ArticlePublisher preview available

Situational factors shape moral judgements in the trolley dilemma in Eastern, Southern and Western countries in a culturally diverse sample

Authors:
To read the full-text of this research, you can request a copy directly from the authors.

Abstract and Figures

The study of moral judgements often centres on moral dilemmas in which options consistent with deontological perspectives (that is, emphasizing rules, individual rights and duties) are in conflict with options consistent with utilitarian judgements (that is, following the greater good based on consequences). Greene et al. (2009) showed that psychological and situational factors (for example, the intent of the agent or the presence of physical contact between the agent and the victim) can play an important role in moral dilemma judgements (for example, the trolley problem). Our knowledge is limited concerning both the universality of these effects outside the United States and the impact of culture on the situational and psychological factors affecting moral judgements. Thus, we empirically tested the universality of the effects of intent and personal force on moral dilemma judgements by replicating the experiments of Greene et al. in 45 countries from all inhabited continents. We found that personal force and its interaction with intention exert influence on moral judgements in the US and Western cultural clusters, replicating and expanding the original findings. Moreover, the personal force effect was present in all cultural clusters, suggesting it is culturally universal. The evidence for the cultural universality of the interaction effect was inconclusive in the Eastern and Southern cultural clusters (depending on exclusion criteria). We found no strong association between collectivism/individualism and moral dilemma judgements.
This content is subject to copyright. Terms and conditions apply.
RegisteRed RepoRt
https://doi.org/10.1038/s41562-022-01319-5
A full list of affiliations appears at the end of the paper.
Moral dilemmas can be portrayed as decisions between two
main conflicting moral principles: utilitarian and deon-
tological. Utilitarian (also referred to as consequentialist)
philosophies1 hold that an action is morally acceptable if it maxi-
mizes well-being for the greatest number of people (in terms of saved
lives, for example). On the other hand, deontological philosophy2
evaluates the morality of the action based on the intrinsic nature
of the action (that is, often reflecting greater concern for individ-
ual rights and duties3). The dilemma between these two principles
plays a prominent role in law and policy-making decisions, ranging
from decisions of health budget allocations4 to dilemmas related to
self-driving vehicles5. This inherent conflict is well illustrated by the
so-called trolley problem, which has long interested both philoso-
phers and psychologists. One version of the dilemma is presented
as follows:6
You are a railway controller. There is a runaway trolley barrelling
down the railway tracks. Ahead, on the tracks, there are five work-
men. The trolley is headed straight for them, and they will be killed
if nothing is done. You are standing some distance off in the train
yard, next to a lever. If you pull this lever, the trolley will switch to a
side track and you can save the five workmen on the main track. You
notice that there are two workmen on the side track. So there will
be two workmen who will be killed if you pull the lever and change
the tracks, but the five workmen on the main track will be saved. Is
it morally acceptable for you to pull the lever?
A deontological decision-maker would argue that pulling the
lever is morally unacceptable, as it would be murder. (Note that
deontological principles are often more complicated than this.
Some of the deontological rules would allow for killing in this situ-
ation. The terms ‘deontological’ and ‘utilitarian/consequentialist’
are labels we use to refer to certain responses.) On the other hand,
utilitarianism would suggest that it is morally acceptable to pull the
lever, as it would maximize the number of lives saved.
In an alternative version of the dilemma, one has to push a man
off a footbridge in front of the trolley (the ‘footbridge’ scenario).
This man will die but will stop the trolley, and the five people in the
way of the trolley will be saved. Interestingly, people are less likely to
make a decision consistent with utilitarian perspectives in the foot-
bridge scenario compared with the standard switch scenario. (We
call these ‘utilitarian’ responses, but the fact that these decisions are
consistent with utilitarianism does not indicate that people gave
them out of utilitarian principles. The same is true for ‘deontologi-
cal’ responses7,8.) The difference between the utilitarian response
rate in those scenarios became the basis of investigations of many
influential cognitive theories in the field of moral judgement3,713.
The fact that people respond differently to the two trolley dilemmas
was proposed to be explained by people’s adherence to the so-called
doctrine of double effect6,9. A simple version of this doctrine is that
harm is permissible as an unintentional side-effect of a good result.
This doctrine is the basis of many policies in several countries all
around the world concerning issues such as abortion6, euthanasia14,
international armed conflict regulations15,16 and even international
business ethics17. According to this doctrine, it is morally impermis-
sible to bomb civilians to win a war, even if ending the war would
eventually save more lives. However, if civilians die in a bombing of
a nearby weapons factory as a side-effect, the bombing is morally
acceptable. The way people perceive or act on these moral rules can
influence the policies that are accepted or even followed, as we can
already see in the case of driverless cars, which sometimes have to
decide between sacrificing their own passengers and saving one or
more pedestrians5.
However, Greene et al.18 and Cushman et al.9 argued that the dif-
ference in utilitarian response rates cannot simply be explained by
the doctrine of double effect. Greene et al. presented evidence for
the interaction of the intention of harm (that is, harm as means or
side-effect, referring to the doctrine of double effect) and personal
Situational factors shape moral judgements in the
trolley dilemma in Eastern, Southern and Western
countries in a culturally diverse sample
The study of moral judgements often centres on moral dilemmas in which options consistent with deontological perspectives
(that is, emphasizing rules, individual rights and duties) are in conflict with options consistent with utilitarian judgements
(that is, following the greater good based on consequences). Greene et al. (2009) showed that psychological and situational
factors (for example, the intent of the agent or the presence of physical contact between the agent and the victim) can play an
important role in moral dilemma judgements (for example, the trolley problem). Our knowledge is limited concerning both the
universality of these effects outside the United States and the impact of culture on the situational and psychological factors
affecting moral judgements. Thus, we empirically tested the universality of the effects of intent and personal force on moral
dilemma judgements by replicating the experiments of Greene et al. in 45 countries from all inhabited continents. We found
that personal force and its interaction with intention exert influence on moral judgements in the US and Western cultural clus-
ters, replicating and expanding the original findings. Moreover, the personal force effect was present in all cultural clusters,
suggesting it is culturally universal. The evidence for the cultural universality of the interaction effect was inconclusive in the
Eastern and Southern cultural clusters (depending on exclusion criteria). We found no strong association between collectivism/
individualism and moral dilemma judgements.
NATURE HUMAN BEHAVIOUR | VOL 6 | JUNE 2022 | 880–895 | www.nature.com/nathumbehav
880
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved
... In this scenario, a runaway trolley is headed toward five workers on one track, and the option is to divert it onto another track with one worker [2]. The current focus of research on the trolley problem and other moral dilemmas is on comparing two normative ethical approaches: deontological perspectives and utilitarian judgments [3]. However, these normative ethical theories have limitations in real-world applications as they oversimplify complex scenarios and may not consider all factors influencing moral decisions [4]. ...
... Southern Cultures: Participants from Southern cultures tended to be more influenced by social and emotional factors, such as personal responsibility and the potential for blame, in their moral judgments. Western Cultures: Individuals from Western cultures exhibited a mixed pattern, with some endorsing utilitarian judgments and others emphasizing rules and duties to make the decision [3]. It can be reasonably concluded. ...
... In the previous research, participants were less likely to endorse utilitarian choices when the victim was a loved one or someone they knew personally, highlighting the influence of emotional closeness. They were more likely to endorse utilitarian choices when the action was perceived as less directly causing harm (e.g., pushing a button to divert the trolley) versus directly pushing someone onto the tracks [3]. Despite applying normative ethics as a basis, these two arguments are situational factors, closeness to the victim, and agency, respectively. ...
Article
Full-text available
Scholars have been constantly interested in studying moral quandaries, including the trolley problem. Despite their widespread adoption, normative ethical theories have challenges in real-world scenarios. This study explores the impact of interpersonal and cross-cultural factors on trolley dilemma judgments through the Morality-as-Cooperation (MAC) model. The study mainly reviews pertinent literature and discusses how the MAC model applies to the trolley dilemma. It demonstrates how interpersonal relationships and cultural norms influence decision-making. Eastern civilizations, for instance, place a high value on communal welfare. Although it has limitations, the MAC model provides a more thorough framework than normative ethics. The MAC model is a prospective alternative, but further research is required to better comprehend moral dilemmas and bridge the disparity between theory and practice in morality research, particularly in enhancing the accuracy of interpersonal perception and methodological considerations.
... In psychological science, we are almost always interested in investigating some kind of latent variable (e.g., personality traits like extraversion). The object of research is often the comparison of mean values of latent variables (or measurements thereof) between different groups; for example, prosociality or moral judgements across countries (Bago et al., 2022;House et al., 2020). This includes both comparisons between different groups (e.g., in cross-cultural research; Milfont & Fischer, 2010) or comparisons across subsequent measurements within the same group (e.g., pre-and posttreatment). ...
... MGFR resolves the rotational indeterminacy per group and locates non-invariant factor loadings by means of hypothesis testing. We demonstrate all of this on an empirical data example from moral psychology (Bago et al., 2022). Because the methods differ in their assumptions and outcomes, a direct comparison does not make too much sense. ...
... For our empirical demonstration of the presented methods, we used the dataset published by Bago et al. (2022) and investigated MI of the Oxford Utilitarianism Scale (OUS; Kahane et al., 2018). In a multilab study, Bago et al. (2022) examined the influence of psychological and situational factors on the judgement of moral dilemmas. ...
... But this results still suggest the cultural difference may change at each age stage and a larger matched sample is needed for further cultural compare. A recent study about moral judgments in trolley dilemma in cultural diverse sample in Eastern, Western and Southern countries found that the personal force (i.e., whether or not to use personal effort to kill the one person) effect was universal in all cultural clusters, but found no strong association between collective/individual culture and moral judgments (Bago et al. 2022). ...
Article
Full-text available
This study explores how peers influence the moral decisions of Chinese adolescents (12‐ to 16‐year‐olds, Mage = 14.32, n = 84) and young adults (18‐ to 26‐year‐olds, Mage = 20.92, n = 99) in moral dilemmas. Participants were asked to make moral decisions individually and then collectively within groups of three to reach a consensus in Trolly dilemma and Footbridge dilemma. They were also required to evaluate the degree to which they felt their decisions were moral. Results showed that adolescents tended to choose “action” (pull the lever in Trolly dilemma, or push the man in Footbridge dilemma) more than adults, and evaluate their “no action” choice as more immoral than young adults across both individual and group settings. Adolescents showed consistent decision‐making patterns regardless of whether decisions were made individually or collectively, while adults were more likely to choose “no action” in group decision‐making. Our results suggest that adolescents are more utilitarian than young adults when making decisions in moral dilemmas, compared to young adults. Young adults are less likely to make utilitarian choices when they are in groups than when they make decisions individually.
... Specifically, morality refers to the principles that guide individuals in distinguishing right from wrong and making decisions that uphold social norms. In order to maintain coherence and avoid actions that violate collective moral principles, which might hinder access to key social and psychological benefits, individuals must evaluate moral situations and respond appropriately [2]. In recent years, an increasing number of studies have found that individuals are significantly influenced by emotions when assessing moral situations; for instance, individuals with low empathy tend to disregard moral norms when they receive negative emotional feedback [3]. ...
Article
Full-text available
Background: Moral evaluation is identified as the first stage in the theory of moral judgment, and academics believe that it may align with the social intuitionist model. This study aims to prove that the model’s emotional dominance hypothesis applies to moral evaluation by presenting a computational decision-making model that mathematically formalizes this emotional dominance decision-making process. We also compared different types of valence evaluation tasks to test the emotional priority hypothesis. Methods: We used a convenience sampling method to randomly recruit 30 enrolled college students. The drift-diffusion model was employed to analyze reaction times for words with various emotional and moral valences Additionally, we designed different valence evaluation tasks based on the response relevance hypothesis and evaluated the processing order through reaction time comparisons. Results: The analysis revealed that the emotional mechanism of immoral evaluation differs from moral evaluation. An increase in emotional valence accelerates the speed of evidence accumulation (v) for moral evaluation (M = 1.21, 0.2% < 0 < 99.8%) but lowers decision caution (a) in immoral evaluation (M = −0.64, 96.1% < 0 < 3.9%). In contrast, moral valence does not have a significant influence on evaluation processes (v, M = −0.28, 72.1% < 0 < 27.9%; a, M = −0.32, 79.3% < 0 < 20.7%). Furthermore, We found no significant difference in reaction times between moral and immoral words in the emotional evaluation task (F(1,29) = 0.55, p = 0.464, partial η2 = 0.02), but a significant difference existed in the moral evaluation task (F(1,29) = 17.99, p < 0.001, partial η2 = 0.38), indicating that the tendency of relatively fast immoral evaluation in emotional evaluation tasks may be caused by emotional priority. Conclusions: Our findings support the intuitive model’s emotional dominance hypothesis and introduce a new emotional mechanism into moral evaluation. This study clarifies the distinct emotional processes in moral and immoral evaluations, fills a gap in the research on moral evaluation, and offers insights into human decision-making in moral contexts.
Article
The cross‐indigenous approach is introduced as a framework for conducting multi‐site studies. The cross‐indigenous approach is a simultaneous multi‐emic approach to studying psychological and social phenomena across cultures which intends to mitigate vulnerabilities commonly found in typical cross‐cultural studies done in social and personality psychology including methodological artifacts introduced when instruments, protocols, or research design do not work as expected across target cultures, and the unrealistic expectation of construct equivalence across sites. The article discusses ways to carry out a cross‐indigenous project which aims to be a principled way of making comparisons across cultures, aiming to stake out what are unique, what are shared and what are universals across populations, to explain psychological and social processes through culture‐sensitive and naturalistic methods.
Article
Full-text available
Ethical dilemmas facing respondents with a choice between sacrificing the lives of a smaller number of people to save a larger number, formulated in correspondence to the famous Trolley Problem, have been of enduring interest since Philippa Foot’s presentation of the canonical version of this problem. In more recent literature, and especially in publications reporting the results of empirical research, decisions of answerers declaring abstention from taking action that would result in saving a larger group of potential victims at the cost of sacrificing the lives of fewer people have come to be referred to as “deontological” choices. On the other hand, declarations of readiness to take such actions are referred to as “utilitarian” or (less frequently) “consequentialist” choices. The aim of the article is to demonstrate the shortcomings of using the aforementioned labels. The argumentation is supported by empirical material collected in the years 2020–2022 among students of the University of Łódź (N = 302). The analysis of justifications explaining the motives behind both types of decisions left by the respondents shows that in numerous cases, “deontological” decisions, that is, passive decisions, actually stemmed from premises much closer to consequentialist ethics than deontological attitudes. Similarly, active behaviour was not always the outcome of utilitarian motives. The results of our research clearly indicate that the dominant, simplified perception of these choices in the literature leads to a distorted picture of the moral attitudes of respondents, thus posing the danger of drawing false conclusions. We claim that distinguishing between attitudes adopted by respondents in dilemmas based on the Trolley Problem should not refer to ethical doctrines. Instead, judging the moral attitudes of respondents requires an analysis of the motives behind the decisions they make, at the very least.
Article
Full-text available
Complex decision making (CDM) processes differ from simple ones in that they require greater cognitive engagement and a longer response time. In previous cognitive experiments, the effect of Repetition (RP) and Emotional Semantic priming (ESP) was evaluated on decisions made by participants randomly divided into 2 groups asking them to choose a face in order to perform an important task (IMT) or without specifying the task (UST). The results indicated that CDM processes could be modulated by both priming when the task was not specified (UST group), but not when the choice was made to perform an important task (IMT group), when response time was higher. These experiments raise the role of the nature of the task in a possible top-down mechanism modulating CDM. The aim of this work was to assess whether it is complexity, rather than relevance, that triggers the top-down mechanism. For this purpose, online experiments were conducted to assess whether RP or ESP modulated the decisions of subject randomly assigned to a new experimental group, which was asked to choose a face (from 4) for a non-important task (NIT), or a new UST group. The NIT group showed no susceptibility to priming, and their response times were longer, compatible with type-2 reflexive processes. These results support the hypothesis that priming modulation might be affected by the cognitive complexity associated with the task, rather than importance, initiating the top-down modulation mechanism. Knowing the conditions that make political decisions less automatic has a social relevance, in order to improve our democracies.
Article
Full-text available
Cilj ovog istraživanja bio je adaptacija na srpski jezik i ispitivanje funkcionalne ekvivalentnosti adaptirane verzije skale porodičnog uticaja na izbor zanimanja i razvoj karijere u odnosu na originalnu verziju na uzorku studenata iz Srbi-je. Uzorak su činila 204 studenta (M starost = 22.24, SD starost = 2.40, Min starost = 18, Max starost = 34), od kojih su 77.5% bili ispitanici ženskog pola. Da bi se ispitala konstruktivna validnost adaptirane verzije skale, korišćena je analiza glavnih komponenti, paralelna analiza i konfirmatorna faktorska analiza. Dobijeni rezultati ukazuju na to da postoji jednak broj dimenzija koji se izdvaja u okviru originalne i adaptirane verzije skale (informacijska podrška, finansijska podrška, očekivanja od strane porodice i vrednosti/verovanja). Pored toga, rezultati idu u prilog konvergentnoj validnosti, razmatranoj preko računanja korelacija sa skalom podrške, uplitanja i nedostatka angažovanja. Ispitana je nomološka mreža adaptirane verzije skale i rezultati su uglavnom išli u prilog njenoj ekvivalenciji sa nomološkom mrežom originalne verzije skale. Interna validnost skale razmatrana je ispitivanjem međusobnih odnosa njenih mera i ti rezultati uglavnom idu u prilog pomenutoj vrsti validnosti. Ova skala je pokazala uglavnom zadovoljavajuću pouzdanost interne konzistencije na našem uzorku. Uprkos ograničenjima studije, adaptirana verzija skale može se koristiti za ispitivanje mogućeg uticaja porodice na izbor zanimanja i razvoj karijere među studentima.
Article
Full-text available
In this article, we present a tool and a method for measuring the psychological and cultural distance between societies and creating a distance scale with any population as the point of comparison. Because psychological data are dominated by samples drawn from Western, educated, industrialized, rich, and democratic (WEIRD) nations, and overwhelmingly, the United States, we focused on distance from the United States. We also present distance from China, the country with the largest population and second largest economy, which is a common cultural comparison. We applied the fixation index ( F ST ), a meaningful statistic in evolutionary theory, to the World Values Survey of cultural beliefs and behaviors. As the extreme WEIRDness of the literature begins to dissolve, our tool will become more useful for designing, planning, and justifying a wide range of comparative psychological projects. Our code and accompanying online application allow for comparisons between any two countries. Analyses of regional diversity reveal the relative homogeneity of the United States. Cultural distance predicts various psychological outcomes.
Article
Full-text available
When do people find it acceptable to sacrifice one life to save many? Cross-cultural studies suggested a complex pattern of universals and variations in the way people approach this question, but data were often based on small samples from a small number of countries outside of the Western world. Here we analyze responses to three sacrificial dilemmas by 70,000 participants in 10 languages and 42 countries. In every country, the three dilemmas displayed the same qualitative ordering of sacrifice acceptability, suggesting that this ordering is best explained by basic cognitive processes, rather than cultural norms. The quantitative acceptability of each sacrifice, though, showed substantial country-level variations. We show that low relational mobility (where people are more cautious about not alienating their current social partners) is strongly associated with the rejection of sacrifices for the greater good (especially for Eastern countries), which may be explained by the signaling value of this rejection. We make our dataset fully available as a public resource for researchers studying universals and variations in human morality: all the data and code used in this article can be downloaded at https://bit.ly/2Y7Brr9.
Article
Full-text available
With the rapid development of artificial intelligence have come concerns about how machines will make moral decisions, and the major challenge of quantifying societal expectations about the ethical principles that should guide machine behaviour. To address this challenge, we deployed the Moral Machine, an online experimental platform designed to explore the moral dilemmas faced by autonomous vehicles. This platform gathered 40 million decisions in ten languages from millions of people in 233 countries and territories. Here we describe the results of this experiment. First, we summarize global moral preferences. Second, we document individual variations in preferences, based on respondents’ demographics. Third, we report cross-cultural ethical variation, and uncover three major clusters of countries. Fourth, we show that these differences correlate with modern institutions and deep cultural traits. We discuss how these preferences can contribute to developing global, socially acceptable principles for machine ethics. All data used in this article are publicly available.
Article
Full-text available
Concerns about the veracity of psychological research have been growing. Many findings in psychological science are based on studies with insufficient statistical power and nonrepresentative samples, or may otherwise be limited to specific, ungeneralizable settings or populations. Crowdsourced research, a type of large-scale collaboration in which one or more research projects are conducted across multiple lab sites, offers a pragmatic solution to these and other current methodological challenges. The Psychological Science Accelerator (PSA) is a distributed network of laboratories designed to enable and support crowdsourced research projects. These projects can focus on novel research questions or replicate prior research in large, diverse samples. The PSA’s mission is to accelerate the accumulation of reliable and generalizable evidence in psychological science. Here, we describe the background, structure, principles, procedures, benefits, and challenges of the PSA. In contrast to other crowdsourced research networks, the PSA is ongoing (as opposed to time limited), efficient (in that structures and principles are reused for different projects), decentralized, diverse (in both subjects and researchers), and inclusive (of proposals, contributions, and other relevant input from anyone inside or outside the network). The PSA and other approaches to crowdsourced psychological science will advance understanding of mental processes and behaviors by enabling rigorous research and systematic examination of its generalizability.
Article
Full-text available
Recent research has relied on trolley-type sacrificial moral dilemmas to study utilitarian versus nonutilitarian modes of moral decision-making. This research has generated important insights into people’s attitudes toward instrumental harm—that is, the sacrifice of an individual to save a greater number. But this approach also has serious limitations. Most notably, it ignores the positive, altruistic core of utilitarianism, which is characterized by impartial concern for the well-being of everyone, whether near or far. Here, we develop, refine, and validate a new scale—the Oxford Utilitarianism Scale—to dissociate individual differences in the ‘negative’ (permissive attitude toward instrumental harm) and ‘positive’ (impartial concern for the greater good) dimensions of utilitarian thinking as manifested in the general population. We show that these are two independent dimensions of proto-utilitarian tendencies in the lay population, each exhibiting a distinct psychological profile. Empathic concern, identification with the whole of humanity, and concern for future generations were positively associated with impartial beneficence but negatively associated with instrumental harm; and although instrumental harm was associated with subclinical psychopathy, impartial beneficence was associated with higher religiosity. Importantly, although these two dimensions were independent in the lay population, they were closely associated in a sample of moral philosophers. Acknowledging this dissociation between the instrumental harm and impartial beneficence components of utilitarian thinking in ordinary people can clarify existing debates about the nature of moral psychology and its relation to moral philosophy as well as generate fruitful avenues for further research.
Article
To get evidence for or against a theory relative to the null hypothesis, one needs to know what the theory predicts. The amount of evidence can then be quantified by a Bayes factor. Specifying the sizes of the effect one’s theory predicts may not come naturally, but I show some ways of thinking about the problem, some simple heuristics that are often useful when one has little relevant prior information. These heuristics include the room-to-move heuristic (for comparing mean differences), the ratio-of-scales heuristic (for regression slopes), the ratio-of-means heuristic (for regression slopes), the basic-effect heuristic (for analysis of variance effects), and the total-effect heuristic (for mediation analysis).
Article
Researchers have used "sacrificial" trolley-type dilemmas (where harmful actions promote the greater good) to model competing influences on moral judgment: affective reactions to causing harm that motivate characteristically deontological judgments ("the ends don't justify the means") and deliberate cost-benefit reasoning that motivates characteristically utilitarian judgments ("better to save more lives"). Recently, Kahane, Everett, Earp, Farias, and Savulescu (2015) argued that sacrificial judgments reflect antisociality rather than "genuine utilitarianism," but this work employs a different definition of "utilitarian judgment." We introduce a five-level taxonomy of "utilitarian judgment" and clarify our longstanding usage, according to which judgments are "utilitarian" simply because they favor the greater good, regardless of judges' motivations or philosophical commitments. Moreover, we present seven studies revisiting Kahane and colleagues' empirical claims. Studies 1a-1b demonstrate that dilemma judgments indeed relate to utilitarian philosophy, as philosophers identifying as utilitarian/consequentialist were especially likely to endorse utilitarian sacrifices. Studies 2-6 replicate, clarify, and extend Kahane and colleagues' findings using process dissociation to independently assess deontological and utilitarian response tendencies in lay people. Using conventional analyses that treat deontological and utilitarian responses as diametric opposites, we replicate many of Kahane and colleagues' key findings. However, process dissociation reveals that antisociality predicts reduced deontological inclinations, not increased utilitarian inclinations. Critically, we provide evidence that lay people's sacrificial utilitarian judgments also reflect moral concerns about minimizing harm. This work clarifies the conceptual and empirical links between moral philosophy and moral psychology and indicates that sacrificial utilitarian judgments reflect genuine moral concern, in both philosophers and ordinary people.