Content uploaded by Eduard Braun
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Eduard Braun on Apr 27, 2023
Content may be subject to copyright.
1
This version has been accepted for publication at The Journal of Institutional Economics and
will appear in a revised form subsequent to peer review and editorial input by Cambridge
University Press.
The published version of this paper will be available soon at www.cambridge.org.
https://doi.org/10.1017/S1744137423000127
The German Historical School on Monetary Calculation and the Feasibility of Socialism
Eduard Braun
Institute of Management and Economics
Clausthal University of Technology
Julius-Albert Straße 2
38678 Clausthal-Zellerfeld
Germany
eduard.braun@tu-clausthal.de
Several scholars anticipated Ludwig von Mises’s calculation argument against socialism. The
present paper summarises the contributions by the members of the German Historical School
of Economics who preceded Mises and provides several examples of anticipation that have
not been discussed in the literature. Furthermore, the paper explains why it is not a coinci-
dence that members of the Historical School claimed as early as the nineteenth century that
socialism was unfeasible due to calculation and knowledge problems. In their attempts to un-
derstand historically specific features of capitalism, they developed an approach to capital that
involved the institutions of private property, money, the market, the enterprise, and monetary
calculation. Starting from this institutional approach to capital and capitalism, it was only a
small step to the question of what it means for socialist systems that those institutions are
lacking.
JEL Classification: B15, P11, P16, P21
Keywords: Historical School of Economics; Monetary Calculation; Capital; Socialism
2
1. Introduction
Almost everybody knows the most popular argument against socialism: Although socialism
sounds great in theory, it cannot work in practice because it presupposes an unrealistic con-
cept of man. Socialists do not realise, the argument runs, that labourers, managers, and bu-
reaucrats are no angels. They need proper incentives in order to give their best. Yet socialism
does not provide sufficient incentives because it abolishes private property and the possibility
of making profits and earning performance-based wages. Accordingly, the population in so-
cialist countries either becomes lazy or goes its own way and circumvents the central plan as
much as possible, thus provoking totalitarian measures by the government.
This argument against socialism is not historically specific. It assumes a certain universal na-
ture of man and claims that all laws and regulations—or economic systems, for that matter—
that ignore this universal nature must perform miserably. Private property, in this argument,
must be understood as a part of our natural condition, not as a social or legal institution
(Hodgson 2015). Not only socialism but also the market economy becomes inefficient insofar
as it ignores these natural conditions, as in the private production of public goods.
Ludwig von Mises (1920) brought forward a more powerful argument against socialism. He
did not merely point out certain anthropological problems of socialism. In fact, he attempted
to demonstrate the impossibility of rational economic calculation under socialism, that is, the
impossibility of a calculation that helps to place the available means to the service of the cho-
sen ends (Mises 1920: 16). Interestingly, Mises’s argument is based much more strongly on
historically specific features of capitalism. The reason why socialism is impossible, according
to Mises, is that it does not have the (capitalistic) institutions of private property, money, a
market for the means of production, and enterprises performing monetary calculation. A cen-
tral planning board is not able to evaluate and compare different production processes because
without these institutions, it is impossible to reduce the myriad of goods and services in mod-
ern societies to a common denominator.
It is well known that some elements of Mises’s arguments were anticipated by other econo-
mists. Mises (1966: 701) himself mentions that Hermann Heinrich Gossen, Albert Schäffle,
Vilfredo Pareto, Nikolaas G. Pierson, and Enrico Barone “touched upon the problem”. In his
overview of the prehistory of Mises’s argument, Ebeling (2003) adds the contributions of
Paul Leroy Beaulieu, William Graham, Victor Cathrein, and Benedict Elder to this list. How-
ever, it escapes most observers that several members of the German Historical School of Eco-
3
nomics anticipated Mises as well and criticised socialism along the same lines as he would
in 1920. Mises is certainly partly responsible for the neglect of the Historical School on this
matter. Although Mises (1966: 701) acknowledges that Schäffle, a member of the Historical
School (Hodgson 2010: 297), touched upon the problem, a few lines later he considers the
Historical School to be not in any way interested in demonstrating the impossibility of social-
ism.
Several recent publications have come to a different conclusion. Hodgson (2010) discusses
Schäffle’s argument against socialism and, while doing so, turns against Mises’s claim that
the Historical School was antieconomic or antitheoretical. Braun (2016) provides additional
evidence for the quality of Schäffle’s argument and demonstrates that two more members of
the Historical School, Bruno Hildebrand (1848) and Lorenz von Stein (1887), criticised so-
cialist plans on the grounds that the central planning board would not be able to calculate ra-
tionally. Braun and Wollboldt (2022) present Friedrich Julius Stahl (1863), a member of the
Historical School of Law, as another predecessor of Mises: he dedicated half a book chapter
to demonstrating that socialism is unfeasible.
The first purpose of the present paper is to summarise the known contributions of the Histori-
cal School to the impossibility argument against socialism and to add further examples. Karl
Knies (1885) was definitively aware of the problem and tried to cope with it, although with
less clarity than others. Starting from the works of Albert Schäffle, the agronomist Georg
Calberla (1877) also came to the conclusion that socialism was impossible due to calculation
problems. The fact that these authors discovered the calculation problems of socialism long
before there was any notable real-world example of socialism to consider makes their antici-
pation even more admirable.
Second, the present paper delves deeper into the question why several members of the Histor-
ical School anticipated Mises. One element of the answer seems to be that their evolutionary
perspective led some of them to doubt the human faculty to create new laws from scratch. The
limits of human knowledge, implied in this view, lend themselves to a critique of central
planning. Furthermore, it appears that the Historical School’s preoccupation with the histori-
cally specific institutions of capitalism led them to a better understanding of the institutional
preconditions of the nationwide or even worldwide division of labour. In its institutional ap-
proach to the theory of capital (Hodgson 2014; Braun 2017), the Historical School dealt with
the specific problems that arise in a society where profit-oriented, privately owned enterprises
4
produce goods and services more or less for the single purpose of making profits on the mar-
ket (see, e.g., Sombart 1919; 1927). It even appears that this institutional approach to capital
is indirectly the basis for Mises’s (1920) argument. After all, Menger (1888) had adopted this
approach to capital from the Historical School, and Mises (1932: 123), for his part, followed
Menger.
Third, the paper briefly indicates why it was a mistake by the economics profession to aban-
don the approach to capital developed by the Historical School and adopted by Menger and
Mises. As this approach is concerned with the actual role of capital and monetary calculation
in organising the societal production process, it is able to serve as a basis for analysing and
comparing different institutional arrangements. Next to the analysis of socialism, foreshad-
owed by the German Historical School itself, it has great potential to advance the study of
reforms that tamper with the institutions of monetary calculation.
In the first two sections, the paper ponders the question of why so many members of the His-
torical School were able to anticipate Mises’s critique of socialism. Their method led some of
them to doubt whether humans had enough knowledge to create new laws or constitutions.
Although they mainly targeted classical liberalism, some of them turned the argument against
socialism (section 2). Further, it appears that it was their interest in understanding capitalistic
institutions and the role they play in organising the production process that led Historical
School economists to consider what happens when these institutions are missing—as in so-
cialism. Their institutional theory of capital is designed to explain the peculiarities of the capi-
talistic production process (section 3). Section 4 reiterates Mises’s original argument against
socialism briefly and dissects it into its different components. The following sections discuss
several members of the Historical School and demonstrate how much they anticipated Mises.
These sections are arranged more or less chronologically, although it is difficult to be precise
in this regard as the lifespans of the respective authors overlapped and the relevant books
sometimes went through several editions and were revised in this process. Section 5 starts
with Friedrich Julius Stahl, who asserted the unfeasibility of socialism already in 1846. Sec-
tions 6 and 7 deal with two of the three founders of the Historical School of Economics, Bru-
no Hildebrand and Karl Knies. Knies’s position on the impossibility of socialism has, to the
best of my knowledge, never been discussed. Wilhelm Roscher, the third founder, is not cov-
ered in this paper. Roscher (1864: 140 ff.) also criticised socialism, claiming that the “central
direction of all production and consumption” would be a “despotism” (151) never seen be-
5
fore.1 However, Roscher did not deal with calculation or knowledge problems but with the
incentive problem mentioned at the outset of this introduction. Section 8 is dedicated to Al-
bert Schäffle. He is the author who comes closest to Mises in terms of the quality and com-
pleteness of the argument. Section 9 presents the previously unrecognised contribution of
Georg Calberla and some other, minor contributions by Historical School economists. Finally,
section 10 explains why the institutional theory of capital is not only of historical importance
as a helpful tool in the debates on socialism. Its current significance is indicated in the face of
recent reforms of the institutions of monetary calculation and corporate governance.
2. The Historical School on the knowledge problem
Mises belonged to the Austrian School of Economics. The Austrian School was opposed to
the German Historical School of Economics in the famous Methodenstreit. These schools
clearly were antagonists, and Mises (1966) wrote that the Historical School had no interest
whatsoever in even considering the impossibility of economic calculation under socialism.
Mises (701) stated that it is not puzzling that the “detractors of economics”—that is, the his-
torical and institutionalist schools—“failed to recognize the problem”. They “disparage eco-
nomics [...] in the interest of their interventionist or socialist propaganda”. We must count
ourselves lucky that these schools “have not succeeded in suppressing the study of economics
entirely”.
Why, then, did several members of the Historical School anticipate large parts of Mises’s fa-
mous argument against the possibility of rational economic calculation under socialism? For
want of any historical source on this matter, it is impossible to answer this question precisely.
What I do in this and the following section, therefore, is reflect on the relationship between
Mises’s argument and the work of the Historical School and highlight their overlap.
If we paid attention only to the statements by the Historical School on social philosophy, it
would be difficult to find common ground with the Austrian School. When the German His-
torical Schools emerged at the turn of the nineteenth century, they turned against the attempts
by classical liberalism and, more generally, the Enlightenment to construct human societies
based on human reason. Friedrich Carl von Savigny founded the Historical School of Law as
1 Throughout the paper, all foreign language quotations have been translated by the author.
6
a direct reaction to the intention of progressive and classical liberal scholars who wanted to
create a new civil law for all German countries more or less from scratch. Savigny (1814:
164–65), as a conservative, argued that it is an illusion to think that humanity is able to step
outside history and to invent new laws without a deep understanding of customs and the his-
torical development that led to the present state of affairs. The entire history of the nation
constitutes the material of law. Law is not arbitrary but emanates from the innermost nature of
the nation and its history. Therefore, “[e]very age must judiciously intend to see through this
material that is given with inner necessity, to rejuvenate it and to keep it alive” (Savi-
gny 1815: 264).
The Historical School of Economics adopted this approach and tried to understand present-
day economic phenomena by studying their role and place in history. For Savigny, the main
target was the idea that humans are able to discover and understand natural rights based on
their reason alone and without consulting history. In a parallel effort, the Historical School of
Economics tended to criticise classical economists for their unhistorical treatment of human
nature and economic laws and for their belief that human societies would flourish based on
individual liberty alone—that is, without any rules or institutions except for private property.
Karl Knies, one of the founders of the Historical School of Economics, expressed his con-
cerns about classical economics as follows:
For Adam Smith himself, the devotion to theoretical absolutism was a natural conse-
quence, first, of the then generally accepted conception of nations in which he saw
completely similar, summary aggregates of general, human individuals who just hap-
pen to be separated by national borders and live under different systems of law; but
probably even more, second, of the fact that the fundamental area of his research was
human labour, an area where the relative, the historical, and the concrete tend to evade
the observer and where a universal foundation of absolute results seems to be given.
(Knies 1885: 27, emphasis in original)
Although the Historical School mainly targeted classical liberalism, it appears that its critical
approach toward the creation of laws from scratch can easily be transferred to a critique of
socialism. In any case, that is how several members of the Austrian School used this argu-
ment.
7
It is well known that Carl Menger had praised Savigny for understanding law as a more or
less unreflective product of a higher wisdom rather than as something derived from the
planned action of a legislative body (Kolev and Dekker 2022). According to Roos (1994:
295), much of what Hayek had to say about “embodied” knowledge in law and society can
also be traced back to the Historical School. Hayek knew Savigny’s work, occasionally citing
him approvingly. Hayek’s (2014: 46) view on the origin of rules is clearly reminiscent of Sa-
vigny:
[N]o single human intelligence is capable of inventing the most appropriate abstract
rules because those rules which have evolved in the process of growth of society em-
body the experience of many more trials and errors than any individual mind could
acquire.
Witt (1997: 47) points out that this argument, typical of Hayek since the late 1930s, is not
consistent with the Austrian method. The younger Hayek himself had been keen to make de-
ductions, in a logically consistent way, based on the premises of a pure equilibrium theory
where there is no lack of knowledge at all. Raico (1995: sect. 7) presumes that both Menger
and the older Hayek leaned toward spontaneous-order explanations for ideological reasons,
that is, because they served to validate their liberal view of the social order. Tellingly, Hayek
usually criticised socialism and interventionism for their pretence of knowledge but tended to
ignore that Savigny, Knies, and others had used similar arguments against classical liberalism
as well.
It is interesting to note that the Historical School of Economics itself did not attack only clas-
sical liberalism on the grounds that it tended to ignore history, customs, and institutions.
Some of its members attacked socialism for the same reason. Bruno Hildebrand, for example,
another founder of the Historical School of Economics, criticised socialists exactly because
they overestimated the power of reason and ignored history:
They [socialists] break with the past and want to transform the rich, free, and diverse
life of humanity into a dead, uniform mechanism. They approach the given world as if
the first men were born a second ago and the first form of communal life should be
created for them by reason. […] [T]hey do not see that every new creation that human-
8
ity passes through in its history can only be spawned from the old, given elements and
draw its sustenance from the fluids of the available soil. (Hildebrand [1848] 1922:
214)
Below we will see that several members of the Historical School, including Hildebrand him-
self, extended this rather general point and questioned the possibility of centrally planning the
economy.
3. The institutional theory of capital
Given that the Historical School influenced the Austrian School on the issue of the limit of
human knowledge, it does not appear to be a coincidence that it also anticipated the Austrian
argument against the possibility of socialism. Yet, the relationship between the approach of
the Historical School and the Austrian argument against socialism is even closer. This is par-
ticularly true for Mises’s original version of the argument.
Not many economists know that Mises deviated from his fellow Austrians when it came to his
treatment of capital and the institutions that underlie it in capitalistic societies (Braun et al.
2016). The standard Austrian theory of capital concentrates on the physical activities of
roundabout production processes and defines capital as produced means of production—i.e.,
as physical factors of production. In this sense, capital is not specific to a certain economic
system or historical period but a universal phenomenon—a phenomenon that all humans can
understand and discuss based on their reason and is independent of historical circumstances
(Braun 2017).
Mises deviated from this approach (Lewin and Cachanosky 2018: 424). Following a rather
unknown and often misinterpreted essay by Carl Menger (1888; see Braun 2015a for a sum-
mary and Braun 2020 for a partial translation), Mises, when he talked about capital, con-
cerned himself with the organisation of capitalism. He argued explicitly that capital is not a
universal production factor but a historically specific concept. Mises (1966: 264) stated that
the “concept of capital cannot be separated from the context of monetary calculation and from
the social structure of a market economy.” Mises (1932: 123) defined it as the tangible and
intangible properties of business enterprises, whether they consist of money or are only ex-
pressed in money terms.
9
It is highly probable that Menger (1888) had adopted his view of capital from Richard Hilde-
brand, a member of the Historical School and the son of Bruno Hildebrand (Braun 2015b:
78 ff.). This notion of capital revolves around the capitalistic institutions of private property,
money, markets, the capitalistic enterprise, and financial accounting. The Historical and Insti-
tutional Schools claimed, as Hodgson (2014: 1070) writes, that capital is historically specific
to capitalism and must be analysed as such because only in this way can important features of
this economic system be grasped.
A mature discussion of capital and its role in capitalism by a member of the Historical School
can be found in Werner Sombart’s writings. Sombart rejected the standard Austrian theory of
capital. Böhm-Bawerk’s famous books on capital and interest “fall outside the area of what I
consider to be fruitful economic theory” (Sombart 1927: 128). It is “ridiculous” to call a child
that is picking berries and placing them in a basket a capitalist who is producing capitalistical-
ly (Sombart 1927: 134). Capital is not a universal phenomenon; it is specific to capitalism,
where capital-based enterprises organise the production process rationally by means of calcu-
lation and accounting (Sombart 1927: 130). Sombart (1927: 129) was explicit on this point:
Capital is a historical-economic term, i.e., a term that evolved within the context of a
certain economic system—the capitalistic one. It is misleading to use this term for dif-
ferent economic systems. Only since business wealth [capital] assumed an independ-
ent existence in capitalistic thinking did it adopt a certain, well-defined meaning.
It is only because certain amounts of wealth came to be dedicated to the purpose of making
profit and separated from personal concerns that the “principle of acquisition” (Erwerbsprin-
zip), distinctive of capitalism, was able to develop without limits. According to Sombart
(1919: 119), the institution of double-entry bookkeeping creates the capitalistic enterprise as a
separate, acting entity. By means of accounting, the enterprise “assumes a separate existence”
and becomes “an entity which emerges as a subject conducting individual economic acts and
which leads a separate life, outlasting the life of individuals” (Sombart 1919: 101). Capital is
inextricably linked to these capitalistic enterprises, which combine the production factors and
organise the production process under capitalism according to the principle of profit maximi-
sation.
10
Mises (1966) constructed a theory of capital based on his historically specific approach to
capital. It explains how the invisible hand of the market arranges for profit-oriented, capital-
istic enterprises to organise the allocation of resources according to consumer demand
(Braun 2017).
Again, it was the Historical School and, ironically, Karl Marx who preceded Mises in the de-
velopment of such an institutional theory of capital. Marx (1859: 101 ff.) tried to understand
and explain the logic of production under capitalism. He described the acquisitive activities of
the capitalistic enterprise with the following formula:
Money – Commodity – Money’
This formula, according to Marx (1859: 102), describes the “current form of bourgeois pro-
duction.” For capitalistic enterprises, money is not a means but the be-all and end-all of all
transactions, “the starting point and the end point of movement” (Marx 1859: 102). The goal
of the production process is not to produce products but to make money. “Money is ex-
changed against a commodity in order to exchange the very same commodity for more mon-
ey” (Marx 1859: 102).
In Das Kapital, Marx famously combined this theory on the circulation of capital with the
labour theory of value in order to explain that the difference between Money’ and Money (the
profit retained by the capitalists) amounts to an exploitation of the labour class. Non-socialist
authors, however, adopted Marx’s approach to capital without combining it with the labour
theory of value and simply used it to explain the role of capital in capitalism.
For example, Otto von Zwiedineck-Südenhorst (1930: 1072), a member of the Historical
School (Grimmer-Solem 2003a: 23), developed an institutional theory of capital as a clear and
explicit attempt to add substance to Marx’s rather abstract approach. He showed how the
transformation of land, labour, and produced means of production into products through pro-
duction is embedded in the circulation of capital.
11
Figure 1: The circulation of capital as illustrated by Zwiedineck-Südenhorst (1930: 1069)
Figure 1 can be used to explain how, in capitalism, the production process depends on numer-
ous institutions. The production factors are combined, and output is produced within the en-
terprise. The enterprise must buy its inputs and sell its output for money on the market. In
order to do so, it must be able to acquire and forego private property in commodities. Its prof-
it is determined as the difference between revenues and expenses with the help of the institu-
tion of financial accounting or monetary calculation.
Zwiedineck-Südenhorst (1930: 1070 ff.) argued that capital is relevant because it allows to
check whether the means applied have served their purpose. According to Mises’s calculation
argument, which is presented in the next section, this is exactly what socialist planning boards
cannot do.
4. The components of Mises’s argument against the possibility of economic calculation
under socialism
Mises (1920; [1932] 1951) is famous for his argument that socialism runs into unsurmounta-
ble difficulties because a central planning board would not be able to calculate, assess, or
compare the value productivity of alternative production processes and therefore could not
allocate resources rationally in society:
The mind of one man alone—be it ever so cunning, is too weak to grasp the im-
portance of any single one among the countlessly many goods of a higher order. No
single man can ever master all the possibilities of production, innumerable as they are,
as to be in a position to make straightway evident judgments of value without the aid
of some system of computation. (Mises 1920: 15)
Land
Labor
Produced means
of production
Money expenses Production Money revenues
Products
12
In other words, as Hayek (1937; 1945) would stress later, socialism has a knowledge problem.
The information available to a planning board would never suffice to allocate resources ra-
tionally. In contrast to Hayek, however, Mises did not confine himself to the knowledge prob-
lem. First and foremost, socialism had a calculation problem (Hülsmann 1997: 24). His point
was that socialist planning boards do not have a common yardstick at the ready that would
help them to reduce the desirability of goods and services to a single dimension.
The decision-makers in capitalism, in contrast, and particularly the entrepreneurs, do have
recourse to such a yardstick. In their calculations, they can rely on the market prices of the
means of production. The market system transforms the ordinal preference rankings of differ-
ent individuals, which are impossible to compare, into common, cardinal units—that is, mon-
ey prices—and thus provides the basis for economic calculation (Hauwe 2019: 201).
Based on prices, entrepreneurs are able to assess whether they can employ a certain good or
labour service usefully in a certain production process simply by calculating expected profits
and losses. As long as they expect an input factor to generate profit—i.e., to increase a prod-
uct’s price enough to exceed the input’s price—its employment is economically justified.
Otherwise, they sell, abandon, or transfer the factor to another production process:
Anyone who wishes to make calculations in regard to a complicated process of pro-
duction will immediately notice whether he has worked more economically than oth-
ers or not; if he finds, from reference to the exchange relations obtaining in the market,
that he will not be able to produce profitably, this shows that others understand how to
make a better use of the goods of higher order in question. (Mises 1920: 10)
Socialism, Mises claimed, lacks a comparable common yardstick. As it abolishes private
property rights in the means of production, these goods are not traded and therefore no market
prices of them exist. Consequently, as a socialist central planning board does not have a yard-
stick to rationally compare inputs, outputs, and net results, they are not able to determine
whether they have employed inputs economically in the production of output:
[I]t lies in the very nature of socialist production that the shares of the particular fac-
tors of production in the national dividend cannot be ascertained, and that it is impos-
sible in fact to gauge the relationship between expenditure [production effort] and in-
13
come [production proceeds]. (Mises 1920: 2; square brackets contain my translations
of the original German)
Mises admitted that socialism could solve this problem if it found “an objectively recogniza-
ble unit of value”, a yardstick “which would permit of economic calculation in an economy
where neither money nor exchange were present” (Mises 1920: 30). Mises added, however,
that the only item which could conceivably replace money prices and be considered such a
yardstick––labour––would be “unworkable” because labour is not homogeneous and of uni-
form quantity (6). His famous conclusion was that it is impossible for a planning board to
economise:
Without economic calculation there can be no economy. Hence, in a socialist state
wherein the pursuit of economic calculation is impossible, there can be—in our sense
of the term—no economy whatsoever. (18)
For the following discussion, it is helpful to dissect Mises’s argument into its individual com-
ponents. Interestingly, Mises based his argument not only on the theoretical and deductive
approach of the Austrian School of Economics but also on important elements of the Histori-
cal School of Economics, particularly the institutional theory of capital.
The first component of Mises’s argument—an Austrian one—is his critique of the labour the-
ory of value. This critique consists of two aspects:
a) Based on the subjective theory of value, Mises argued that the labour theory of value
is utterly wrong. Objective values cannot be measured at all, he claimed, and relative
values or prices depend on consumer choices, not on the amount of labour invested.
b) Even if we accepted the idea that value is somehow measurable, labour could not
serve as a yardstick for economic calculation anyway because labour is not uniform or
homogenous.
It must be added that this critique had numerous predecessors. Streissler (1990) pointed out
that the subjective theory of value had been wide-spread in the German-language area before
the neoclassical revolution of the 1870s. It is therefore unsurprising that, below, we will find
it in the writings of several members of the Historical School.
14
The second component of his argument—a historical or institutional one—is his description
of how capitalism solves the problem of economic calculation. Several capitalistic institutions
are necessary to make this possible. They are the same as those that constitute the foundation
of the institutional theory of capital. We need private property in the means of production; we
need money so that there are money prices of all traded goods; and we need the enterprise and
the institutions of monetary calculation, bookkeeping and financial accounting, so that we are
able to calculate profits accurately.
Component 3 of his argument is that the market for the means of production guarantees that
these means have market prices. This allows enterprises to extend their economic calculation
to the higher stages of production—and hence the entire production process. Component 3 is
historical as well. I separate it from component 2 because most predecessors of Mises missed
it.
Component 4, the consequence of the other three components, is the point that socialist plan-
ning boards cannot solve the knowledge problem and are therefore unable to allocate re-
sources and organise the production process rationally. This, of course, is the component that
must be present or at least perceptible in any work dealt with in this paper; otherwise, an au-
thor cannot be understood as having anticipated Mises. As we have seen in section 2, it is
closely related to the approach of the Historical School as well.
Table 1 collects the components of the economic calculation argument. In the following sec-
tions, I refer to this table when characterising the arguments made by the predecessors of
Mises and Hayek in the Historical School of Economics.
1a The labour theory of value is wrong. Value is a subjective magnitude.
1b Labour cannot measure value because it is not homogenous or uniform.
2 Capitalistic institutions are a precondition for rational economic calculation.
3 There must be market prices of the means of production.
4 A central planning board cannot obtain and process all the necessary information.
Table 1: Components of the economic calculation argument
15
It is no wonder that the connection between the historically specific notion of capital and the
problem of economic calculation under socialism suggested itself to several members of the
Historical School. Almost all of the scholars discussed in the following sections not only an-
ticipated one or several components of Mises and Hayek’s argument against socialism, but
also employed a historically specific notion of capital or focused on one or several of the in-
stitutions behind this notion. Except perhaps for Schäffle (1870), they did not employ all
components of Mises’s argument. Nevertheless, their achievements are still remarkable given
that real-world examples of socialism were still a long way off at their time.
5. Friedrich Julius Stahl on the impossibility of socialism
Chronologically, the first scholar that must be mentioned as a predecessor of Mises is Frie-
drich Julius Stahl (1802–1861). Stahl was a German legal philosopher associated with the
Historical School of Law. In the preface of the first edition of his magnum opus on the phi-
losophy of law, he spoke very positively of Friedrich Savigny, the founder of this school.
Stahl (1847: xix ff.) announced that he would apply, in his book, the historical method, pro-
posed by Savigny, not only to civil law, as Savigny had done, but to law as such.
Stahl’s contribution to the impossibility of socialism has been noticed only very recently
(Braun and Wollboldt 2022). This is surprising because Stahl is not at all an unknown figure.
Born in 1802 near Würzburg (Germany), Stahl was and still is famous as a Christian and reac-
tionary legal philosopher. Renowned management theoretician Peter F. Drucker (1933) even
argued that Stahl shaped German thinking about the state up until the First World War. Some
of Stahl’s works have been translated into English, among them the lecture series that con-
tains the most detailed version of his argument (Stahl 1978). Unfortunately, copies of Stahl
(1978) are hard to come by, and then it contains numerous errors and confusing mistransla-
tions.
Before I present Stahl’s contribution, I have to say a few words about the origin of his ideas.
In a footnote, he referred to Dönniges (1845), who “has illustrated the economic unfeasibility
of the social theory [socialism] on the grounds that it removes the distinction between the
value of labour and [the value of] its products” (Stahl 1846: 75).
Stahl exaggerated. Dönniges (1845) did not maintain the unfeasibility of socialism, and he did
not go into a lot of detail on this issue. Dönniges criticised socialism mostly on the grounds of
components 1a and 1b (see table 1). The value of labour is not inherent to labour but derives
16
from its products and the needs it satisfies (Dönniges 1845: 573). As talents and efforts differ,
the value of labour is not the same for each labourer (574). From this, Dönniges (573) did not
deduce the impossibility of socialism but claimed that “[i]t would be the highest arbitrariness
and despotism to equalise the prices of goods or, what amounts to the same thing, to organise
them according to principles of justice”.
Stahl, however, concluded from reading Dönniges (1845) that socialism was actually impos-
sible. His own arguments are more sophisticated and contain mainly components 1a, 1b,
and 4 (see table 1). Component 2 features less prominently but can still be detected.
The first reference by Stahl to the argument in question that I can detect is in the second edi-
tion of the fourth volume of his book on the philosophy of law (Stahl 1846). It contains a sec-
tion labelled “The social theories [socialism] are indeed unfeasible”. Stahl (75) anticipated
component 4 by saying:
Another error of the social theories [socialism], that makes it unfeasible, is the failure
to recognise the limit of human intelligence. […] Even if the will of man were that
pure as they [these theories] assume, they would still have to fail because of the inabil-
ity of the human mind to calculate the entire demand and the produce of labour in ad-
vance and direct the industrial activities in all its circles accordingly.
Stahl (1863) elaborated on this argument at length in a chapter entitled “Review of the social-
ist system and of Proudhon’s doctrine of value from the economic point of view”. Stahl start-
ed the chapter with the blunt statement that “[f]rom the standpoint of economics, it [the so-
cialist system] proves to be impossible and to be a system that does not enhance prosperity
and enjoyment, but diminishes, even destroys them” (Stahl 1863: 240).
Once again, component 4 loomed large in his discussion. He attacked socialists such as
Charles Fourier who had claimed that it was possible to plan the production process from
above and in advance and without recourse to any measure of value. Stahl (1863: 245 f.) ar-
gued that these plans would fail due to the “limit of human intelligence”:
Socialism, however, ventures itself to take over nature’s whole task, to achieve that
balance between consumption and production solely through human intelligence. It
undertakes to sketch out in advance the annual budget for the needs and funds of the
17
entire human race, according to the needs of each individual family, and then to set up
systematically the entire labour activity, assigning to everyone his daily business. Now
this would not remotely be accurate even in the moment where the need is detected;
but the uninterrupted change, the oscillation of wants would remain totally unsatisfied
if it were no longer to assert itself through its own direct effect via demand and sales,
but only through notification of the superiors and a commissarial investigation.
Stahl (1863) dug deeper than Stahl (1846). The quoted passage demonstrates that he was
aware of the general role of the institutional framework of capitalism (component 2). He con-
trasted the market––demands and sales––with central planning and claimed that the latter
could not at all accomplish the task of allocating resources satisfactorily. His position on these
institutions remains unclear, however, as he appears to identify them with “nature”, here and
elsewhere.
Stahl (1863) also addressed other socialist proposals. Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, for example,
had made the point that it was possible to introduce labour time as the measure of value of all
goods and, consequently, to pay labourers according to their labour time. What needed to be
done, Stahl wrote, was to demonstrate the unfeasibility of Proudhon’s demand that it is the
task of society to fix the price of all products and all services according to the standard of la-
bour time and to achieve the corresponding equality of wages per hour (Stahl 1863: 248).
In his response to Proudhon’s challenge, Stahl employed components 1a and 1b. First of all,
he wrote, goods are not valued according to the labour time that is necessary to produce them.
It is the other way around: labour is valued because and insofar as its product is valuable to
consumers: “All value is based on the product itself, i.e., the usefulness, the utility, the virtue
that it has in itself” (250). Stahl (249) ridiculed the labour theory with the following story:
A farmer has a tooth extracted by a surgeon; the operation is carried out beautifully
and in no time at all and the surgeon demands the usual charge as payment. But then
the farmer breaks out in indignation: What! Your predecessor also once extracted a
tooth from me, he pulled and tore at me for a whole hour but did not charge me more
than you, and you were finished in a moment and almost without me noticing it.
18
Stahl did not leave it at that. The classical economists had not been able to explain prices
based on a subjective theory of value (use value) because they could not solve the diamond-
water paradox of value. Stahl (1863: 250) did not cite his influences, but like several German-
language economists of his time (Streissler 1990), he anticipated the neoclassical revolution
of the 1870s by explaining how goods with objectively high use value (such as water) can end
up having lower prices than goods with objectively low use value (such as diamonds):
This utility or virtue of the product (or service) […] depends on the need: in the
French army during the retreat from Moscow, lemonade and ice may have been of low
value and fur of high value, and vice versa during the campaign in Egypt. It [utility] is
based on rarity; for it is a general law of nature, not that the rare is the best, but that
the best is rare.
Stahl then went on to demonstrate that even if we grant the possibility of taking labour time as
the measure of value, socialism is still “not achievable” (Stahl 1863: 251) because labour time
is not homogenous (component 1b):
For if one takes the working time of the individual as a measure—the time that person
A and person H have really spent—the consequences are that individual goods of the
same kind have different prices, depending on the random expenditure of time by the
workers, even that the goods that the slow beginner has made have everywhere to be
paid dearer than those of the masters; and who dares to determine how much time the
particular worker has spent each time! If one takes the general average amount of
work as a yardstick, the inequality of wages becomes already reestablished in princi-
ple, since one person needs more than the average time and another one less.
The quality of Stahl’s argument and the number of details he mentioned are astonishing given
that the lectures printed in Stahl (1863) stem from the 1850s. He was the first of a number of
members of the Historical School who criticised socialists for their ignorance of the calcula-
tion and knowledge problems.
19
6. Bruno Hildebrand on economic calculation under socialism
Bruno Hildebrand (1812–1878) discussed the impossibility of socialism in his programmatic
book Die Nationalökonomie der Gegenwart und Zukunft (The economics of the present and
the future), one of the foundational treatises of the Historical School. The “fundamental er-
rors” of socialists and communists, Hildebrand stated, are their organisational plans for a so-
cialist society: “[W]e will demonstrate that all socialist organisation plans are impossible”
(Hildebrand 1848: 213). In the subsequent chapter, entitled “All socialist organisation plans
are unfeasible”, Hildebrand employed components 1b, 2, and 4 of table 1. Component 2 in
particular is much more prominent in Hildebrand than in Stahl. It must be added, however,
that Hildebrand (1848: 213) referred to Stahl’s treatment of socialism but did not give him
credit for his attempt to demonstrate the unfeasibility of socialism a few years earlier.
We have seen in section 2 that Hildebrand applied Savigny’s arguments against classical lib-
eralism to socialism. He argued that socialists “break with the past” and try to “form commu-
nal life […] by reason” (Hildebrand 1848: 214). But, he did more. In the same way that Savi-
gny had argued that law cannot be invented from scratch but must develop organically, Hil-
debrand argued that the economy cannot be re-organised from scratch as if it had no history.
Accordingly, he defended the institutions of private property, money, and the market against
the attacks of the socialists who wanted to abolish them and to organise the economy in a new
and different way (Hildebrand 1848: 196–211).
The organisational plans of socialists are doomed, Hildebrand concluded, because the social-
ists do not have a method of rational allocation of resources in society. Socialists would have
to come up with an alternative to the market economy. What they need is rules or laws that
determine how the individual suppliers of goods and services are compensated in a way that
consistently guarantees that the value of outputs surpasses that of inputs:
Any socialist economy which suppresses the individual private economy […] necessi-
tates a law which regulates, first, the mutual ratio between the individual contributions
of production and consumption and, second, the ratio between these individual contri-
butions (of production and consumption) and the total of them. (Hildebrand 1848:
215)
20
There is no foundation for such a law, Hildebrand (1848: 215) added. First of all, “it presup-
poses the knowledge of the entire demand and the entire supply [Leistungen]” (indication of
component 4). Second, and more importantly for Hildebrand, outside a market economy it is
impossible to find rules that indicate how the individual contributors should share in the con-
sumption of the social product. Statements such as “From each according to his ability, to
each according to his need” (Hildebrand 1848: 216) are mere slogans that are of no help.
The reason he gave for the inability of socialism to find such rules clearly foreshadows com-
ponent 1b of Mises’s argument. For Hildebrand (1848: 215), the main deficiency of socialism
is its lack of a yardstick for the value of production or consumption:
Furthermore, as individual labour capabilities, talents, and wants are different every-
where, any law of distribution and accommodation presupposes the existence of an ab-
solute measure of individual contributions to production and consumption. Yet, such a
measure has neither been discovered, nor is it possible because these contributions are
individual, that is, infinitely various, not only quantitatively but also qualitatively, and
therefore not objectively measurable.
Earlier in his book, Hildebrand (1848: 208) stated that money is necessary as a measure of
value. Socialism, in short, is unfeasible for Hildebrand because it lacks the historically grown
institutions of capitalism, where money prices serve as a yardstick in the economic calcula-
tions of entrepreneurs and where the distribution of the social product to the productive fac-
tors is oriented towards the contribution of each factor to the monetary profits of enterprises.
7. Karl Knies on the role of money in capitalism and socialism
Hildebrand hinted at the important role of money as a measure of value, but Karl Knies
(1821–1898) dedicated large parts of his book on money to this issue. At the outset, Knies
(1885: 6) stated that the institution of money is supposed to eliminate the “social evil” that
comes with the “so very difficult and so unsatisfying assessment and comparison” of econom-
ic goods in a natural economy. Any plans for organising the production process without trade
and money would bring along this social evil, especially in modern societies with their highly
developed and complicated system of division of labour. It is no coincidence, Knies (1885: 5)
wrote, that social reformers who demand the abolishment of money suggest that the organisa-
21
tion of the economy should depend on “the unlimited prevalence either of fatherly benevo-
lence facing naive piety or of a supposedly highly prudent, highly just etc. supreme power
facing blind obedience on the part of all people that are involved”.
Knies did not claim explicitly that socialism is unfeasible. Yet, he tried to demonstrate why
Marx had not succeeded in his attempts to replace the monetary unit with the quantity of la-
bour as the measuring rod for the value of goods and claimed that socialism would drift to-
wards a despotic government if it were to abandon money and money prices. His argument
built mainly on components 1b and 2 of table 1.
It must be mentioned that when it comes to capitalistic institutions (component 2), Knies
(1885: 72) was well aware that some economists claim that capital is historically specific––a
“historical category”, as he expressed it. However, Knies was not ready to follow these econ-
omists. Knies (1885: 29) was of the opinion that it had not helped economic science that Ad-
am Smith and many other economists tended to make apodictic pronouncements in favour of
certain definitions of capital over others. Accordingly, Knies (1885: 24–83) himself, in his
long discussion of capital, did not dare to come to a definite conclusion on the term capital
but rather discussed the merits and demerits of existing definitions of the term. That is, he did
not opt for capital as a historical category that is a part of the institutional framework of capi-
talism.
Still, his argument against socialism rests on his analysis of one capitalistic institution, name-
ly money, and how it helps to solve the issue of valuating goods and services. Knies (1885:
151) mentioned that Karl Marx had wrestled with exactly this problem. His argument against
Marx’s solution runs as follows.
According to Marx, exchange value derives from the quantity of simple labour that is neces-
sary, on average, to produce a certain good. Knies (1885: 156) objected that there are many
cases where this is not true at all and where labour time cannot be the substance of value. The
apprentice will never be able to replicate “the artwork of his master even in a multiple of the
time that the master needs”. Knies (1885: 158) added that it is an illusion if Marx wants to
measure the value of all products of labour by the quantity of simple labour (component 1b of
table 1). According to Knies, the problem is that different kinds of labour cannot be com-
pared. They appear to be comparable only because in capitalistic societies they all have a
money price. That the price of advanced labour can be expressed as the multiple of the price
of simple labour, however, does not imply that simple labour could serve as a measuring unit
22
for advanced labour (1885: 158). Knies’s argument was that the existence of money may
make it possible to express the price of any good as a multiple of the price of any other good,
but that does not mean that it is possible to express the quantity of any good as a multiple of
the quantity of any other good. Rather, what is needed is a tertium comparationis, a monetary
unit that has a certain and predetermined amount of value itself that can be used to express the
value of all other goods (1885: 163). The task of money is to “be the special tool by means of
which the social fungibility of value, necessary because of the division of labour in the ex-
change economy, is realised in all valuable goods” (1885: 164).
Although Knies (1885) did not explicitly deny the possibility of socialism, he came to the
conclusion that a “socialistically organised society errs” when it “determines the value sub-
stance and the measure of value” (1885: 165) on the basis of labour and not on the basis of
use value, which is present in all goods as well as the monetary unit.
To sum up, Knies tried to understand the role that the institution of money plays in capitalism.
As part of his analysis, he demonstrated the problems that economic systems that abolish
money would face. In doing so, he employed and combined components 1b and 2 of Mises’s
argument.
8. Albert Schäffle on economic calculation under socialism and capitalism
Albert Schäffle (1831–1903) was a member of the German Historical School. He was a soci-
ologist, economist, and politician and Carl Menger’s direct predecessor at the University of
Vienna. Schäffle’s contribution to the economic calculation argument against socialism is
well established. Hodgson (2010) covers Schäffle’s Quintessence of Social Democracy, and
Braun (2016) focuses on his Kapitalismus und Socialismus. Schäffle (1878: 307 ff.) contains
another discussion on economic calculation under socialism. However, Schäffle (1878) is less
forceful than Schäffle (1870), probably because of some developing socialist tendencies in his
thinking. That is why I concentrate on Schäffle (1870) and confine myself to categorising its
contributions according to table 1.
In 1870, Schäffle was still convinced that socialism would be impossible. He stated explicitly
that it is “utopistic that the economy of a large people could be directed from a central point”
(Schäffle 1870: 192) and that it simply “cannot be done” (Schäffle 1870: 205). His argument
is reminiscent of component 4 of table 1:
23
Communism completely ignores […] the difficulty of governing national and interna-
tional societies from a single central point. You do not find any idea about how the
millions and squillions of people who are separated from each other by hemispheres
(locally) and by years, decades, even centuries (temporally) […] are supposed to be
governed by a host of civil servants such that they perform the economic valuation
process according to costs and utility (Schäffle 1870: 206).
Schäffle (1870) substantiated this claim with components 1a, 1b, 2, and 3. As Braun (2016)
focused on the role of 1a and 1b in Schäffle’s work (for component 1a see also Dekker 2016:
55 f.), the present paper concentrates on component 2, the necessity of capitalistic institutions
for rational economic calculation, and component 3, the necessity of money prices of the
means of production.
At the outset, Schäffle (1870: 19 ff., 92) distinguished clearly between capital goods
(Kapitalgüter) and capital (Kapitalvermögen). Whereas he defined capital goods as produced
means of production, as technical or physical elements of the production process, capital is
something entirely different. Capital “directs” and “organises” (Schäffle 1870: 21) the pro-
duction process via monetary calculation:
The reduction of all cost and use values to exchange values and money implies that
each invested particle of labour and each particle of already arranged product can be-
come and actually does become subject to calculation. An exactly developed econom-
ic art of calculation—bookkeeping and cost accounting—records all cost elements and
revenues in monetary terms, it records, in equal magnitudes of value, the entire pro-
cess of the never-ending transformation of capital [goods] and labour. […] Only now
it becomes and remains obvious where in the business and the household the conduct
of affairs has been economical and where it has not been so. (Schäffle 1870: 109, em-
phasis in original)
According to Schäffle, the capitalistic institutions of money, financial accounting, and private
property in the means of production make rational economic calculation possible. Capital,
understood as a correlate of these institutions, plays the essential role in the production pro-
cess. It “combines” the different assets that are technically necessary for the production of
24
specific goods. For example, the viticulturist combines, with his capital, all assets that are
necessary for the production of wine (Schäffle 1870: 109).
Schäffle is the only one of the authors discussed in this paper who even included compo-
nent 3 of Mises’s argument. He wrote that there is, at the societal level, a division of capital, a
coordination of the individual business assets of the numerous entrepreneurs in the different
stages of production. Schäffle (1870: 109-110) explained that the division and specialisation
of capital is made possible because the assets of all the individual enterprises together consti-
tute a large, intertwined production apparatus. The organic relationship of all capital goods in
this apparatus is created by the striving of the capital of each enterprise for the highest profit.
In this way, enterprises put checks and balances in place for each other. Their “competitive
seeking for profit has become the organising power of the economy” (Schäffle 1870: 114).
Schäffle (1870: 114) included the means of production in the higher stages of production in
his analysis of how capitalism is organised:
Each subsequent entrepreneur in the production chain takes vengeance for the ineffi-
ciency of his suppliers by refunding them less than they have disbursed. Competition
between all enterprises is objectively and imperatively inducing the highest efficiency
of the modern capitalistic structure of production.
In other words, Schäffle is aware of the role that the prices of the means of production play in
capitalistic societies. Schäffle’s discussion of the way enterprises organise the capitalistic
economy by orienting their actions towards monetary profits therefore foreshadows Mises’s
discussion in his magnum opus Human Action.
Schäffle’s Kapitalismus und Socialismus indeed does more than allude to the economic prob-
lem of socialism. It contains all components of Mises’s later argument against socialism and
demonstrates that what Mises did years later is closely connected to the research programme
of the Historical School. It was his analysis of capitalistic institutions—money, financial ac-
counting, private property, and the market—that led Schäffle to claim that socialism was un-
feasible.
I must add that Schäffle’s book is more than seven hundred pages long and is based on public
lectures. His arguments are scattered throughout the book and accompany treatments of philo-
sophical, sociological, and historical issues. Still, Schäffle had a very good sense of the role of
25
monetary calculation in capitalism and the problem any economic system would face if it
were to forgo capitalistic institutions.
9. Further members of the German Historical School on the impossibility of socialism
Lorenz von Stein (1815–1890) was a lawyer and economist who wrote extensively on the role
of capital and enterprises in capitalism. He is important in the history of economics and so-
cialism because he brought the first important debates on socialism in France to the attention
of the German public (Pasquino 1981: 1). Stein (1887: 370) did not focus on the role of eco-
nomic calculation, but it appears that he was aware of the problem. He declared that “50% of
all socialists believe in the promises of communism because they do not have an idea of even
the simplest accounting procedures”. He even claimed that “nobody who has learned to calcu-
late and to account could ever become a socialist”.
The German agronomist Georg Calberla (1845–1904) was not a direct member of the Histori-
cal School. In his critique of Marx, however, he referred to Gustav Schmoller and especially
Albert Schäffle as his two role models who had directed analysis of socialism to the right
channels (Calberla 1877: 11).
Calberla (1877: 46) stated that “a socialist system absolutely needs a measure of value in or-
der to distribute the social product”. However, Marx had made the “fateful error” of con-
structing “equal undifferentiated abstract human labour as the actual essence of value”. In his
book, Calberla (1877: 46) demonstrated “how wrong this is”.
According to Calberla (1877: 25), it is the “fundamental theorem of the entire socialist doc-
trine” that “the sole basis of [exchange] value is the human labour embodied in each com-
modity”. Calberla argued against this that labour cannot serve as a measure of value. He em-
ploys elements 1a and 1b (see table 1) in order to demonstrate this point. It is “not the intensi-
ty of human effort, not the duration of labour” that determines the value of the product of la-
bour but “the degree of urgency of the needs that the product can satisfy” (Calberla 1877: 30).
Therefore, different kinds of labour have different values, depending on the needs they can
satisfy. From a “subjective standpoint”, human labour is “not of equal value, not equally use-
ful, not equal” (Calberla 1877: 34).
As the fundamental theorem of socialism is wrong, Calberla (1877: 59) concludes that social-
ism is impossible:
26
[T]he most important foundations and necessary conditions of a social organisation
according to the recipe of present-day socialists are entirely called into question and
are not present if––as we have demonstrated––from a subjective standpoint human la-
bour is not equal and undifferentiated but profoundly diverse; and if the measure of its
value is not its duration but the degree of its social utility.
Calberla (1877) is a work of criticism. It deals with the problems of socialist systems. There-
fore, it does not contain an analysis of capitalistic institutions (component 2 of table 1). But
Calberla was well aware of the role that these institutions play. In a short passage, he stated:
“Everyone has to admit that production on the basis of free, individual property and the ex-
change of value by means of general signs of value [money] are the preconditions of the pre-
sent-day degree of material emancipation of humanity” (Calberla 1877: 58). Private property
and money appear to be necessary for the division of labour in modern societies.
A brief comment is warranted on the so-called younger Historical School around Gustav
Schmoller and Adolph Wagner. This school is sometimes referred to as “socialism of the
chair.” However, as Bunyk and Krasnozhon (2022: 180 f.) explain, while the younger Histor-
ical School was arguing for an interventionist state and social policy, it could hardly be called
socialistic. On the contrary, an important impulse for the social reform activities Schmoller
organised and directed since the early 1870s was his fear of socialist revolution (Grimmer-
Solem 2003b: 107). And even though I was not able to trace the calculation argument in the
literature of the younger Historical School, Wagner (1907: 692) at least echoed Bruno Hilde-
brand’s point briefly. Despite his sympathy for some socialist ideas, he stated explicitly that
the “realisation of the Socialistic system of economy makes demands upon the intellectual
and moral qualities of men […] which all that we know of men […] shows to be pitched far
too high.”
10. The continuing importance of the institutional theory of capital
In the socialist calculation debate, Oskar Lange and Abba Lerner opposed the idea, propagat-
ed by Mises, that socialism would fail without a market in which the prices for the means and
factors of production could be determined. They backed their position with mathematical
standard models. As Boettke et al. (2014: 283) explain, the Lange–Lerner theorem basically
applied neoclassical economics to a socialist system. These authors and their followers main-
27
tained that a central planning board could act as a Walrasian auctioneer by announcing and
adjusting prices until equilibrium is achieved. The neoclassical general equilibrium model
was supposed to describe not only capitalist market economies but also socialist economies
(Hodgson 2016: 37). The applicability of the model was thought to be independent of the ac-
tual institutional context.
In contrast, Mises position was that the rational allocation of resources, described by the neo-
classical equilibrium model, is contingent on a certain institutional and historical background.
Only in a market economy where private property rights in the means of production are up-
held and the institutions of monetary calculation exist can societal resources be reasonably
evaluated according to their utility for the final consumer. Socialism, which does not have or
even actively rejects these institutions, is therefore not able to evaluate and economise its re-
sources.
One basic element of Mises’s argument––the institutional theory to capital––has since been
abandoned by large parts of the economics profession (Hodgson 2014: 1077). Tellingly, the
three-volume collection of seminal papers on capital theory published by Edward Elgar in
2005 contains only two (out of a total of 71) contributions that are associated with this theory:
Schumpeter (2005) and a few, mainly polemical pages in Veblen (2005: 161-167).
We must not overlook the fact that the adherents of the institutional approach to capital are at
least partly to blame for its neglect. Apart from Veblen’s contribution, the three major contro-
versies on capital in the history of economics took place without notable interference by ad-
vocates of the institutional approach. Neither the Austrians Menger and Mises nor the respec-
tive generations of Historical School economists entered the debate. Furthermore, what may
have been the most extensive attempt to develop the institutional theory of capital, Mises
(1966), has been neglected not only by his intellectual opponents but also by most of his fol-
lowers in the Austrian School, who preferred and still prefer the standard Austrian theory of
capital, which defines capital as a physical factor of production.
From a current perspective, this must be considered a loss for economic science. The institu-
tional theory of capital does not exhaust itself in the critique of socialism. Its purpose is to
describe important processes within the market economy and how they depend on certain
institutional preconditions. These processes are at risk of being jeopardised not only by the
outright socialisation of the means of production. Any reform of these institutions may have
28
important, possibly undesirable consequences for the creation and distribution of wealth in
market societies.
To give an important example, by abandoning the institutional theory of capital, economists
have deported themselves of the ability to comment profoundly on the implications of the far-
reaching reforms of financial accounting and corporate governance witnessed in recent dec-
ades. This is not the place to comment on the viability of these reforms. The point is that they
concern activities of capitalistic enterprises, particularly monetary calculation and profit-
making, which are described and explained by the institutional theory of capital. Therefore,
this theory is not only important for demonstrating certain problems of socialism; it may also
serve as a basis for explaining and commenting on somewhat related problems that have
haunted capitalistic economies since at least the 1980s, especially the increasing macroeco-
nomic instability and the supposed or actual tendency of managers toward short-termism.
9. Conclusion
Mises’s argument against the feasibility of socialism is based on the institutional setting pecu-
liar to a certain economic system in a specific period of time. According to Mises, it is the
institutions of private property, money, markets, and monetary calculation of the capitalistic
enterprise that make possible rational economic calculation in capitalism. In socialism these
institutions do not exist, or at least exist only in a crippled form, and therefore no rational
economic calculation is possible.
This paper has demonstrated two points. First, Mises’s argument was foreshadowed by sever-
al members of the Historical School: Friedrich Julius Stahl, Bruno Hildebrand, Karl Knies,
Albert Schäffle, and Georg Calberla. Second, these contributions should not be viewed with
surprise. The members of the German Historical School of Economics were interested in the
historically specific institutions of capitalism. They wanted to understand how and why capi-
talism works—that is, how the international division of labour was made possible in the mar-
ket economy. By doing so, they came to the institutions that Mises would employ in his ar-
gument against socialism. Their institutional theory of capital explains the role of these insti-
tutions in the production process.
Starting from their interest in these institutions, some members of the Historical School not
only anticipated Mises’s argument but developed an approach to capital that incorporated
these institutions. Menger (1888) adopted this approach, and it is highly probable that the
29
contributions of the Historical School influenced Mises’s thinking indirectly via Menger’s
essay. In my opinion, backed up throughout this paper, the Historical School deserves some
credit for Mises’s contribution on the possibilities and preconditions of economic calculation
in different economic systems. Further, economists should revive its institutional theory of
capital, as it could serve as a tool for understanding the current reforms in financial account-
ing and corporate governance.
References
Boettke, P. J., C. J. Coyne and P. T. Leeson (2014). ‘Hayek versus the neoclassicists: Lessons
from the socialist calculation debate’, in R. W. Garrison and N. Barry (eds.), Elgar compan-
ion to Hayekian economics. Cheltenham et al.: Elgar, pp. 278–293.
Braun, E. (2015a). ‘Carl Menger’s Contribution to Capital Theory’, History of Economic Ide-
as, 23(1): 77–99.
Braun, E. (2015b). ‘Unsuspected Origins of Modern Austrian Economics: The Historical
School of Economics on Capital and Economic Calculation’, in P. Bylund and D. Howden
(eds.), The Next Generation of Austrian Economics, Auburn (AL): Mises Institue, pp. 75–87.
Braun, E. (2016). ‘The German historical school on the impossibility of economic calculation
under socialism’, Betriebswirtschaftliche Forschung und Praxis, 68(2): 126–35.
Braun, E. (2017). ‘The theory of capital as a theory of capitalism’, Journal of Institutional
Economics, 13(2): 305–25.
Braun, E. (2020), ‘Carl Menger: Contribution to the Theory of Capital (1888), Section V’,
Journal of Institutional Economics, 16(4): 557–68.
Braun, E. and M. Wollboldt (2022), Friedrich Julius Stahl (1802–1861) on the impossibility
of socialism,
https://www.researchgate.net/publication/365704347_Friedrich_Julius_Stahl_1802-
1861_on_the_impossibility_of_socialism
30
Braun, E., P. Lewin and N. Cachanosky (2016), ‘Ludwig von Mises’s Approach to Capital as
a Bridge between Austrian and Institutional Economics’, Journal of Institutional Econom-
ics, 12(4): 847–66.
Bunyk, M. and L. Krasnozhon (2022), ‘Young Mr. Mises and younger historicists: origins
of Mises’s liberalism’, Review of Austrian Economics, 35(2): 177–191.
Calberla, G. M. (1877), Karl Marx, „Das Kapital“ und der heutige Sozialismus. Kritik einig-
er ihrer Fundamentalsätze, Dresden: Schönfeld.
Dekker, E. (2016), The Viennese students of Civilization: Humility, Culture and Economics in
Interwar Vienna and Beyond, Doctoral Thesis. Erasmus University Rotterdam.
Dönniges, W. v. (1845), ‘Ueber die wissenschaftliche und praktische Bedeutung des Socia-
lismus und Communismus‘, Allgemeine Zeitung, 1845(69): 545–47; (70): 554–57; (71): 563–
65; (72): 572–74
Drucker, P. F. (1933), Friedrich Julius Stahl: konservative Staatslehre und geschichtliche
Entwicklung, Tübingen: Mohr.
Ebeling, R. M. (2003), ‘Economic calculation under socialism: Ludwig von Mises and his
predecessors’, in R. M. Ebeling, Austrian Economics and the Political Economy of Freedom,
Cheltenham and Northampton: Edward Elgar, pp. 101–35.
Grimmer-Solem, E. (2003a), The Rise of Historical Economics and Social Reform in Germa-
ny 1864-1894, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Grimmer-Solem, E. (2003b), ‘Imperialist Socialism of the Chair. Gustav Schmoller and Ger-
man Weltpolitik, 1897-1905‘, in: G. Eley and J. Retallack (eds.), Wilhelminism and Its Lega-
cies, New York and Oxford: Berghahn Books, pp. 106-121.
31
Hauwe, L. v. d. (2019), ‘Ludwig von Mises’ Argument Against the Possibility of Socialism:
Early Concepts and Contemporary Relevance’, in J. Backhaus et al. (eds.): The First Sociali-
zation Debate (1918) and Early Efforts Towards Socialization, Cham: Springer, pp. 191–222.
Hayek, F. A. (1937), ‘Economics and Knowledge’, Economica (New Series), 4(13): 33–54.
Hayek, F. A. (1945), ‘The Use of Knowledge in Society’, American Economic Review, 35(4):
519–30.
Hayek, F. A. (2014), The Collected Works of F. A. Hayek, Vol. XV, edited by B. Caldwell,
Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.
Hildebrand, B. ([1848] (1922)), Die Nationalökonomie der Gegenwart und Zukunft und ande-
re gesammelte Schriften, Jena: Fischer.
Hodgson, G. M. (2010), ‘Albert Schäffle’s critique of socialism’, in: J. Vint (ed.), Econnomic
Theory and Economic Thought, London et al.: Routledge, pp. 296–315.
Hodgson, G. M. (2014), ‘What is capital? Economists and sociologists have changed its
meaning: should it be changed back?’, Cambridge Journal of Economics, 38(5): 1063–1086.
Hodgson, G. M. (2015), ‘Much of the ‘economics of property rights’ devalues property and
legal rights’, Journal of Institutional Economics, 11(4): 683–709.
Hodgson, G. M. (2016), ‘Some Limitations of the Socialist Calculation Debate’, Schmollers
Jahrbuch, 136(1): 33-58.
Hülsmann, J. G. (1997), ‘Knowledge, Judgment, and the Use of Property’, Review of Austrian
Economics, 10(1): 23-48.
Knies, K. (1885), Geld und Credit. Vol I: Das Geld. Darlegung der Grundlehren von dem
Gelde, 2nd edition, Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung.
32
Kolev, S. and E. Dekker (2022), ‘Carl Menger’s Smithian contributions to German political
Economy’, Review of Austrian Economics, online first
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11138-022-00602-y
Lewin, P. and N. Cachanosky (2018), ‘Substance and semantics: The question of capital’,
Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 150: 423-431.
Marx, K. (1859), Zur Kritik der Politischen Oekonomie, Berlin: Duncker.
Menger, C. (1888), ‘Zur Theorie des Kapitals’, Jahrbücher für Nationalökonomie und Statis-
tik, 17: 1–49.
Mises, L. v. ([1920] (2012)), Economic Calculation in the Socialist Commonwealth, translat-
ed from German by S. Adler, Auburn (AL): Mises Institute.
Mises, L. v. ([1932] (1951)), Socialism. An Economic and Sociological Analysis, translated
by J. Kahane, New Haven: Yale University Press
Mises, L. v. (1966), Human Action: A Treatise on Economics, 3rd edition, Chicago: Henry
Regnery.
Pasquino, P. (1981), ‘Introduction to Lorenz von Stein’, Economy and Society, 10(1), 1-6.
Raico, R. (1995), ‘The Austrian School and Classical Liberalism’, Advances in Austrian Eco-
nomics, 2A: 3-38.
Roscher, W. (1864), System der Volkswirthschaft. Vol. 1, 5th edition, Stuttgart: Cotta.
Roos, N. H. M. (1994), ‘Hayek’s Kantian Heritage and Natural Law’, in J. Birner and R. v.
Zijp (eds.), Hayek, Co-ordination and Evolution, London and New York: Routledge, pp. 287-
307.
33
Savigny, F. C. v. ([1814] (1973)), ‘Vom Beruf unsrer Zeit für Gesetzgebung und Rechtswis-
senschaft’, in H. Hattenhauer (ed.), Thibaut und Savigny. Ihre programmatischen Schriften,
München: Franz Vahlen, pp. 95–192.
Savigny, F. C. v. ([1815] (1973)), ‘Über den Zweck dieser Zeitschrift’, in H. Hattenhauer, H.
(ed.), Thibaut und Savigny. Ihre programmatischen Schriften, München: Franz Vahlen, pp.
261–68.
Schäffle, A. E. F. (1870), Kapitalismus und Socialismus mit besonderer Rücksicht auf Ge-
schäfts- und Vermögensformen, Tübingen: Laupp.
Schumpeter, J. A. (2005), ‘Interest on Capital’, in C. Bliss, A. J. Cohen and G. C. Harcourt
(eds.), Capital Theory. Vol. 1. Cheltenham (UK) and Northampton (MA): Elgar, pp. 350-404.
Sombart, W. (1919), Der moderne Kapitalismus, Volume 2.1, München and Leipzig: Duncker
& Humblot.
Sombart, W. (1927), Der moderne Kapitalismus, Volume 3.1, München and Leipzig: Duncker
& Humblot.
Stahl, F. J. (1846), Die Philosophie des Rechts. Vol. 2: Rechts- und Staatslehre auf der
Grundlage christlicher Weltanschauung. Sect. 2: Die Lehre vom Staat und die Principien des
deutschen Staatsrechts, 2nd edition, Heidelberg: Mohr.
Stahl, F. J. (1847), Die Philosophie des Rechts. Vol. 1: Geschichte der Rechtsphilosophie, 2nd
edition, Heidelberg: Mohr.
Stahl, F. J. (1863), Die gegenwärtigen Parteien in Staat und Kirche, Berlin: Verlag von Wil-
helm Hertz.
Stahl, F. J. (1978), The present-day parties in the state and church: twenty-nine academic
lectures, State College (PA): Blenheim Publishing House.
34
Stein, L. v. (1887), Lehrbuch der Nationalökonomie, Wien: Manz.
Streissler, E. W. (1990), ‘The influence of German economics on the work of Menger and
Marshall’, History of Political Economy, 22(S1), 31-68.
Veblen, T. (2005), ‘Professor Clark’s Economics’, in C. Bliss, A. J. Cohen and G. C. Har-
court (eds.), Capital Theory. Vol. 1, Cheltenham (UK) and Northampton (MA): Elgar, pp.
445-493.
Wagner, A. (1907), ‘The Rights and Wrongs of Socialism’, Fortnightly Review, 81(484): 682-
694.
Witt, U. (1997), ‘The Hayekian Puzzle: Spontaneous Order and the Business Cycle’, Scottish
Journal of Political Economy, 44(1): 44-58.
Zwiedineck-Südenhorst, O. v. (1930), ‘Kapital und Kapitalismus’, Schmollers Jahrbuch,
54(2): 1059-1092.