Content uploaded by Tim Lomas
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Tim Lomas on Mar 17, 2023
Content may be subject to copyright.
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
1
Towards an Expanded Taxonomy of Happiness:
A Conceptual Analysis of 16 Distinct Forms of Mental Wellbeing
Journal of Humanistic Psychology
Dr. Tim Lomas, Harvard University, tlomas@hsph.harvard.edu
Prof. Tyler J. VanderWeele, Harvard University
Abstract
Recent decades have seen a surge of scientific interest in happiness. However, its theoretical
conceptualisation is a work in progress. Much of the literature focuses on two main forms:
hedonic (encompassing life satisfaction and positive affect), and eudaimonic (encompassing
phenomena such as character development and meaning in life). However, this binary has
been critiqued as being incomplete, in part because it reflects a Western-centric perspective
that overlooks forms emphasised in non-Western cultures. As a result, scholars have begun to
highlight other forms besides hedonia and eudaimonia. This paper surveys the literature to
identify 16 potential forms in total, classified according to whether they primarily pertain to
feelings (hedonic, contended, mature, chaironic, and vital), thought (evaluative, meaningful,
intellective, aesthetic, and absorbed) or action (eudaimonic, masterful, accomplished,
harmonic, nirvanic, and relational). The paper thus offers a more expansive, albeit still just
provisional, taxonomy of this vital and still-evolving topic.
Key words: happiness; wellbeing; health; taxonomy; cross-cultural.
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
2
Few concepts are as cherished in the modern era as happiness. Indeed, variants of this state
have been a human concern throughout history (Lomas et al., 2021). Yet few phenomena are
perhaps so contested, with little consensus on its nature. That said, recent decades have seen
an expansive scientific effort to conceptualise and study the topic. This paper explores this
process of conceptualisation, offering a provisional typology of different forms of happiness.
What is Happiness?
Before delving into the various forms, it is worth contextualising and defining the concept
itself, and situating it relative to other related notions. Thus, the following is a basic set of
orienting definitions that, although by no means the only way of configuring the territory, is
parsimonious with most of the relevant literature. It will help to begin with wellbeing, which
most scholars regard as an overarching concept that includes happiness within. Our reason for
starting with wellbeing is to situate happiness within a broader framework of relevant ideas,
thereby allowing a more comprehensive understanding of its nature and significance. One
issue with happiness research is that it is often unmoored from other similar concerns and
related fields, with different disciplines that share areas of interest speaking past each other.
Consider that arguably the most prominent concept in happiness scholarship is Diener’s
operationalization of subjective wellbeing (SWB), featuring an affective (i.e., positive affect)
and an evaluative component (i.e., life satisfaction/evaluation) (Diener et al., 1999). We are
indebted to Diener’s pioneering efforts, which has inspired decades of research. However,
most of this fails to elucidate how SWB relates conceptually to myriad other concepts that
deploy the term “wellbeing,” qualified with various adjectives. Take for instance the WHO’s
(1948) influential definition of health as “a state of complete physical, mental and social
well-being, and not merely the absence of disease and infirmity.” Rarely does work on SWB
attempt to place the concept in relation to the three dimensions in this definition, nor to the
many other wellbeing-related constructs in the literature, from spiritual wellbeing (Larson,
1996) to economic wellbeing (Bakar et al., 2015). Instead, SWB tends to be a free-floating
psychological construct – just an independent or dependent variable of interest – without
much articulation of its status in a wider taxonomy of wellbeing.
Our position is that happiness constitutes a subset of wellbeing, and specifically a
subset pertaining to mental wellbeing. Therefore, to explicate this conceptual nesting, it is
necessary to first outline an understanding of wellbeing more broadly, within which we can
then situate happiness. We have begun to develop a theoretical framework of wellbeing – and
related concepts like health and flourishing – at length elsewhere (Lomas & VanderWeele,
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
3
2022; VanderWeele & Lomas, 2022), of which we offer a brief summary here to allow our
taxonomy of happiness to be placed within this broader context of ideas. With wellbeing, as
per happiness, this too has been notoriously difficult to operationalise. Reviewing trends in
conceptualizations of wellbeing for the 2022 World Happiness Report, Barrington-Leigh
(2022) suggests that while its use has risen sharply recently, it is “typically poorly defined.”
Given this confusion, we have formulated our own conceptualization of wellbeing, which
involves two subtly different definitions, both with the same key words. First, we view
wellbeing as the quality of one’s personal state. We use “personal” to differentiate it from
flourishing, which we regard as personal and systemic: while wellbeing applies specifically
to humans, flourishing applies to humans and the myriad contexts – both human (e.g.,
communities) and non-human (e.g., the natural environment) – in which they are situated.
“State” signifies a condition or mode of being that is not permanent, but can vary widely in
duration (from a fleeting emotion to a durable way of being that could even last for years).
Finally, we harness the idea of “quality,” as deployed in notions of quality of life, a common
framing in work on wellbeing (Nussbaum & Sen, 1993), and which has further been explored
by Pirsig (1974), for whom it represents a fundamental and irreducible sense of a
phenomenon being deemed good or valuable in some way (Reeves & Bednar, 1994).
We then define the parameters of this state using the concepts of illness and health.
Illness denotes a relative absence of wellbeing, as signified by undesirable phenomena known
collectively by terms such as diseases, disorders, and injuries. Conversely, health describes
not merely the absence of those undesirable phenomena, but the active presence or attainment
of certain desiderata. Thus, we define health as a personal state of quality, and conversely
illness as a personal state lacking quality. Crucially, relative absence of illness is not the
same as active presence of health. Such insights have been especially prominent in the realm
of mental wellbeing. Traditionally the field has focused on mental illness, as acknowledged
by Freud, who saw the goal of psychotherapy as generally limited to turning “hysterical
misery into ordinary unhappiness” (Breuer & Freud, 1955, p.308). However, a growing
movement of scholars – led by humanistic psychologists like Maslow (1962) – have argued
that being ostensibly free of mental illness does not necessarily mean a person is actively
thriving. Instead, they may just be languishing – not ill per se, but not excelling either (Keyes,
2007). Thus, these scholars argued for also focusing on positive forms of health. As Maslow
put it, “It is as if Freud supplied us the sick half of psychology and we must now fill it out
with the healthy half (p.5). So, using these definitions, wellbeing serves as an overarching
concept, encompassing illness and health. However, in common language wellbeing can also
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
4
be used, as per health, to describe the attainment of desirable forms of that state. As such, our
second definition of wellbeing is the same as that for health: a personal state of quality.
We acknowledge these definitions may seem sparse or generic compared to others in
the literature. However, these initial formulations serve as a semantic building block, upon
which more specific forms of wellbeing can be operationalized by adapting the definitions as
needed. This includes tailoring the definitions for different forms of happiness, as outlined
below. First though we can start by applying them to different dimensions of existence. There
are many ways of conceptualising this complex ontological terrain, but one common framing
is to acknowledge physical, mental, and social dimensions of existence, as per the WHO’s
definition of health. In addition, some scholars suggest that we ought to recognize spiritual
wellbeing (Larson, 1996; VanderWeele, 2020). Together, we refer to these four dimensions
as the “WHO+” ontological framework. We can therefore adapt the generic definitions of
wellbeing to apply to these dimensions specifically. For example, one can describe mental
wellbeing as pertaining to the quality of one’s mental state (definition 1) – with “personal”
now omitted as superfluous, since mental states are inherently personal – and its attainment
(i.e., mental health) as a mental state of quality (definition 2), while mental illness is a mental
state lacking quality. One could similarly adapt these for the other dimensions by switching
the operative adjective.
Here is where happiness re-enters the conversation. Essentially, we deploy this term
expansively to denote almost the entire positive territory of the mental wellbeing dimension.
Thus, we define happiness as a mental experience of quality (with “mental” encompassing all
qualia, including emotions). Note this is very close to, but subtly different from, the definition
of mental wellbeing, as it refers to an experience rather than a state. The reason is happiness
may not cover the entire realm of mental wellbeing, which also involves the various faculties
of the mind – attention, perception, memory, etc. – broadly “working well.” So, we describe
this entire realm using “state,” within which is the narrower terrain of subjective experience,
for which we use the label happiness. Again, we note this definition of happiness may seem
sparse or generic and even unusual compared to others. However, per our operationalization
of wellbeing, it is constructed to fit within a broader framework of ideas, and moreover, to be
adapted to different types of happiness, of which we identify 16 forms. In conceptualizing
happiness in this way, we explicitly advocate an expansive vision of the topic, encompassing
a significant range of psychological territory. Like many interesting signifiers, happiness is a
contested construct. Some people use it narrowly, perhaps merely synonymous with pleasure.
By contrast, others – us included – use it far more expansively, encompassing a wide swathe
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
5
of positive mental states. This linguistic point can be understood using a cartographic
metaphor. One function of language is to map our experiential world (Lomas, 2018). In that
respect, some words cover more “ground” than others, and encompass related words within.
Love, for instance, has been described as an “empire uniting all sorts of feelings, behaviours,
and attitudes, sometimes having little in common” (Murstein, 1988, p.33). Then, within that
empire, one can find words covering specific regions, from “passion” to “care.” Our view of
happiness is similarly broad, covering nearly the entire positive territory of mental wellbeing,
from the lowest possible increment into this realm (e.g., the mildest, briefest moment of
positive affect) to its farthest possible reaches (e.g., the most intense, long-lasting positive
experiences conceivable). In that respect, this paper offers a typology of forms of happiness
within this broad territory. That said, this taxonomy is also still useable and relevant for
people who define happiness more narrowly, and who may prefer to regard some forms here
as simply aspects of mental wellbeing rather than happiness per se.
An Evolving Taxonomy
In the 80 or so years since the likes of Maslow first emphasised the importance of attending
to the positive terrain of mental wellbeing – which we label broadly as happiness – research
and theory has steadily accumulated. This evolving body of scholarship is illustrated in
Figure 1, which presents the 16 forms of happiness in our taxonomy in terms of five different
“bands.” These bands have two related functions, indicating both: (a) conceptualizations of
happiness in terms of narrowness-broadness (with band 1 the narrowest, and 5 the broadest);
and (b) chronological emergence (with 1 the earliest main focus of academic scholarship, and
5 the most recent). Overall, most work has tended to focus on two main types, hedonic (band
1) and eudaimonic (band 2). This distinction has a long pedigree, usually traced to Aristotle
(1986), who depicted the former as simple states of pleasure, and the latter as deeper forms of
happiness arising through self-cultivation, being the “activity of the soul in accordance with
virtue” (p.11). However, we suggest this binary actually incorporates other experiences which
warrant treating as distinct forms, as elucidated below. Initially, most work focused on
hedonic happiness, particularly through the prism of SWB, which emerged in the 1950s
before coming to prominence especially through the work of Diener in the 1980s (Diener et
al., 1999). This is represented as band 1, in which we use “hedonic happiness” only for the
affective component of SWB, and present its evaluative component (i.e., life satisfaction) as a
separate form of “evaluative happiness.” This was soon augmented by a growing interest in
eudaimonic wellbeing, which can be traced back to humanistic psychologists like Maslow,
but especially attracted attention following Ryff’s (1989) work on “psychological wellbeing.”
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
6
This strand of theorising constitutes band 2, which involves eudaimonic happiness per se, as
well as three other forms which are usually bound up with eudaimonia – which in modern
scholarship has swelled to often become a catch-all for anything non-hedonic – but which we
treat as distinct forms, including meaningful, masterful, and accomplished happiness.
Figure 1. An emergent chronology of happiness constructs.
However, as important as hedonia and eudaimonia – and the four other forms we have
extracted from them – may be, they do not exhaustively cover the broad terrain we designate
as happiness. To start with, in Authentic Happiness, Seligman (2002) suggests “engagement”
constitutes one of three “pathways” to mental wellbeing (alongside hedonia and eudaimonia).
This is reflected in Csikszentmihalyi’s (1990) notion of flow, which we label as “absorbed
happiness,” accompanied in band 3 by two newer proposed forms that also pertain to
engagement (aesthetic and vital). From there, happiness research continued to develop. Wong
(2011) formulated the idea of positive psychology 2.0, also known as the field’s second wave
(Lomas & Ivtzan, 2016). This critiqued the field for initially focusing mainly on positively-
valenced phenomena, and overlooking the relevance to wellbeing of states that are neutral or
even negatively-valenced. This work is represented as band 4, featuring three types proposed
by Wong (contented, mature, and chaironic).
Building on this scholarship, Lomas et al. (2021) developed the idea of a third wave
of the field. A driving force of Wong’s work is the recognition that happiness research – and
psychology as a whole – is Western-centric, with Henrich et al. (2010) suggesting the vast
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
7
majority of research in psychology has been conducted by and on people in contexts that are
WEIRD (Western, Educated, Industrialized, Rich, and Democratic). Thus, drawing on his
Chinese background, Wong proposed happiness forms valued especially in Eastern cultures.
Lomas et al. then suggested this work was part of a broader third wave to expand beyond the
field’s Western-centricity and engage with happiness-related ideas from across the globe.
This shift is exemplified by the Global Wellbeing Initiative, which involves developing new
items for the Gallup World Poll that reflect non-Western perspectives on wellbeing, including
ones relating to four forms detailed below (contented, eudaimonic, harmonic, and relational),
as featured in the 2022 World Happiness Report (Lomas, Lai, et al., 2022). Thus, from this
third wave are emerging still newer proposed constructs pertaining to happiness, labelled here
as band 5, including harmonic, relational and nirvanic. Moreover, these developments are not
limited to positive psychology: Lomas (2022a) suggests its third wave is part of a broader
new wave of “global wellbeing scholarship” that not only involves other kinship fields within
psychology (e.g., humanistic psychology), but other academic disciplines, such as Tay and
Pawelski’s (2021) emerging “positive humanities” paradigm. Indeed, it is possible and even
likely that these new movements – which are still in their early phases – will identify other
forms of happiness beyond the 16 included here. One of the authors for instance has recently
received a grant to explore Muslim perspectives on wellbeing, which have hitherto received
little attention in psychology. It may be that such projects will mean the taxonomy will need
updating, with new forms perhaps added to band 5, and indeed future research may well
generate further emergent bands we cannot yet even envisage (see e.g., Lomas, 2022b, for
speculations regarding future directions in wellbeing scholarship).
As such, even while this paper represents our best attempt to survey the terrain of
happiness as it stands, it is a dynamically evolving picture, so our framework is only a
provisional account of the current literature and may need updating with future scholarship.
Moreover, we acknowledge that scholars differ in how expansively they view happiness, and
might not regard all these types as constituting happiness per se. Some may prefer to use the
term only for SWB, and will regard the forms in bands 2-5 as outside the remit of happiness.
Others may have a slightly wider scope, perhaps expanding to bands 2 and 3. Yet others –
including us – take a yet broader view, encompassing all five bands. Whatever preference
people have is fine; regardless of labels per se, all these forms will still likely be of interest to
all these scholars. Thus, for those who take a narrower view, whichever forms are regarded as
outside the realm of happiness could simply be labelled as forms of mental wellbeing. Then,
in addition to grouping the forms by bands in an emergent chronology, we also sought to
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
8
bring a different conceptual order to the taxonomy by classifying types according to whether
they primarily involve one of three main experiential modalities, as illustrated in Figure 2:
feeling (types 1-5); thinking (6-10); and doing (11-16). Of course, every form likely involves
all three modalities in some way, as experience is generally multidimensional. Moreover, a
given experience of happiness may well combine several types, as if distinct flavours
combining to form a unique taste. Nevertheless, this classificatory approach is a useful
heuristic. We have also sought to bring consistency to the taxonomy by using our basic
definition of happiness (a mental experience of quality) and building upon it in various ways
to identify specific forms. Moreover, using this basic definition in turn allows this taxonomy
to be situated within our broader framework of wellbeing. As a final point, we recognize this
is a novel framework that requires validation in future research. As such, for each form we
offer hypotheses that could be explored, followed in the conclusion by some broader ideas for
a research program into this new taxonomy.
Figure 2. An expanded taxonomy of happiness.
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
9
Feeling Types
1. Hedonic
These first five forms pertain primarily to feelings. By far the most widely studied is what is
often called “hedonic” happiness. The dominant construct here is SWB, comprising two main
dimensions: cognitive (life evaluation/satisfaction) and affective (hedonic tone). We reserve
hedonic happiness for the latter though, with the former – which is not really about hedonism,
conventionally understood – constituting a distinct form of evaluative happiness, discussed
below. This affective dimension pertains to how people feel right now (or relatively recently),
usually conceptualised in terms of a ratio of positive to negative affect (Watson et al., 1988).
Calculations of this ratio thereby generate an appraisal of the affective dimension of SWB,
hence – on our conceptualization here – of hedonic happiness. Appraisals of positive affect
usually focus on high arousal forms, possibly reflecting the valorisation of such emotions in
Western cultures (Tsai et al., 2006). As such, low arousal forms – like calmness – tend to be
overlooked. One option would be to ensure hedonic happiness includes these. However, to
emphasise their distinctiveness, we treat low arousal states as a separate form of contented
happiness, considered next. So, we define hedonic happiness as a mental experience of
quality in relation to one’s present emotions and feelings, with particular emphasis on higher
arousal varieties. Another potentially relevant point of distinction may be attention. Although
hedonic happiness has higher levels of arousal than contented, we predict it may actually
have lower attentiveness, particularly orienting and executive forms of attention (Posner &
Petersen, 1990), since the latter are primarily about attentional control, and evidence links
high arousal pleasure to reduced attentional control (Schwebel et al., 2009).
2. Contented
This first neglected form of happiness covers the emotional territory of low arousal positive
affect (McManus et al., 2019). While often overlooked in favour of high arousal forms, as
noted above, scholars are now paying greater attention to cultural perspectives that emphasise
these emotions. In psychospiritual traditions like Hinduism and Buddhism, for instance,
qualities of equanimity and detachment are valorised as reflecting an ability to eschew
attachments (seen as a cause of suffering), as captured by the Quiet Ego scale (Wayment et
al., 2015). To that point, such traditions corroborate our hypothesis that attentiveness may be
higher in contented than hedonic happiness, since they have a wealth of meditative practices
which, (a) function primarily by training attention, and (b) are associated in particular with
contented happiness (Kabat-Zinn, 2003). This observation prompts another hypothesis: since
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
10
research on meditation shows attention can be trained, this suggests that contented happiness
can be more readily cultivated (e.g., through meditation) than hedonic happiness (which is
less about attentional control, so in that respect is less easily generated). Moreover, such
happiness may be more universally valued than often appreciated. Exploring lay perceptions
of happiness in 12 countries across five continents, Delle Fave et al. (2016) found the most
prominent definition was one of “inner harmony,” involving inner peace, contentment, and
balance. Similarly widespread patterns were also observed in the Global Wellbeing Initiative,
which found that low arousal states were universally sought and experienced (Lomas et al.,
2022). While some scholars may prefer to expand hedonia to encompass these forms, the
connection between hedonia and high arousal is so established – as are broader cultural
associations with hedonism – that low arousal forms are better treated as their own distinct
form, defined as a mental experience of quality in relation to one’s present emotions and
feelings, with particular emphasis on lower arousal varieties.
3. Mature
While contented happiness covers relatively neutral positive emotional states, some theorists
argue that happiness can even encompass negatively valenced states. To that point, Wong has
proposed the notion of “mature happiness” (Wong & Bowers, 2019). A key influence here is
Frankl (1963), who powerfully argued meaning and redemption can be found even amidst the
difficulties of life. Going further, these issues may even be sources of positive mental states.
This insight rests on the recognition that people’s very experience of suffering may actually
be causally connected to subsequent experiences and appreciation of wellbeing – an insight
similarly recognised in the literature on post-traumatic growth, described by Tedeschi et al.
(1998) as “positive changes in the aftermath of crisis.” However, this realisation does not
necessarily come easily, but may require hard-won experience, hence “mature.” This form
might thus be conceived as a mental experience of quality regarding the way one has dealt
with suffering in one’s life. Although a relatively new construct per se, Wong and Bowers'
Mature Happiness Scale has begun to receive empirical validation (Carreno et al., 2021).
Moreover, there is an extensive literature on phenomena pertaining to mental wellbeing that
can be viewed through the lens of mature happiness, including post-traumatic growth, work
on “redemption narratives” (McAdams et al., 2012), and new research on people’s preference
for a “psychologically rich life,” involving diverse experiences and emotions, including
negatively valenced ones (Oishi & Westgate, 2021). In terms of better understanding the
dynamics here, an intriguing research question concerns the distinction between affective
versus cognitive valence (i.e., thoughts being positive or negative in tone). Even if mature
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
11
happiness usually has negative affective valence, we suggest it is likely characterised by
positive cognitive valence, with even negative emotions interpreted in constructive ways.
4. Chaironic
Although hedonic happiness focuses on high arousal forms of positive affect, it tends not to
broach its most intense or significant forms (instead invoking less highly charged states like
enjoyment and pleasure). As such, Wong (2011) has also proposed the idea of chaironic
happiness, based on the Greek chairo, which has meanings like gladness, joy, bliss, grace and
blessing. Given its etymology, one might construe this as a form of spiritual happiness,
defined as “feeling blessed and fortunate because of a sense of awe, gratitude, and oneness
with nature or God” (p.70). Again, while a relatively new construct, it rests upon a substantial
literature connecting spirituality to happiness – and wellbeing more broadly – a paradigm
known as the “religion health connection” (Ellison & Levin, 1998). Although most such work
treats spirituality as a factor which influences happiness, some presents spirituality itself as a
form of happiness (Fisher, 2010), which we label “chaironic happiness,” defined as a mental
experience of quality in relation to some kind of spiritual or transcendent reality. This of
course overlaps with the subtly different idea of spiritual wellbeing, with chaironic happiness
being an experience of such spirituality, rather than the state of spiritual wellbeing itself.
Spirituality of course is itself a complex and contested construct (Hill et al., 2000), so further
research is needed to further elucidate this form. To that end, we suggest different forms of
happiness may vary in the frequency with which they are experienced. So, drawing on work
such as Maslow’s (1962) concept of peak experiences, we hypothesise chaironic happiness
may be among the rarest forms, both in terms of populations (i.e., relatively few people
experience it), and people themselves (i.e., those that attain it do so relatively infrequently).
5. Vital
Of the five forms classified as primarily involving feelings, this last brings into consideration
the different ontological territory of the body. Among the 16 forms, three branch away from
mental wellbeing, and intersect with other wellbeing dimensions. Chaironic happiness links
to spiritual wellbeing, and below relational happiness is associated with social wellbeing.
Completing the trifecta, vital happiness pertains to physical wellbeing. Just as we use
“happiness” for positive mental health, one might deploy “vitality” to cover the realm of
positive physical health. However, from a critical perspective, the whole distinction between
physical and mental is somewhat artificial and constructed, as the mind permeates the body
and vice versa (Bostic et al., 2000). In objective terms, the physical body and brain constitute
one interconnected system. Likewise, subjectively, qualia tend to involve both embodied
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
12
physical sensations and mental manifestations. In that respect, in objective terms, vitality
might mean high physical energy or skill, while subjectively it could include feelings of zest
and vigour (Ryan & Fredrick, 1997). As such, although vitality fundamentally pertains to
physical wellbeing, conceptually and experientially it “overlaps” with mental wellbeing
(Lomas, Ritchie-Dunham et al., 2022). Indeed, aspects may pertain more to mind than body,
with Ryan and Frederick's (1997) Subjective Vitality Scale described as indexing “a positive
feeling of energy and aliveness.” Elucidating this, they share our view of vitality as straddling
physical and mental dimensions, describing it as “a reflection of both organismic and
psychological wellness” (p.532). Other scales likewise overlap the dimensions, such as the
Vitality Plus Scale (Myers et al., 1999), which collectively have generated a broad literature
(Lavrusheva, 2020). We therefore refer to the more mental manifestations of vitality as “vital
happiness”: a mental experience of quality with respect to one’s physical being. Given the
affinities between vital happiness and physical wellbeing, we hypothesise that vital happiness
may be especially impaired – even more than other forms of happiness – by physical issues
and behaviours, from overwork to impaired sleep quality (Sampaio et al., 2014).
Thinking Types
6. Evaluative
These next five forms pertain primarily (though not only) to thinking. This first is the most
widely studied form of happiness, involving the great wealth of research into the cognitive
component of SWB. Over the years many influential concepts and measures have been
developed, from Cantril's (1965) “ladder” to the Satisfaction with Life Scale (Diener et al.,
1985). These usually reflect a global assessment (i.e., all elements of life together) of one’s
life in general (i.e., over a reasonable span of time). Although this tends to be conflated with
hedonia, as noted above, we regard it as a distinct form, as evaluative happiness is primarily
cognitive, being a mental experience of quality with respect to evaluating one’s life, either as
a whole, or in specific domains. Given the vast literature on this form, we need not dwell
further on its details. One salient point to address though is the suggestion that since such
evaluations concern life as a whole, this form might offer an ultimate summary assessment of
happiness, or even all wellbeing. However, someone may be dissatisfied with life overall
(there are aspects with which they are unhappy), yet satisfied in what matters most to them
(e.g., chaironic happiness). It is not clear such people would trade the latter for the former.
Indeed, research on Nozick’s “experience machine” thought experiment suggest many people
would not want a simulated existence of perfect satisfaction, and instead prefer a real life in
all its vicissitudes (Hewitt, 2010), a point also borne out by the notion of a “psychologically
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
13
rich life.” That said, such speculations are relatively untested. As such, we might speculate
that, (a) if asked to rank forms of happiness in terms of importance to them, most people
would not place evaluative happiness at the very top; moreover, (b) of these people, if asked
whether, to preserve their experience of their most valued form, they would significantly
sacrifice evaluative happiness – for example dropping several rungs on Cantril’s ladder – a
significant minority would assent.
7. Meaningful
This next form broaches territory usually associated with eudaimonia, as captured by Ryff’s
(1989) model of “psychological wellbeing” (with its six dimensions of self-acceptance,
positive relationships, autonomy, environmental mastery, purpose in life, and personal
growth). However, as noted above, eudaimonia has now become a catch-all for anything
happiness-related outside SWB, so an expanded taxonomy allows some qualities often
bundled up within it to be acknowledged as distinct forms of happiness in their own right. In
so doing, we reserve eudaimonia for self-development – the cultivation of character and
virtue, as elucidated below – as this more closely aligns with classical theorizing on the
concept. Doing so moreover allows other dimensions in Ryff’s model to be valued on their
own terms. After all, some do not necessarily involve any such self-development, removing
them from the scope of eudaimonia as classically understood. This concern applies to the
notions of meaning and purpose. Extensive research has shown these to be integral to mental
wellbeing, such as work using Steger et al.'s (2006) Meaning in Life Questionnaire. However,
while cultivation of meaning/purpose may well involve self-development, crucially, people
can experience these without any such development. For example, Seligman (2011) suggests
meaning/purpose are above all found in “belonging to and serving something that you believe
is bigger than then self” (p.17). Crucially, many people find meaning in forms of communal
participation, like supporting a sports team, that require no self-cultivation per se. So, distinct
from eudaimonia, there is merit in identifying a separate form of meaningful happiness, as a
mental experience of quality with respect to one’s meaning and purpose in life. That said, we
might nevertheless predict that a given state of meaningful happiness would be stronger if it
is combined with feelings of eudaimonic happiness (i.e., a sense of one’s own development).
8. Intellective
This next form also relates to eudaimonia, but tends to be overlooked by modern researchers.
Nevertheless, it was certainly present in classical theorising. In his Nicomachean Ethics –
pivotal in elucidating the idea of eudaimonia – Aristotle suggests the highest happiness
comes from the highest exercise of virtue, namely, reflective study, contemplation, and
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
14
understanding of what is best and most noble in life. For people spiritually inclined, such
contemplation may take on a religious character (thus overlapping with chaironic happiness).
In his interpretations of Aristotle, St. Aquinas for instance depicts such contemplation as a
perfect happiness, involving a full, final intellective vision of God. Such considerations
suggest one may attain elevated and rarefied states of being in thoughtful contemplation or
understanding of some great good. We thus call this “intellective happiness”: a mental
experience of quality relating to one’s intellectual or contemplative life. Although some
scholars might simply enfold this within an expanded eudaimonia, we suggest it is distinct
enough from self-development per se to merit its own form. That said, not only is the
construct of “intellective happiness” new, there does not appear to be any empirical work
pertaining to it (unlike most others, where even if the label is novel there is still a substantial
research base). So, work will especially be needed on this. One line of enquiry is whether
there are individual differences in people’s likelihood of valuing, seeking, and experiencing
specific happiness forms. In that respect, we might envisage that intellective happiness will
be higher in people with greater cognitive capacities (e.g., as indexed by IQ), and/or with a
personality profile characterised by conscientiousness, introversion, and openness.
9. Aesthetic
While intellective happiness is an experience of quality relating to the contemplation and
cognitive understanding of an object or idea, this is not the only kind of valued relationship
one can have with such phenomena. Many people experience happiness through perception
of natural beauty or some object; likewise, for millennia humans have produced art forms that
appeal, at least partly, to sensual perception and appreciation. While such experiences may
involve the intellect, they do not necessarily do so principally, and many may elude cognitive
understanding altogether. In this realm for instance one might include states of awe, which
Keltner and Haidt (2003) describe as “a moral, spiritual, and aesthetic emotion … on the
upper reaches of pleasure and the boundary of fear” (p.297). Thus, aesthetic experiences
could be deemed a distinct class of happiness experience: not merely a factor that influences
it, but a form of happiness in its own right (Lomas, 2016), being a mental experience of
quality concerning one’s sensual perceptions. While there is currently not much work on this
notion, there is certainly a substantial literature on the psychological dimensions of aesthetics
– such as the Desire for Aesthetic Experience Scale (Lundy et al., 2010) – which could be
interpreted through the lens of our definition. Nevertheless, more research will be needed to
explore this form. One resource for exploring its dynamics is Keltner and Haidt’s work on
awe, which draws upon Romantic notions of the “sublime.” A particularly interesting aspect
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
15
of that construct is it may not only involve positively valenced emotions, but sometimes
negatively valenced ones too, as explored by second wave positive psychology (Wong, 2011;
Lomas & Ivtzan, 2016). Indeed, one might speculate that the most powerful experiences of
aesthetic happiness will involve some negative emotional valence – combined with positive
valence in a potent mixed emotion (Lomas, 2017) – thereby elevating the experience in
complexity and profundity beyond those that are just positively valenced.
10. Absorbed
The fifth form relating to thinking uses this term in its broadest sense, referring to cognition
in general. This form concerns the way attention modalities are deployed, involving valued
states like absorption, engagement, and flow. A key notion in this space is Csikszentmihalyi's
(1990) concept of flow, involving activities experienced as intrinsically rewarding, and well
matched to one’s skills, with an accompanying sense of total involvement, absorption, or
concentration, such that one is completely task-focused (e.g., no extraneous thoughts). Such
activities are not enjoyable per se – otherwise they might be classed under hedonism – even if
people describe enjoying them afterwards. This terrain also encompasses the multitude of
meditative practices and states, all of which involve training and developing attention skills,
such that one can deploy these to benefit one’s wellbeing (Kabat-Zinn, 2003). We view such
states as “absorbed happiness” – a mental experience of quality relating to one’s attentional
engagement – though adjectives like engaged or attentive also suit it. Indeed, as noted above
vis-à-vis band 3, Seligman (2002) suggests engagement is one of three distinct pathways to
overall mental wellbeing – alongside pleasure and meaning – with each described as “neither
sufficient nor redundant; therefore necessitating cultivation of each to achieve the full life”
(Schueller & Seligman, 2010, p.253). In terms of further research, an interesting question is
what differentiates mindfulness and flow. Although sometimes treated as similar or even
identical, scholars are increasingly sensitive to potential differences (Cathcart et al., 2014),
with a possible point of divergence being “self-presence” – how self-conscious versus selfless
a state is (Millière, 2020). While selflessness is an ultimate goal of many forms of meditation,
we predict that overall it is more easily and frequently attained during flow than mindfulness.
Doing Types
11. Eudaimonic
The final six forms are primarily about “doing,” of which the most well-known and studied is
eudaimonia. However, although this term often serves as a catch-all for all happiness-related
experiences outside SWB, we use it more narrowly to refer to self-development – aligning
with classical depictions of the concept – being a mental experience of quality in relation to
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
16
one’s sense of character development. Such development may be somewhat intangible and
difficult to experience in the moment. It is more an appraisal that requires a person to observe
and assess their life from some distance, over time. Nevertheless, one can, at a given moment,
sense whether one is progressing towards one’s ideal version of oneself. In Ryff’s (1989)
model of psychological wellbeing, for example, the personal development subcomponent is
exemplified by someone who “has a feeling of continued development; sees self as growing
and expanding [and] sees improvement in self and behavior over time.” In terms of research
questions, our suggestion pertains to us situating eudaimonia as primarily a form of doing.
Our reading of eudaimonia leads us to hypothesise that, while it can be experienced when one
is relatively quiescent (e.g., sitting in reflection), it is more likely encountered in the midst of
physical behaviour (e.g., action in service of one’s values). Moreover, this form of happiness
may also involve negatively valenced emotions; indeed, one sign that a person is making
progress is they are outside their comfort zone, mentally, physically, socially, or spiritually.
Doing so may feel challenging, but ultimately can be integral to a sense of development. So,
we further suggest the more difficult/challenging the behaviour, the greater the eudaimonia.
12. Masterful
We now consider two further forms which are usually included in eudaimonia, but which also
fall outside its boundaries as classically conceived, and are better valued on their own terms.
This first refers to skilfully navigating life – captured in Ryff’s (1989) model as “mastery” –
defined as a mental experience of quality concerning the development and use of one’s skills.
While eudaimonia is primarily about character, mastery concerns skills, and although skills
and character sometimes overlap, they are not identical (one can be skilled at abilities that
matter little to one’s personal values but are nevertheless conducive to wellbeing). Moreover,
skills are not necessarily about blossoming into one’s “best self” – the essence of eudaimonia
– but the fit between oneself and one’s environment, and tend to be context-dependent and
situationally relevant. This form of happiness also encompasses the rewards one may receive
from successful skill use, both social (e.g., status) and non-social (e.g., material benefits, like
safely negotiating one’s environs). Although this form lacks a research base per se, it pertains
to phenomena with a vast literature – and associated construct and measurement development
– especially coping and resilience. Although the latter are usually explored in the context of
mental illness rather than health, there are also moves to consider these in the context of
positive wellbeing. For instance, Akin and Akin (2015) found that “coping competence”
mediates the relationship between mindfulness and SWB. Moreover, we submit that such
mastery is not only associated with happiness, but itself constitutes an experience of quality,
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
17
hence being a form of happiness in its own right. The experience of acting masterfully can
itself be rewarding, shown by an extensive literature connecting work engagement to mental
wellbeing (Li et al., 2022). While this form overlaps with absorbed happiness, it is temporally
broader, extending beyond specific states of absorption per se; indeed, of all happiness forms,
we suggest masterful may be among the most long-lasting (in an extended, continuous sense).
13. Accomplished
Closely related to mastery – yet worth differentiating – is accomplishment/achievement.
Mastery often, but not always, leads to achievement, while achievement will sometimes but
not always require mastery. Independent of mastery, accomplishment is a pillar of Seligman’s
(2011) PERMA model of flourishing (with positive emotions, engagement, relationships, and
meaning, which align respectively with hedonic, absorbed, relational, and meaningful
happiness). While mastery concerns skill use in the present, accomplished happiness is more
about the past and the outcome, constituting a mental experience in relation to what one has
achieved. Once again, although as a specific construct this is a novel proposition, a wealth of
research can be interpreted through its lens, like extensive literatures on the interrelated topics
of motivation and goals, both of which intrinsically involve accomplishment (Covington,
2000). Indeed, a common way to understand the very concept of valence is through notions
of approach versus withdrawal, with feelings of pleasure and reward arising in relation to the
extent one is progressing towards a goal. So, although construing accomplishment as a form
of happiness per se is novel, there is a substantial literature for viewing such experiences as
mental states of quality. In further exploring this form, an interesting angle is the question of
moral worth (Nash et al., 2013). In that regard, we predict accomplished happiness will be
heightened to the degree one appraises the successes it reflects as having such worth.
14. Harmonic
A key finding of the Global Wellbeing Initiative is the importance of balance and harmony in
life. As with contented happiness, these notions are closely associated with Eastern cultures,
and likewise are linked to low arousal positive emotions. However, as with the latter, the
World Poll data shows balance and harmony are experienced and valued globally (Lomas,
Lai, et al., 2022), as did Delle Fave et al.'s (2016) analyses of lay perceptions of happiness.
The importance of these ideas has also been captured by Kjell et al.'s (2016) Harmony in Life
Scale, focusing on “psychological balance and flexibility in life”. In this and follow up work
by Kjell and Diener (2021), the authors suggest such harmony constitutes a distinct aspect of
the cognitive component of SWB. Rather than this component being unidimensional (just life
satisfaction), they argue it has two factors (i.e., also involving harmony in life). Such findings
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
18
augment the process of granular disaggregation we are deploying with SWB. We separated
its cognitive aspect into its own form of evaluative happiness, and differentiated the affective
aspect into two forms – high arousal (hedonic) and low arousal (contented). Complementing
this process, Kjell’s work suggests we should likewise differentiate the cognitive component
into evaluative and harmonic happiness, the latter being a mental experience of quality with
respect to how well the different elements of one’s life are ordered and operating together.
This is still a new area of enquiry though, so more work is needed. In terms of hypotheses,
we suggest harmonic and evaluative happiness ought not to be too highly correlated (e.g., at
least below 0.7), which would justify Kjell and colleagues’ suggestion of treating them as
separate components of SWB’s cognitive dimension.
15. Nirvanic
This taxonomy has mainly drawn on contemporary academic concepts relating to happiness.
However, many religious/spiritual traditions have also developed detailed ideas in this area,
and moreover continue to meaningfully contribute to our understanding, including insights
presently not well understood by modern science. Buddhism in particular has a wealth of
psychologically-oriented theories about happiness of all kinds. Uppermost is its ultimate goal,
nirvāṇa, a complex concept which alludes to the complete and lasting cessation of duḥkha
(roughly, suffering), and attainment of mokṣa (total freedom), resulting from following the
Buddhist path (Collins, 2010). This path involves various actions (e.g., ethical behaviour),
hence positioning this form as relating to “doing.” Thus, nirvanic happiness might be
conceived as a mental experience of quality with respect to one’s capacity to be relatively
permanently free of suffering. While rarefied and even esoteric territory, such teachings
remind us we have yet much to explore and understand in this arena. To that point, although
this form lacks a substantial modern empirical research base, a voluminous literature has
developed within traditions over the centuries around such states, elucidating their properties
in depth. We accord with modern scholars of such accounts in taking them seriously as
illuminating significant potentials of the human condition (Fontana, 2007). Indeed, some
empirical inroads are being made: there is now considerable research on the neurophysiology
of meditation, for instance, including advanced transcendent states (Wahbeh et al., 2018).
Still, much more work is needed. To that point, while this form is ostensibly linked to
Buddhism, similar themes appear in other traditions, and many cultures have concepts that
represent a similar apotheosis. Thus, we predict mental states with significant similarities to
nirvāṇa will be found across cultures and religious traditions.
16. Relational
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
19
This final form is – as per chaironic and vital happiness – of a different ontological order to
the rest: happiness as a relational phenomenon. The others can all be conceived as individual-
level phenomena. Even if they involve other people – e.g., relationships are one component
of Ryff's (1989) notion of psychological wellbeing – all are conceptualised as existing within
the person as an inner psychological state, potentially reflecting the individualism of the
Western cultures that shaped psychology (Christopher & Hickinbottom, 2008). By contrast,
some other cultures – especially those seen as “collectivistic” – prioritise perspectives on
happiness that are fundamentally relational (Izquierdo, 2005). However, even in relatively
individualistic Western cultures, people still need close relationships and recognise their
importance, as per the voluminous literature on social capital (Putnam, 1995). Indeed,
arguably the apex of relational happiness is love, which most people would surely regard as
universal. Such relational happiness – which Hitokoto and Uchida (2015) call interdependent
happiness – is intersubjective, existing at the level of multiple people as an emergent gestalt
phenomenon. Nevertheless, it is still experienced by individuals, so can be defined as a
mental state of quality arising from an interpersonal dynamic. This of course overlaps with
social wellbeing, as vital and chaironic happiness did with physical and spiritual wellbeing.
However, as in those cases, it is also worth having this as a mental experiential concept. The
key point here is that relationships are not merely a factor that influences happiness, but in
themselves may constitute a form of happiness, one which only exists in an interpersonal
way. More work is needed to explore this form, though some progress has already been made
through Hitokoto and Uchida's (2015) Interdependent Happiness Scale, which has started to
be explored in contexts like Italy and Poland (Mosca, et al., 2021) and Turkey (Demirci,
2022). In that respect, we predict relational happiness will be more highly sought, valued, and
experienced than people often expect, especially in contexts usually viewed as individualistic.
Conclusion
This paper has proposed an expanded taxonomy of happiness, featuring 16 distinct forms.
However, this is a novel framework, and will require corroboration in future research. To that
end, for each form, we offered a hypothesis that may help establish its validity. Building on
these predictions, we conclude by adding some general hypotheses and considerations that
apply across all forms, and provide a roadmap for exploring the contours of happiness in
greater detail. First, a general principle is that for the taxonomy to be upheld, it should be
possible to differentiate the forms empirically. Thus, an overall prediction is that self-report
scales for the forms ought to not correlate too highly, while there will nevertheless be some
correlation. One might envisage that, just as any given set of intelligence tests tends to result
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
20
in a common “g” factor (general intelligence), so might we find a common “h” factor, where
overall a person’s scores on different forms of happiness tend to coalesce around similar
levels – influenced for instance by genetically-influenced temperament (Lomas, Bartels, et
al., 2022). Indeed, several overarching constructs have been proposed that might serve as a
potential unifying factor, including positive orientation (Caprara et al., 2010), and the joyful
life (Robbins, 2021). A fruitful line of enquiry will be to explore the extent to which these
concepts map onto and potentially – if serving as an overarching h factor – encompass all 16
forms. If assigning figures, we might expect a range of correlations between the forms of .3
to .7 (based on Ryff’s (1989) work on psychological wellbeing, with correlations between its
dimensions ranging from .32 to .72). Currently not all forms have scales – notably intellective
and nirvanic happiness – and their development will be a key aspect of future research. As for
the remaining 14, these do have scales that would serve as a basis for empirical enquiry.
Where possible, psychometric analyses could ideally be augmented by other methods,
especially qualitative and neurophysiological approaches. First, gaining rich qualitative data
about the forms would help elucidate their nature (in addition to any psychometric analysis).
Participants could perhaps be recruited based on experiencing a given type, and asked about
it through in-depth interviews, with the results analysed by Interpretative Phenomenological
Analysis, which allows in-depth exploration of subjectivity. Complementing such analyses
are neurophysiological assessments of these states. For example, there are already hundreds
of such studies of meditative states, giving valuable clues about their neurophysiological
signatures (Lomas, Ivtzan, et al., 2015). Even more powerfully, the neurophenomenology
paradigm combines both approaches, triangulating phenomenological analysis of qualia with
neurophysiological analyses of brain states, providing integrative accounts of how realms
might intersect (Cahn & Polich, 2006). This kind of program could be employed to explore
all forms of happiness. This would require inducing these while a person is connected to a
relevant neurophysiological recording device. One possibility is using virtual/augmented
reality technology to immerse people in digital environments geared towards generating
specific forms of happiness. For instance, Chirico et al. (2021) used virtual reality to induce
experiences of the sublime (a concept discussed above in relation to aesthetic happiness).
Although they did not conduct neurophysiological assessment during this experience, one
could easily add it to the paradigm. In such a way, we would obtain a neurophysiological
signature of the sublime. One could then augment this with qualitative interviews to truly
obtain a detailed picture of this state. One could aim to similarly elicit and study all happiness
forms in this manner, thereby developing detailed understanding of not only their subjective
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
21
dynamics, but how these dynamics relate to the corresponding neurophysiology, which will
truly allow us to chart the fine-grained forms of happiness in all their rich complexity.
Finally, future work would ideally trace the relationships between this taxonomy and
other theories and frameworks that also pertain to the broad terrain we are labelling happiness
– or more generically, mental wellbeing – but which conceptually carve it up in other ways.
One important example is Maslow’s work on self-actualization, as for example interpreted by
Kaufman (2023), whose new scale of self-actualization features ten dimensions, in which one
can arguably see refracted the various happiness forms, including: continued freshness of
appreciation (e.g., aesthetic, absorbed, chaironic, intellective); acceptance (mature, contented,
harmonic, evaluative); authenticity (eudaimonic, mature); equanimity (contented, mature);
purpose (meaningful, masterful, accomplished); efficient perception of reality (aesthetic,
intellective); humanitarianism (relational, harmonic); peak experiences (hedonic, chaironic,
nirvanic); good moral intuition (eudaimonic, relational); and creative spirit (intellective,
aesthetic). As one can see, these dimensions potentially capture all forms here, except vital,
interestingly, which perhaps reflects the way the body has largely been overlooked by
psychology. Another key framework in the arena of mental wellbeing is self-determination
theory (Ryan & Deci, 2000). Again, one can picture how the happiness forms might pertain
to the core needs of relatedness (especially relational happiness), achievement (especially
masterful, accomplished, and evaluative happiness), and autonomy (with the most relevant
perhaps being eudaimonic happiness, albeit less directly). However, that the latter lacks an
obvious candidate speaks to the fact that our taxonomy may not be exhaustive, and may
warrant including additional forms. Vis-à-vis autonomy, for instance, one might imagine an
further form centred on experiences like individuation, liberation, freedom, etc., perhaps as a
form of “liberated happiness.”
In addition to these multidimensional frameworks are specific constructs which also
pertain to mental wellbeing. In the sections above we identified ones that pertain to different
forms. However, some such are not easily pigeonholed, and are more overarching, spanning
numerous forms. We already noted that positive orientation and the joyful life potentially
cover all forms. Besides these are various others which, if not as all-encompassing, at least
pertain to several forms. Resilience for example not only relates to coping and adaptation, but
has been explored from a virtue perspective as “a positive by-product of having endured
adversities while transforming them into insightful opportunities for renewal” (Kim et al.,
2018, p.195). Such qualities would appear integral to numerous forms, not only masterful (as
discussed above), but also mature, accomplished, eudaimonic, and nirvanic. Another fecund
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
22
concept is love of life (Abdel-Khalek, 2007), which taps into many forms, especially hedonic,
chaironic, aesthetic, absorbed, and nirvanic. Finally, besides relating the taxonomy to other
ideas concerning mental wellbeing specifically, it will also be valuable to situate it relative to
concepts across psychology more broadly. A prime example is the Big Five model of
personality; indeed, not only have factors like extraversion been linked to happiness (Lucas &
Fujita, 2000), but “stable extraversion” has been proposed as constituting happiness (Frances,
1999). However, such research tends to focus on hedonic and evaluative happiness, and it is
unclear how personality dimensions would map onto other forms. That said, one might
hypothesise that openness to experience may pertain especially to intellective, absorbed, and
aesthetic happiness, agreeableness to relational, contented, and harmonic happiness, and
conscientiousness to eudaimonic, accomplished, and masterful happiness. However, this will
need exploring in future. At the very least, as this conclusion has indicated, there is fertile
ground to explore not only in developing an enriched conception of happiness, but situating
its constructs within the broader network of ideas in psychology, and beyond that within the
still-wider web of concepts across myriad fields interesting in wellbeing. It is hoped this
paper will provide a foundation and impetus for this kind of enquiry, allowing us to develop a
better understanding of these vital topics.
References
Abdel-Khalek, A. M. (2007). Love of life as a new construct in the well-being domain. Social
Behavior and Personality, 35(1), 125-134. doi:10.2224/sbp.2007.35.1.125
Akin, Ü., & Akin, A. (2015). Mindfulness and subjective happiness: The mediating role of
coping competence. Ceskoslovenska Psychologie, 59(4).
Aristotle. (1986). Nicomachean Ethics (translated by M. Ostwald). Macmillan.
Barrington-Leigh, C. P. (2022). Trends in conceptions of progress and well-being. In J.
Helliwell, R. Layard, J. D. Sachs, J.-E. De Neve, L. Aknin, S. Wang, & S. Paculor
(Eds.), World Happiness Report 2022 (pp. 55–74). Sustainable Development Solutions.
Bostic, T. J., Rubio, D. M., & Hood, M. (2000). A validation of the subjective vitality scale
using structural equation modeling. Social Indicators Research, 52(3), 313–324.
Breuer, J., & Freud, S. (1955). Studies on hysteria. In J. Strachey (Ed.), The standard edition
of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud (Vol. 2). Hogarth Press.
Cahn, B. R., & Polich, J. (2006). Meditation states and traits: EEG, ERP, and neuroimaging
studies. Psychological Bulletin, 132(2), 180–211. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.132.2.180
Cantril, H. (1965). The Pattern of Human Concerns. Rutgers University Press.
Caprara, G. V., Steca, P., Alessandri, G., Abela, J. R., & McWhinnie, C. M. (2010). Positive
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
23
orientation: Explorations on what is common to life satisfaction, self-esteem, and
optimism. Epidemiology and Psychiatric Sciences, 19(1), 63-71.
doi:0.1017/s1121189x00001615
Carreno, D. F., Eisenbeck, N., Pérez-Escobar, J. A., & García-Montes, J. M. (2021). Inner
harmony as an essential facet of well-being: a multinational study during the COVID-19
pandemic. Frontiers in Psychology, 12, 911. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2021.648280
Cathcart, S., McGregor, M., & Groundwater, E. (2014). Mindfulness and flow in elite
athletes. Journal of Clinical Sport Psychology, 8(2), 119–141.
Chalmers, D. J. (2013). How can we construct a science of consciousness? Annals of the New
York Academy of Sciences, 1303(1), 25–35. doi:10.1111/nyas.12166
Chirico, A., Clewis, R. R., Yaden, D. B., & Gaggioli, A. (2021). Nature versus art as elicitors
of the sublime: A virtual reality study. PloS One, 16(3), e0233628.
doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0233628
Christopher, J. C., & Hickinbottom, S. (2008). Positive psychology, ethnocentrism, and the
disguised ideology of individualism. Theory & Psychology, 18(5), 563–589.
doi:10.1177/0959354308093396
Covington, M. V. (2000). Goal theory, motivation, and school achievement: An integrative
review. Annual Review of Psychology, 51(1), 171–200.
doi:10.1146/annurev.psych.51.1.171
Csikszentmihalyi, M. (1990). Flow: The psychology of happiness. Random House.
Delle Fave, A., Brdar, I., Wissing, M. P., Araujo, U., Castro Solano, A., Freire, T., … Soosai-
Nathan, L. (2016). Lay definitions of happiness across nations: The primacy of inner
harmony and relational connectedness. Frontiers in Psychology, 7.
doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2016.00030
Demirci, İ. (2022). Family harmony and flourishing in Turkey: The roles of interdependent
happiness and harmony in life. Journal of Happiness Studies, 23(3), 985–1005.
doi:10.1007/s10902-021-00437-7
Diener, E., Emmons, R. A., Larsem, R. J., & Griffin, S. (1985). The Satisfaction With Life
Scale. Journal of Personality Assessment, 49(1), 71–75.
doi:10.1207/s15327752jpa4901_13
Diener, E., Suh, E. M., Lucas, R. E., & Smith, H. L. (1999). Subjective well-being: Three
decades of progress. Psychological bulletin, 125(2), 276–302. doi:10.1037/0033-
2909.125.2.276
Dor-Ziderman, Y., Berkovich-Ohana, A., Glicksohn, J., & Goldstein, A. (2013).
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
24
Mindfulness-induced selflessness: a MEG neurophenomenological study. Frontiers in
Human Neuroscience, 7, https://www.frontiersin.org/article/10.3389/fnhum.2013.00582
Ellison, C. G., & Levin, J. S. (1998). The religion-health connection: Evidence, theory, and
future directions. Health Education & Behavior, 25(6), 700–720.
Fisher, J. (2010). Development and application of a spiritual well-being questionnaire called
SHALOM. Religions, 1(1), 105–121. doi:10.3390/rel1010105.
Fontana, D. (2007). Mystical experience. In M. Velmans & S. Schneider (Eds.), The
Blackwell Companion to Consciousness (pp. 163–172). Blackwell Publishing.
Frances, L. J. (1999). Happiness is thing called stable extraversion: A further examination of
the relationship between the Oxford Happiness Inventory and Eysenck’s dimensional
model of personality and gender. Personality and Individual Differences, 26, 5–11. doi:
10.1016/s0191-8869(98)00185-8
Frankl, V. E. (1963). Man’s search for meaning. First Washington Square Press.
Helliwell, J. F., Layard, R., Sachs, J. D., De Neve, J.-E., Aknin, L., Wang, S., & Paculor, S.
(2022). The 10th World Happiness Report. Sustainable Development Solutions.
Hewitt, S. (2010). What do our intuitions about the experience machine really tell us about
hedonism? Philosophical Studies, 151(3), 331–349.
Hill, P. C., Pargament, K. I., Hood, R. W., McCullough, J. . M. E., Swyers, J. P., Larson, D.
B., & Zinnbauer, B. J. (2000). Conceptualizing religion and spirituality: Points of
commonality, points of departure. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 30(1),
51–77. doi:10.1111/1468-5914.00119
Hitokoto, H., & Uchida, Y. (2015). Interdependent happiness: Theoretical importance and
measurement validity. Journal of Happiness Studies, 16(1), 211–239. doi:
10.1007/s10902-014-9505-8
Izquierdo, C. (2005). When “health” is not enough: Societal, individual and biomedical
assessments of well-being among the Matsigenka of the Peruvian Amazon. Social
Science and Medicine, 61, 767–783. doi:10.1016/j.socscimed.2004.08.045
Kabat-Zinn, J. (2003). Mindfulness-based interventions in context: Past, present, and future.
Clinical Psychology: Science and Practice, 10(2), 144–156. doi:10.1093/clipsy.bpg016
Kaufman, S. B. (2023). Self-actualizing people in the 21st century: Integration with
contemporary theory and research on personality and well-being. Journal of Humanistic
Psychology, 63(1), 51–83. doi:10.1177/0022167818809187
Keyes, C. L. M. (2007). Promoting and protecting mental health as flourishing: A
complementary strategy for improving national mental health doi. American
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
25
Psychologist, 62, 95–108. doi:10.1037/0003-066x.62.2.95
Kim, J. H., Hawley, C. E., Gonzalez, R., Vo, A. K., Barbir, L. A., McMahon, B. T., Lee, D.-
H., Lee, J. H., & Lee, Y. W. (2018). Resilience from a virtue perspective. Rehabilitation
Counseling Bulletin, 61(4), 195–204. doi:10.1177/0034355217714995
Kjell, O.N.E., Daukantaitė, D., Hefferon, K., & Sikström, S. (2016). The Harmony in Life
Scale complements the Satisfaction with Life Scale: Expanding the conceptualization of
the cognitive component of subjective well-being. Social Indicators Research, 126(2),
893–919. doi:10.1007/s11205-015-0903-z
Kjell, Oscar N E, & Diener, E. (2021). Abbreviated three-item versions of the Satisfaction
with Life Scale and the Harmony in Life Scale yield as strong psychometric properties
as the original scales. Journal of Personality Assessment, 103(2), 183–194.
doi:10.1080/00223891.2020.1737093
Larson, J. S. (1996). The World Health Organization’s definition of health: Social versus
spiritual health. Social Indicators Research, 38(2), 181–192. doi:10.1007/BF00300458
Lavrusheva, O. (2020). The concept of vitality. Review of the vitality-related research
domain. New Ideas in Psychology, 56 100752. doi:10.1016/j.newideapsych.2019.100752
Li, W. H., Zhou, Y., Su, J. X., Ma, H. Y., Zhang, J., & Tang, H. Y. (2022). Engage your
work, and enjoy your evening: How daily work engagement promotes non-work mastery
and control experiences. Current Psychology. doi:10.1007/s12144-022-03100-3
Lindahl, J., Kaplan, C., Winget, E., & Britton, W. (2014). A phenomenology of meditation-
induced light experiences: traditional buddhist and neurobiological perspectives .
Frontiers in Psychology, 4; www.frontiersin.org/article/10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00973
Lomas, T. (2016). Positive art: Artistic expression and appreciation as an exemplary vehicle
for flourishing. Review of General Psychology, 20, 171–182. doi:10.1037/gpr0000073
Lomas, T. (2017). The value of ambivalent emotions: A cross-cultural lexical analysis.
Qualitative Research in Psychology. doi:10.1080/14780887.2017.1400143
Lomas, T. (2018). Experiential cartography and the significance of “untranslatable” words.
Theory and Psychology, 28(4), 476–495. doi:10.1177/0959354318772914
Lomas, T. (2022a). Making waves in the great ocean: A historical perspective on the
emergence and evolution of wellbeing scholarship. The Journal of Positive Psychology,
17(2), 257-270. doi:10.1080/17439760.2021.2016900
Lomas, T. (2022b). Stranger than we can imagine: the possibility and potential significance
of non-human forms of consciousness and wellbeing. The Journal of Positive
Psychology. doi:10.1080/17439760.2022.2131608
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
26
Lomas, T., Bartels, M., Weijer.M, V. De, Pluess, M., Hanson, J., & VanderWeele1, T. J.
(2022). The architecture of happiness. Emotion Review, 14(4), 288–309.
doi:10.1177/17540739221114109
Lomas, T., Case, B., Cratty, F. J., & VanderWeele, T. (2021). A global history of happiness.
International Journal of Wellbeing, 11(4), 68–87. doi:10.5502/ijw.v11i4.1457
Lomas, T., & Ivtzan, I. (2016). Second wave positive psychology: Exploring the positive–
negative dialectics of wellbeing. Journal of Happiness Studies, 17(4), 1753-1768.
doi:10.1007/s10902-015-9668-y
Lomas, T., Ivtzan, I., & Fu, C. H. Y. (2015). A systematic review of the neurophysiology of
mindfulness on EEG oscillations. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews, 57, 401–410.
doi:10.1016/j.neubiorev.2015.09.018
Lomas, T., Lai, A., Diego-Rosell, P., Uchida, Y., & VanderWeele, T. J. (2022). Insights from
the first global survey of balance and harmony. In J. Helliwell, R. Layard, J. D. Sachs,
J.-E. De Neve, L. Aknin, S. Wang, & S. Paculor (Eds.), World Happiness Report 2022
(pp. 127–154). Sustainable Development Solutions.
Lomas, T., Ritchie-Dunham, J., Lee, M. T., & VanderWeele, T. J. (2022). The varieties of
vitality: A cross-cultural lexical analysis. International Journal of Wellbeing, 12(4). doi:
10.5502/ijw.v12i4.2627
Lomas, T., & VanderWeele, T. J. (2022). The garden and the orchestra: Generative
metaphors for conceptualizing the complexities of well-being. International Journal of
Environmental Research and Public Health, 19(21), 14544.
doi:10.3390/ijerph192114544
Lomas, T., Waters, L., Williams, P., Oades, L. G., & Kern, M. L. (2021). Third wave positive
psychology: broadening towards complexity. The Journal of Positive Psychology, 16(5),
660-674. doi:10.1080/17439760.2020.1805501
Lucas, R. E., and Fujita, F. (2000). Factors influencing the relation between extraversion and
pleasant affect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79, 1039–1056. doi:
10.1037/0022-3514.79.6.1039
Lundy, D. E., Schenkel, M. B., Akrie, T. N., & Walker, A. M. (2010). How important is
beauty to you? The development of the Desire for Aesthetics Scale. Empirical Studies of
the Arts, 28(1), 73–92. doi:10.2190/EM.28.1.e
Maslow, A. H. (1962). Toward a Psychology of Being. John Wiley.
McAdams, D. P., Reynolds, J., Lewis, M., Patten, A. H., and Bowman, P. J. (2001). When
bad things turn good and good things turn bad: Sequences of redemption and
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
27
contamination in life narrative and their relation to psychosocial adaptation in midlife
adults and in students. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 27, 474–485. doi:
10.1177/0146167201274008
McManus, M. D., Siegel, J. T., & Nakamura, J. (2019). The predictive power of low-arousal
positive affect. Motivation and Emotion, 43, 130–144. doi:10.1007/s11031-018-9719-x
Millière, R. (2020). The varieties of selflessness. Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 1(I), 1–
41. doi:0.33735/phimisci.2020.I.48
Mosca, O., Maricchiolo, F., Krys, K., & Lauriola, M. (2021). Two countries, one happiness?
The interdependent happiness scale in Italy and Poland. TPM: Testing, Psychometrics,
Methodology in Applied Psychology, 28(2021). doi:10.4473/TPM28.3.5
Murstein, B. I. (1988). A taxonomy of love. In R. Sternberg & M. Barnes (Eds.), The
Psychology of Love (pp. 13–37). Yale University Press.
Myers, A. M., Malott, O. W., Gray, E., Tudor-Locke, C., Ecclestone, N. A., Cousins, S. O., &
Petrella, R. (1999). Measuring accumulated health-related benefits of exercise
participation for older adults: The Vitality Plus Scale. Journals of Gerontology Series A:
Biomedical Sciences and Medical Sciences, 54(9), M456–M466.
doi:0.1093/gerona/54.9.M456
Nash, W. P., Marino Carper, T. L., Mills, M. A., Au, T., Goldsmith, A., & Litz, B. T. (2013).
Psychometric evaluation of the Moral Injury Events Scale. Military Medicine, 178(6),
646–652. doi:10.7205/MILMED-D-13-00017
Nussbaum, M., & Sen, A. (1993). The Quality of Life. Clarendon Press.
Oishi, S., & Westgate, E. C. (2021). A psychologically rich life: Beyond happiness and
meaning. Psychological Review. doi:10.1037/rev0000317
Pargament, K. I., Wong, S., & Exline, J. J. (2016). Wholeness and holiness: The spiritual
dimension of eudaimonics. In Handbook of eudaimonic well-being (pp. 379–394).
Springer.
Pirsig, R. (1974). Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance: An Inquiry into Values.
Random House.
Posner, M. I., & Petersen, S. E. (1990). The attention system of the human brain. Annual
Review of Neuroscience, 13(1), 25–42.
Putnam, R. D. (1995). Tuning in, tuning out: The strange disappearance of social capital in
America. Political Science and Politics, 28(4), 664–683. doi:10.2307/420517
Reeves, C. A., & Bednar, D. A. (1994). Defining quality: alternatives and implications.
Academy of Management Review, 19(3), 419–445.
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
28
Robbins, B. D. (2021). The joyful life: An existential-humanistic approach to positive
psychology in the time of a pandemic. Frontiers in Psychology. 12, 648600;
https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2021.648600
Ryan, R. M., & Deci, E. L. (2000). Self-determination theory and the facilitation of intrinsic
motivation, social development, and well-being. American Psychologist, 55(1), 68–78.
doi:10.1037/0003-066X.55.1.68
Ryan, R. M., & Frederick, C. (1997). On Energy, Personality, and Health: Subjective Vitality
as a Dynamic Reflection of Well-Being. Journal of Personality, 65(3), 529–565.
doi:10.1111/j.1467-6494.1997.tb00326.x
Ryff, C. D. (1989). Happiness is everything, or is it? Explorations on the meaning of
psychological well-being. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 57(6), 1069–
1081. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.57.6.1069
Sampaio, R. A. C., Sewo Sampaio, P. Y., Yamada, M., Tsuboyama, T., & Arai, H. (2014).
Self‐reported quality of sleep is associated with bodily pain, vitality and cognitive
impairment in Japanese older adults. Geriatrics & Gerontology International, 14(3),
628–635.
Schueller, S. M., & Seligman, M. E. P. (2010). Pursuit of pleasure, engagement, and
meaning: Relationships to subjective and objective measures of well-being. The Journal
of Positive Psychology, 5(4), 253–263. doi:10.1080/17439761003794130
Schwebel, D. C., Stavrinos, D., & Kongable, E. M. (2009). Attentional control, high intensity
pleasure, and risky pedestrian behavior in college students. Accident Analysis &
Prevention, 41(3), 658–661. doi:10.1016/j.aap.2009.03.003
Seligman, M. E. P. (2002). Authentic Happiness: Using the New Positive Psychology to
Realize your Potential for Lasting Fulfillment. Free Press.
Smith, J. A. (2011). Evaluating the contribution of interpretative phenomenological analysis.
Health Psychology Review, 5(1), 9–27. doi:10.1080/17437199.2010.510659
Steger, M. F., Frazier, P., Kaler, M., & Oishi, S. (2006). The meaning in life questionnaire:
Assessing the presence of and search for meaning in life. Journal of Counseling
Psychology, 53(1), 80–93. doi:10.1037/0022-0167.53.1.80
Tay, L., & Pawelski, J. O. (Eds.). (2022). The Oxford Handbook of the Positive Humanities.
Oxford University Press.
Tedeschi, R. G., Park, C. L., & Calhoun, L. G. (1998). Posttraumatic growth: Positive
changes in the aftermath of crisis. Routledge.
Tsai, J. L., Knutson, B., & Fung, H. H. (2006). Cultural variation in affect valuation. Journal
Running head: AN EXPANDED TAXONOMY OF HAPPNESS
29
of Personality and Social Psychology, 90(2), 288–307. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.90.2.288
VanderWeele, T. J. (2020). Spiritual wellbeing and human flourishing: conceptual, causal,
and policy relations. In A. B. Cohen (Ed.), Religion and Human Flourishing (pp. 43–
54). Baylor University Press.
VanderWeele, T. J., & Lomas, T. (2022). Terminology and the well-being literature. Affective
Science, 1-5. doi:10.1007/s42761-022-00153-2
Wahbeh, H., Sagher, A., Back, W., Pundhir, P., & Travis, F. (2018). A systematic review of
transcendent states across meditation and contemplative traditions. Explore, 14(1), 19–
35. doi:10.1016/j.explore.2017.07.007
Watson, D., Clark, L. A., & Tellegen, A. (1988). Development and validation of brief
measures of positive and negative affect: The PANAS scales. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 54(6), 1063–1070. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.54.6.1063
Wayment, H. A., Bauer, J. J., & Sylaska, K. (2015). The Quiet Ego Scale: Measuring the
Compassionate Self-Identity. Journal of Happiness Studies, 16(4), 999–1033.
doi:10.1007/s10902-014-9546-z
Wong, P. T. P., & Bowers, V. (2019). Mature happiness and global wellbeing in difficult
times. In Scientific concepts behind happiness, kindness, and empathy in contemporary
society (pp. 112–134). IGI Global.
World Health Organization (1948). Preamble to the Constitution of the World Health
Organization as Adopted by the International Health Conference, New York, 19-22
June, 1946. World Health Organization.