Content uploaded by Leda Cosmides
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Leda Cosmides on Oct 12, 2022
Content may be subject to copyright.
This shareable PDF can be hosted on any platform or network and is fully compliant with publisher copyright.
A moral trade-o system produces intuitive judgments that are rational and coherent and
strike a balance between conicting moral values
Ricardo Andrés Guzmán, María Teresa Barbato, Daniel Sznycer, Leda Cosmides
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, October 2022, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences
DOI: 10.1073/pnas.2214005119
Making moral tradeos when facing a
dilemma
What is it about?
Intuitions about right and wrong clash in moral dilemmas. This paper is about how
our mind makes judgments when that happens. It shows we have a cognitive system
that handles dilemmas very well, producing intuitive judgments that are rational
*and* coherent *and* strike a balance between conicting moral values.
We reported evidence that dilemmas activate a moral trade-o system: a cognitive
system that is well designed for making trade-os between conicting moral values.
When asked which option for resolving a dilemma is morally right, many people
made compromise judgments, which strike a balance between
conicting moral values by partially satisfying both. Furthermore, their moral
judgments satised a demanding standard of rational choice: the Generalized Axiom
of Revealed Preferences. Deliberative reasoning cannot explain these results, nor can
a tug-of-war between emotion and reason. The results are the signature of a
cognitive system that weighs competing moral considerations and chooses the
solution that maximizes rightness.
Why is it important?
Many psychologists underestimate the sophistication and rationality of human
cognition. They argue that we can reason deliberatively (which is obviously true), but
that evolved emotions, heuristics, or inferences pre-empt, interfere with, or bias our
reasoning. A case in point involves sacricial moral dilemmas (in which saving the
most lives requires harming innocents--as in trolley problems). According to an
inuential theory, these moral dilemmas elicit a tug-of-war between emotions and
reasoning, which prevents us from making judgments that strike a balance between
conicting moral values by partially satisfying both. But this makes no sense from an
evolutionary perspective. Moral dilemmas are, and always have been, part of the
human condition. Our ancestors lived in dense, interdependent social groups, and
had obligations and duties to children, parents, siblings, friends, neighbors,
coalitional allies and others. In many (most?) cases, it was impossible to fully satisfy
all of these obligations. Sometimes the best you can do is partially satisfy several of
them. This suggests that natural selection would have built computational
machinery that is good at weighing various obligations, and producing compromise
judgments (ones that partially satisfy two or more conicting values). Our research
provides evidence of a cognitive system that does just that, producing intuitive
judgments systematically and rationally, while maintaining moral coherence (i.e., the
judgments vary sensibly with changing conditions). Across situations, people
In partnership with:
Read Publication
https://link.growkudos.com/1myw8bfmi2o
consistently chose the resolution to a dilemma that was *most right*, given how
their mind weighed the competing moral values. In fact, their judgments satised a
standard of rationality from microeconomics that implies the existence of an
optimizing algorithm.
Perspectives
LC
Leda Cosmides
University of California Santa Barbara
My personal perspective:
Strangely, I found our results (and the evolutionary analysis accompanying it)
comforting. For years, I suered because I could not gure out how to be a good
mother and a good professor at the same time. I always felt I was failing someone. If
I was fully satisfying my obligations to my child, I was failing at some of my duties in
the department, to my colleagues or students. If I was doing right by my grad
students, I felt like I was failing my child. Working on this paper brought home that
doing it all was literally impossible. Often, the best choice--the one that is most right-
-is to satisfy most of your obligations partially: a compromise judgment. What counts
as "most right" will vary from person to person, of course, because it depends on
how heavily you weigh your competing obligations, to family, students, colleagues,
etc. (a "rightness function" (as discussed in the paper) expresses those weights). But
it is comforting to know that we have a cognitive system that takes all that
information into account, does a nonconscious computation that determines which
available option maximizes rightness, given your values--and that *that* is the option
that will feel most right (an intuitive judgment). And to me, it is interesting to know
that the option that feels most right is sometimes a compromise judgment. I was
always going all-out, exhausted most of the time, yet feeling like I was failing at all my
obligations. Now I realize that it was my expectations that were nuts, and what I saw
as failures were compromise moral judgments--my mind was striking a balance
between all these obligations. And that is just part of the human condition.
The following have contributed to this page: Leda Cosmides
PDF generated on 11-Oct-2022
Create your own PDF summaries at www.growkudos.com.