ArticlePDF Available
Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at
https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=uajb20
The American Journal of Bioethics
ISSN: (Print) (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/uajb20
Personhood, Welfare, and Enhancement
Hugh Desmond
To cite this article: Hugh Desmond (2022) Personhood, Welfare, and Enhancement, The
American Journal of Bioethics, 22:9, 37-39, DOI: 10.1080/15265161.2022.2105428
To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/15265161.2022.2105428
Published online: 30 Aug 2022.
Submit your article to this journal
Article views: 8
View related articles
View Crossmark data
THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF BIOETHICS
2022, VOL. 22, NO. 9, 3739
https://doi.org/10.1080/15265161.2022.2105428
OPEN PEER COMMENTARIES
Personhood, Welfare, and Enhancement
Hugh Desmond
a,b
a
Leibniz Universitat Hannover;
b
University of Antwerp
The debate on enhancement ethics cannot escape
some of the deeper questions troubling the concept of
personhood. That is, in a sentence, my reading of
Robert Sparrows target article (Sparrow 2022). This
development is significant for enhancement ethics,
because personhood has assumed the grounding role
once played by human nature. Thinking in terms of
effects on persons (instead of on human nature) fits
in with liberal approaches to enhancement, where
enhancements are either like life choices to be regu-
lated along libertarian principles, or like goods such as
education to be regulated along principles of fairness.
Genetic enhancement in particular can be subsumed
under parental autonomy: parents choosing the best
for their child. However, insofar the liberal approach
rests on the metaphysical fulcrum of personhood,
problems with the latter reverberate throughout
enhancement ethics. In this commentary I will add
two problems to those already identified by Sparrow:
one regarding person-affecting enhancement, and the
other regarding identity-affecting enhancement.
A PROBLEM FOR PERSON-AFFECTING
ENHANCEMENT
What is the object of enhancement? The standard
answer is: a person, and more specifically, a persons
welfare (defined as the total of benefits minus harms
befalling that person). However, Parfit divorces wel-
fare from personhood. According to Parfit, there is
nothing more to a person than different gradations of
psychological connectedness(Parfit 1984, 215).
Parfit argued for this by means various futuristic puz-
zles regarding personal identity (brain transplants;
teletransportation; and so on), but his metaphysics
ultimately concerned ethics: if one could adopt this
reductionist stance on personhood, the impersonality
required by genuine utilitarianism made sense. What
matters is the quality of experiences being had, not
whether those experiences are being had by you or by
me, or even by someone at great spatiotemporal dis-
tance (Parfit 1984, 346).
Like many utilitarians, in no meaningful way does
Parfit speak of how utilitarian calculations should be
affected by the particulars of the social structures in
which a person is contingently embedded, such as
families, communities, or institutions. Experiences just
are there. If one adopts the Parfitian reductionism
towards persons, the social embeddedness of persons
(or more exactly, the embeddedness of loci of psycho-
logical connectedness) poses a problem for the con-
cept of person-affecting enhancement. For when the
subjective experiences of welfare are so connected
with external social processes, how much sense does it
still have to maintain that a personis the object of
enhancement?
As a first illustration of what I have in mind, con-
sider one of the most straightforward forms of human
enhancement: athletic enhancement. Who are athletes
aiming to benefit when they choose performance-
enhancing drugs? Themselves? Not if the athlete is a
true Parfitian. A Parfitian athlete would be moved by
the prospect of giving millions of sports fans a more
enjoyable experience, or of giving more prize earnings
to charity. Most athletes, of course, are not Parfitian.
They report on motivations to obtain a hero status
and financial gain without any further goal beyond
their own benefit (see discussion in Desmond 2021,
CONTACT Hugh Desmond hugh.desmond@gmail.com Department of Philosophy, Leibniz Universitat Hannover, Hannover, 30167, Germany;
Department of Philosophy, University of Antwerp, Antwerpen, 2000, Belgium.
ß2022 Taylor & Francis Group, LLC
THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF BIOETHICS 37
38). Nonetheless, we could question here who pre-
cisely is intended to receive the future benefit from
the athletic doping. Is it the future personconsti-
tuted of a rich interconnectedness of memories, val-
ues, experiences? Or, a socialized idealization of their
future self that the athlete has constructed?
Sparrow elucidates a structurally similar example
when pointing out that acting as to maximize welfare
would dictate that parents choose the embryos best
adapted to racist, sexist, and heteronormative social
environments. Here we can similarly question who
precisely the parents wish to target with the enhance-
ment intervention. A person as some rich, unique
combination of traits, or an avatar consisting of a
small number of desirable traits?
Such examples are not marginal considerations for
the ethics of enhancement. Elsewhere I have worked
to show how social status infiltrate many of our deci-
sionsespecially decisions to enhanceand how an
ethics of enhancement should reflect this (Desmond
2020,2021). The examples also point to the limits of
an individual-focused ethics, since our ideas about
what will bring us welfareor benefitis inextricably
bound up with the evaluative judgments present in
families, communities, or even online environments
such as social media (for the latter, see
Desmond 2022).
The problem I wish to raise for the category of
person-affecting enhancementis that it is often
ambiguous whether a person (and a persons welfare)
is targeted by an enhancement or rather a representant
of a status class. Here I mean representantin the
mathematical sense where persons are modeled as
interchangeable members of equivalence classes. For
instance, an advertiser might want the Olympic cham-
pion in the 100-meter dashit would not matter who
they are, just as long as the person being hired hap-
pens to have that title. The category of fair-weather
friendencapsulates this idea: this type of friend does
not care about who you are as a person, but merely
who you are as a representant of a certain type of suc-
cess or status.
Similarly, if we strive to enhance ourselves in order
to achieve a type of welfare that ultimately consists of
the approval of others, we can become our own fair-
weather friends. I do not wish to deny that the pleas-
ure we feel at receiving praise, recognition, or honor
from others may be genuine. However, if an enhance-
ment that is directed at ones future self is driven
(even if unconsciously) by a desire for social status,
the target is not a person but rather an abstract repre-
sentation of a person. One could call this
representation by various names: a socialized idealiza-
tion, an avatar, or a representant of a social status
equivalence class. However, the upshot is that such
enhancements may increase welfare without being
genuinely person-affecting in even the reductionist,
Parfitian sense of person.
IDENTIFY-AFFECTING ENHANCEMENT AND THE
LIBERAL APPROACH TO ENHANCEMENT
That being said, genetic enhancement, as it is cur-
rently implemented, is not person-effecting. Phrases
such as knocking out a geneare misleading in this
regard, since they suggest that genetic enhancement is
akin to pressing a particular switch in the internal
mechanisms of a persons body. The science is much
more complicated than that, as Sparrow emphasizes.
The latest genome engineering technologies (CRISPR-
Cas) merely affect the probabilities of how an embryo
will develop. From the perspective of philosophy of
science, this is not surprising: cells are highly stochas-
tic and the common textbook representation of them
as complex machines is a significant idealization of
reality (Nicholson 2019). For many epistemic chal-
lenges this idealization does the job, but for others it
does not and the ethics of CRISPR-Cas seems to be
one of those. Whether following the technique of edit-
ing the genome of a live embryo, or of inducing gam-
etogenesis of gene-edited pluripotent stem cells, it is
necessary to conduct several attempts and subse-
quently select the most desirable embryo. In other
words, genetic enhancement for the foreseeable future
will involve generating and selecting between multiple
embryos. Instead of increasing the welfare of existing
persons, genetic enhancement de facto selects which
persons can come into existence.
Such identify-affecting enhancements may not
seem very puzzling for a Parfitian ethics. Parfit argues
that one should simply select the persons with highest
expected welfare (Parfit 1984, 356360). One could of
course question how helpful this prescription is: the
idea of being able to make total expected welfare cal-
culation of an entire person calls to mind an omnisci-
ent God on judgment day. However, even if we
bracket such concerns, the category of identity-affect-
ing enhancements runs into fundamental problems.
The first problem is that liberal principles are not
necessarily respected when selecting persons with
highest expected welfare. Think of how eugenicists
justified measures such as forcible sterilization with
reference to a utilitarian calculation where the short-
term pains of administering cruel treatments and of
38 OPEN PEER COMMENTARIES
suppressing instincts of sympathy were outweighed by
the long-term benefit to the human stock. Similarly, if
we stipulate that some type of trait, such as
intelligence,is an intrinsic good because it raises the
welfare of the person involved, one could use utilitar-
ian reasoning to justify the genetic enhancement of
such a trait through methods that are equivalent to
improving human stock. Of course, there is a signifi-
cant moral difference between the artificial selection
on embryos and the artificial selection on fully devel-
oped human beings. Nonetheless, there is nothing in
this line of reasoning that should preclude the
endorsement of widespread social programs to
improve human stock at the embryonic stage.
So it would be desirable (for ethicists) to be able to
conceptualize identity-affecting enhancements in a
way that safeguards basic liberal principles. However,
which principles are applicable? It makes no sense to
refer to the autonomy of the enhancee given that the
act of enhancement brings them into existence. One
cannot refer to parental autonomy either, because
genetic enhancement does not involve acting in the
best interests of a specific offspring in the way that
guardianship, where parental autonomy is paradigmat-
ically appropriate, does. Could we then say that one
should select those persons that have the best chance
of flourishing? Unfortunately, the concept of flourish-
ing is intertwined with concepts of human nature,
and it would seem unsatisfactory for a person-based
ethics of enhancement to bottom out in human
nature. Alternatively, one could invoke an older
meaning of the word liberal,namely that it refers to
respecting the intrinsic value of a person. In this older
sense of liberalism, respect of human autonomy is
merely one way of respecting the intrinsic value of a
person. However, what is the intrinsic valueof a
person? With this type of language, we are approach-
ing a Thomistic mindset, where the concept of human
nature is precisely what grounds the intrinsic value of
persons (Eberl 2014). This line of reasoning also bot-
toms out in the concept of human nature, raising the
same problem for a person-based enhancement ethics.
In this way, if one accepts that genetic enhance-
ment is not a person-affecting enhancement, but must
be an identity-affecting enhancement, it becomes
unclear how precisely liberal approaches to enhance-
ment should reason about such cases. As a final
remark, this problem suggests a different diagnosis
(compared to Sparrows) why person-affecting
enhancements have received outsized attention in the
literature: they neatly fit into a liberal approach to
enhancement. By contrast, it is not clear how identify-
affecting enhancements fit in, if at all.
FUNDING
The author(s) reported there is no funding associated with
the work featured in this article.
ORCID
Hugh Desmond http://orcid.org/0000-0002-4822-923X
REFERENCES
Desmond, H. 2020. Service and status competition may
help explain perceived ethical acceptability. The American
Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience 11 (4):25860. doi:10.
1080/21507740.2020.1830874.
Desmond, H. 2021. In service to others: A new evolutionary
perspective on human enhancement. The Hastings Center
Report 51 (6):3343. doi:10.1002/hast.1305.
Desmond, H. 2022. Reclaiming Privacy and Care in the Age
of Social Media. Royal Institute of Philosophy
Supplements. doi:10.1017/S135824612200025X.
Eberl, J. T. 2014. A Thomistic appraisal of human enhance-
ment technologies. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 35
(4):289310. doi:10.1007/s11017-014-9300-x.
Nicholson, D. J. 2019. Is the cell really a machine? Journal
of Theoretical Biology 477 (September):10826. doi:10.
1016/j.jtbi.2019.06.002.
Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and persons. Oxford: Clarendon
Press.
Sparrow, R. 2022. Human germline genome editing: On the
nature of our reasons to genome edit. The American
Journal of Bioethics 22 (9):415. doi: 10.1080/15265161.
2021.1907480.
THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF BIOETHICS 39
ResearchGate has not been able to resolve any citations for this publication.
Article
Full-text available
Social media has invaded our private, professional, and public lives. While corporations continue to portray social media as a celebration of self-expression and freedom, public opinion, by contrast, seems to have decidedly turned against social media. Yet we continue to use it just the same. What is social media, and how should we live with it? Is it the promise of a happier and more interconnected humanity, or a vehicle for toxic self-promotion? In this essay I examine the very structure of social media communications in order to sketch how we should engage with social media. Social media communications are, I argue, a public communication of private content. This allows connections to be made with others in ways that would not otherwise be possible; however, it also submits the private to a status competition, which in turn is linked to mental health challenges. A ‘virtuous’ engagement with social media means being aware of these dynamics, and choosing to subordinate social media to other, more important goods.
Article
Full-text available
In enhancement ethics, evolutionary theory has been largely perceived as supporting liberal views on enhancement, where decisions to enhance are predominantly regulated by the principle of individual autonomy. In this paper I critique this perception in light of recent scientific developments. Cultural evolutionary theory suggests a picture where individual interests are entangled with community interests, and this undermines the applicability of the principle of autonomy. This is particularly relevant for enhancement ethics, given how – I argue – decisions to enhance are often influenced by desires to increase social status. The “service view on enhancement”, based on principles of service and trust, is proposed as offering better guidance for the challenges of social living.
Article
Full-text available
Debate concerning human enhancement often revolves around the question of whether there is a common "nature" that all human beings share and which is unwarrantedly violated by enhancing one's capabilities beyond the "species-typical" norm. I explicate Thomas Aquinas's influential theory of human nature, noting certain key traits commonly shared among human beings that define each as a "person" who possesses inviolable moral status. Understanding the specific qualities that define the nature of human persons, which includes self-conscious awareness, capacity for intellective thought, and volitional autonomy, informs the ethical assessment of various forms of enhancement. Some forms of cognitive and physical enhancement may be desirable from the perspective of what constitutes the "flourishing" of human persons in our fundamental nature; while other forms of enhancement, such as emotive or so-called "moral" enhancement, run the risk of detracting from human flourishing when evaluated from the virtue-theoretic perspective Aquinas promotes.
Article
Ever since the publication of Derek Parfit’s Reasons and Persons, bioethicists have tended to distinguish between two different ways in which reproductive technologies may have implications for the welfare of future persons. Some interventions harm or benefit particular individuals: they are “person affecting.” Other interventions determine which individual, of a number of possible individuals, comes into existence: they are “identity affecting” and raise the famous “non-identity problem.” For the past several decades, bioethical debate has, for the most part, proceeded on the assumption that direct genetic modification of human embryos would be person affecting. In this paper, I argue that that genome editing is highly unlikely to be person affecting for the foreseeable future and, as a result, will neither benefit nor harm edited individuals.