giorgio, Opus Dei: An Archaeology of Duty, trans. Adam Kotsko. Stanford: Stanford
University Press, 2013.
Agamben, Giorgio, The Church and the Kingdom. London: Seagull Books, 2018.
Agamben, Giorgio, The Kingdom and the Glory, trans. Lorenzo Chiesa. Stanford, CA: Stanford
University Press, 2011.
Agamben, Giorgio, The Time That Remains: A Commentary on the Letter to the Romans. Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 2005.
Cayley, David, Ivan Illich: An Intellectual Journey. University Park: The Pennsylvania State
University Press, 2021.
Chakrabarty, Dipesh, Provincializing Europe: Postcolonial Thought and Historical Difference.
Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2007.
Chatterjee, Partha, More on Modes of Power and the Peasantry, in Selected Subaltern Studies,
ed. Ranajit Guha and Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, 35190. New York: Oxford University
Press, 1988.
Chatterjee, Partha, The Disciplines in Colonial Bengal, in Texts of Power, ed. Partha
Chatterjee. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1995.
Chomsky, Noam, Profit Over People. New York: Seven Stories Press, 2011.
Chomsky, Noam, and Michel Foucault. Human Nature: Justice vs Power; The Chomsky-Foucault
Debate, ed. Fons Elders. London: Souvenir Press, 2011.
Christiaens, Tim, “Agamben’s Theories of the State of Exception: From Political to Economic
Theology, Cultural Critique 110:1 (2021), 4974.
Christiaens, Tim, “Destituent Potential and Camus’ Politics of Rebellion, in Agamben and the
Existentialists, ed. Marcus Antonio Norris and Colby Dickinson, 17490. Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press, 2021.
Chrulew, Matthew, Pastoral Counter-Conducts: Religious Resistance in Foucault’s
Genealogy of Christianity, Critical Research on Religion 2:1 (2014), 5565.
Cleaver, Harry, "The Inversion of Class Perspective in Marxian Theory: From Valorisation to
Self-Valorisation, in Open Marxism, Volume 2; Theory and Practice, ed. John Holloway,
Werner Bonefeld, and Kosmas Psychopedis, 10644. London: Pluto Press, 1992.
Coulthard, Glenn Sean, Red Skin, White Masks: Rejecting the Colonial Politics of Recognition.
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2014.
Danowski, Déborah, and Eduardo Batalha Viveiros de Castro, The Ends of the World. Malden:
Polity, 2017.
Davidson, Arnold, In Praise of Counter-Conduct, History of the Human Sciences 24:4 (2011),
2541.
De Boever, Arne, Plastic Sovereignties: Agamben and the Politics of Aesthetics. Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press, 2016.
De Sousa Santos, Boaventura, Epistemologies of the South: Justice against Epistemicide. London:
Routledge, 2016.
Ungovernable Counter-Conduct
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 48
De Sousa Santos, Boaventura, and Steve Brett, "A Process of Learning and Unlearning: A
Dialogue with Boaventura de Sousa Santos, 3rd Space, 10 September 2022. https://3rd-
space.org/a-process-of-learning-and-unlearning-a-dialogue-with-boaventura-de-sousa-
santos/?utm_source=rss&utm_medium=rss&utm_campaign=a-process-of-learning-and-
unlearning-a-dialogue-with-boaventura-de-sousa-santos (accessed March 28, 2023).
Dean, Mitchell, Governmentality: Power and Rule in Modern Society. London: SAGE, 2010.
Dean, Mitchell, The Signature of Power: Sovereignty, Governmentality and Biopolitics. London:
SAGE, 2013.
Dean, Mitchell, and Kaspar Villadsen, State Phobia and Civil Society: The Political Legacy of Michel
Foucault. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2016.
Dean, Mitchell, and Daniel Zamora, The Last Man Takes LSD: Foucault and the End of Revolution.
London: Verso Books, 2021.
Death, Carl, Counter-Conducts: A Foucauldian Analytics of Protest, Social Movement Studies
9:3 (2010), 23551.
Duran de Huerta, Marta, An Interview with Subcomandante Insurgente Marcos,
International Affairs 75:2 (1999), 26979.
Elden, Stuart, Foucault’s Last Decade. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2016.
Escobar, Arturo, Degrowth, Postdevelopment, and Transitions: A Preliminary
Conversation, Sustainability Science 10:3 (2015), 45162.
Escobar, Arturo, Encountering Development: The Making and Unmaking of the Third World.
Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2012.
Escobar, Arturo, Imagining a Post-Development Era? Critical Thought, Development and
Social Movements, in Power of Development, ed. Jonathan Crush, 2056. London:
Routledge, 1995.
Escobar, Arturo, Pluriversal Politics: The Real and the Possible. Durham: Duke University Press,
2020.
Federici, Silvia. Revolution at Point Zero: Housework, Reproduction, and Feminist Struggle.
Oakland, CA: PM Press, 2012.
Foucault, Michel, Du gouvernement des vivants: cours au Collège de France 1979-1980. Paris:
Gallimard/Seuil, 2012.
Foucault, Michel, Histoire de la sexualité II: L’usage des plaisirs. Paris: Gallimard, 1982.
Foucault, Michel, Le sujet et le pouvoir [1982], in Dits et écrits II. 1976-1988, 104162. n. 306.
Paris: Gallimard, 2001.
Foucault, Michel, Les aveux de la chair. Paris: Gallimard, 2018.
Foucault, Michel, “L’intellectuel et le pouvoir [1981], in Dits et écrits II, 1976-1988, 156671. n.
359. Paris: Gallimard, 2001.
Foucault, Michel, Naissance de la biopolitique. Paris: Gallimard/Seuil, 2004.
Foucault, Michel, “Omnes et Singulatim: Towards a Criticism of Political Reason [1979], in
The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, ed. Sterling McMurrin, 22454. Salt Lake City:
University of Utah Press, 1981.
TIM CHRISTIAENS
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 49
Foucault, Michel, “Omnes et Singulatim: vers une critique de la raison politique [1982], in
Dits et écrits II, 1976-1988, 95380. n. 291. Paris: Gallimard, 2001.
Foucault, Michel, “Qu’est-ce que la critique? [1978], in Qu’est-ce que la critique? Suivie de La
culture de soi, 3380. Paris: VRIN, 2015.
Foucault, Michel, “Qu’est-ce que les Lumières? [1984], in Dits et écrits II, 1976-1988, 138197.
n. 339. Paris: Gallimard, 2001.
Foucault, Michel, Sécurité, territoire, population: cours au Collège de France, 1977-1978. Paris:
Gallimard/Seuil, 2004.
Foucault, Michel, The Birth of Biopolitics: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1978-79, trans. by
Graham Burchell. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010.
Foucault, Michel, The Subject and Power, Critical Inquiry 8:4 (1982), 77795.
Foucault, Michel, What Is Critique?,” [1978] in The Politics of Truth, ed. by Sylvère Lotringer,
trans. by Lisa Hochroth and Catherine Porter, 4182. Los Angeles: Semiotext(e), 2007.
Golder, Ben, Foucault and the Politics of Rights. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2015.
Hardt, Michael, and Antonio Negri, Empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000.
Hartch, Todd, The Prophet of Cuernavaca: Ivan Illich and the Crisis of the West. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2015.
Harvey, Neil, Globalisation and Resistance in Post-Cold War Mexico: Difference, Citizenship
and Biodiversity Conflicts in Chiapas, Third World Quarterly 22:6 (2001), 104561.
Harvey, Neil, Practicing Autonomy: Zapatismo and Decolonial Liberation, Latin American
and Caribbean Ethnic Studies 11:1 (2015), 124.
Harvey, Neil, Rebellion in Chiapas: Rural Reforms and Popular Struggle, Third World
Quarterly 16:1 (1995), 3973.
Harvey, Neil, The Chiapas Rebellion: The Struggle for Land and Democracy. Durham: Duke
University Press, 1998.
Holloway, John. We Are the Crisis of Capital: A John Holloway Reader. Oakland, CA: PM Press,
2017.
Illich, Ivan, An Expansion of the Concept of Alienation, Journal of Social Philosophy 4:1 (1973),
17.
Illich, Ivan, Deschooling Society. London: Marion Boyars, 2002.
Illich, Ivan, Development as Planned Poverty, in The Post-Development Reader, ed. by Majid
Rahnema and Victoria Bawtree, 94101. London: Zed Books, 1997.
Illich, Ivan, Disabling Professions. London: Marion Boyars, 1987.
Illich, Ivan, Gender. New York: Pantheon Books, 1982.
Illich, Ivan, Medical Nemesis: The Expropriation of Health. New York: Pantheon Books, 1982.
Illich, Ivan, Powerless Church and Other Selected Writings, 1955-1985. University Park: The
Pennsylvania State University press, 2018.
Illich, Ivan, Shadow Work. London: Marion Boyars, 1981.
Illich, Ivan, Toward a History of Needs. New York: Pantheon Books, 1978.
Ungovernable Counter-Conduct
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 50
Illich, Ivan, and David Cayley, The Rivers North of the Future: The Testament of Ivan Illich.
Toronto: House of Anansi, 2005.
Illich, Ivan, and Barry Sanders, ABC: The Alphabetization of the Popular Mind. New York:
Vintage Books, 1989.
Khasnabish, Alex, Zapatistas: Rebellion from the Grassroots to the Global. London: Zed Books,
2013.
Klein, Naomi, The Shock Doctrine: The Rise of Disaster Capitalism. London: Penguin, 2014.
Latouche, Serge. La planète des naufragés. Paris: Editions La Découverte, 1991.
Legg, Stephen, Beyond the European Province: Foucault and Postcolonialism, in Space,
Knowledge and Power, ed. by Stuart Elden and Jeremy Crampton, 26589. London:
Routledge, 2007.
Lemke, Thomas, Foucault’s Analysis of Modern Governmentality: A Critique of Political Reason
[2010]. London: Verso Books, 2019.
Leshem, Dotan, “Embedding Agamben’s Critique of Foucault: The Theological and Pastoral
Origins of Governmentality, Theory, Culture & Society 32:3 (2015), 93113.
Lorenzini, Daniele, From Counter-Conduct to Critical Attitude: Michel Foucault and the Art
of Not Being Governed Quite So Much, Foucault Studies 21 (2016), 721.
Lorenzini, Daniele, Governmentality, Subjectivity, and the Neoliberal Form of Life, Journal
for Cultural Research 22:2 (2018), 15466.
Lorenzini, Daniele, The Emergence of Desire: Notes Toward a Political History of the Will,
Critical Inquiry 45:2 (2019), 44870.
Mignolo, Walter, The Darker Side of Western Modernity: Global Futures, Decolonial Options.
Durham: Duke University Press, 2011.
Mora Bayo, Mariana, Kuxlejal Politics: Indigenous Autonomy, Race, and Decolonizing Research in
Zapatista Communities. Austin: University of Texas Press, 2017.
Newman, Saul, 'Critique Will Be the Art of Voluntary Inservitude': Foucault, La Boétie and
the Problem of Freedom, in Foucault and the History of Our Present, ed. by Sophie Fuggle,
Yari Lanci, and Martina Tazzioli, 5873. Cambridge: Palgrave Macmillan, 2015.
Raffnsøe, Sverre, Marius Gudmand-Høyer, and Morten S. Thaning, Michel Foucault: A Research
Companion. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2016.
Sachs, Wolfgang, ed. The Development Dictionary: A Guide to Knowledge as Power. London: Zed
Books, 2019.
Said, Edward, Michel Foucault, 1927-1984, Raritan Quarterly 4:2 (1984), 111.
Samaddar, Ranabir, Michel Foucault and Our Postcolonial Time, in The Biopolitics of
Development: Reading Michel Foucault in the Postcolonial Present, ed. by Sandro Mezzadra,
Julian Reid, and Ranabir Samaddar, 2544. New York: Springer, 2013.
Schwarzkopf, Stefan, ed. The Routledge Handbook of Economic Theology. London: Routledge,
2021.
Scott, David, Colonial Governmentality, Social Text 43 (1995), 191220.
TIM CHRISTIAENS
Foucault Studies, No. 34, 25-51. 51
Scott, James C., The Art of Not Being Governed: An Anarchist History of Upland Southeast Asia.
London: Yale University Press, 2009.
Serra, Narcís, and Joseph Stiglitz, eds. The Washington Consensus Reconsidered: Towards a New
Global Governance. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.
Spivak, Gayatri Chakravorty, In Other Worlds: Essays in Cultural Politics. New York: Routledge,
2006.
Stahler-Sholk, Richard, Resisting Neoliberal Homogenization: The Zapatista Autonomy
Movement, Latin American Perspectives 34:2 (2007), 4863.
Stoler, Ann Laura, Race and the Education of Desire. Durham: Duke University Press, 1995.
Tazzioli, Martina, Revisiting the Omnes et Singulatim Bond: The Production of Irregular
Conducts and the Biopolitics of the Governed, Foucault Studies 21 (2016), 98116.
Vergara-Camus, Leandro, Land and Freedom: The MST, the Zapatistas and Peasant Alternatives to
Neoliberalism. London: Bloomsbury, 2014.
Zapatista National Liberation Army, Voices of Fire. Berkeley: New Earth Publications, 1994.
Author info
Tim Christiaens
t.christiaens@tilburguniversity.edu
Assistant Professor
Department of Philosophy
Tilburg University
Netherlands
Dr Tim Christiaens is assistant professor of philosophy and economic ethics at Tilburg
University (Netherlands). His research focuses on the intersection between economic topics,
like the digitalisation of work, neoliberalism, and financialisation, and contemporary critical
theory. Tim has recently published a book on Digital Working Lives (2022) with Rowman &
Littlefield, and his research has appeared in, among others, Theory, Culture & Society, European
Journal of Social Theory, and Philosophy & Social Criticism.
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank the participants of the Warwick Continental Philosophy Conference of
2022 and the anonymous reviewers for their comments. I also wish to thank Bernard Harcourt,
who advised me on the notion of ungovernability. Last but certainly not least, I would like to
express my gratitude to Toon Braeckman, Mitchell Dean, Rudi Laermans, and Rob Devos,
without whom I would probably never have studied Michel Foucault’s work in the first place.
ResearchGate has not been able to resolve any citations for this publication.
Chapter
Full-text available
Giorgio Agamben has introduced the concept of 'destituent potential' to evade the perennial debate between reform or revolution. He argues that the rendering inoperative of political communities can destitute the hold of sovereign power over living beings. I argue that Agamben's version of destituent potential, however, encounters some problems that can be addressed through Albert Camus' politics of rebellion in The Rebel . Camus similarly wishes to circumvent the 'reform or revolution'-dilemma, but not by rendering community inoperative. He rather attempts to conceptualize the formation of human communities on their shared resistance to pain and suffering.
Book
On 26 August 1974, Michel Foucault completed work on Discipline and Punish, and on that very same day began writing the first volume of The History of Sexuality. A little under ten years later, on 25 June 1984, shortly after the second and third volumes were published, he was dead. This decade is one of the most fascinating of his career. It begins with the initiation of the sexuality project, and ends with its enforced and premature closure. Yet in 1974 he had something very different in mind for The History of Sexuality than the way things were left in 1984. Foucault originally planned a thematically organised series of six volumes, but wrote little of what he promised and published none of them. Instead over the course of the next decade he took his work in very different directions, studying, lecturing and writing about historical periods stretching back to antiquity. This book offers a detailed intellectual history of both the abandoned thematic project and the more properly historical version left incomplete at his death. It draws on all Foucault’s writings in this period, his courses at the Collège de France and lectures elsewhere, as well as material archived in France and California to provide a comprehensive overview and synthetic account of Foucault’s last decade.