ArticlePDF Available

Abstract

How can we capture the intuitive distinction between lying and misleading? According to a traditional view, the difference boils down to whether the speaker is saying (as opposed to implying) something that they believe to be false. This view is subject to known objections; to overcome them, an alternative view has emerged. For the alternative view, what matters is whether the speaker can consistently deny that they are committed to knowing the relevant proposition. We point out serious flaws for this alternative view, and sketch a simpler alternative that incorporates key insights of the traditional view.
Forthcoming in The Journal of Philosophy
1
Saying, commitment, and the lying
misleading distinction
Neri Marsili (University of Barcelona) and Guido Löhr (Eindhoven University
of Technology)
Introduction
How can we capture the intuitive distinction between lying and merely misleading?
1
According to a traditional view,
2
the difference boils down to whether the speaker
saysas opposed to merely implies – something that they believe to be false.
3
Consider
this classic example:
4
DYING WOMAN
A dying woman asks a doctor whether her son is well. The doctor saw the son
yesterday, when he was fine, but knows that he was killed shortly afterwards. The
doctor wants to spare the dying woman the news of her son’s death. She utters:
Version A: (1) He’s fine.
Version B: (2) I saw him yesterday and he was fine
In version A, the doctor lies: he says something he believes to be false, namely that
the son is fine. By contrast, in version B the doctor is merely misleading, because he
does not say that the son is fine: he says that he was fine, and merely implies that he
still is. On the basis of examples of this sort, it is often argued that the difference
between lying and misleading is grounded in the difference between saying and
merely implicating.
1
There is a debate on whether lying is always morally worse than merely misleading, but our interest
here is primarily in what the lying-misleading distinction consists in. For a general overview, see
Jennifer Saul, Lying, Misleading, & What is Said: An Exploration in Philosophy of Language and in Ethics
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012).
2
Saul, ibid; Andreas Stokke, Lying and Insincerity (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018); Jonathan
Adler Lying, Deceiving, or Falsely Implicating. Journal of Philosophy 94, 9 (1997): 43552.
3
Some would add: with the intent to deceive. Whether intended deception is required for lying is
only tangential to our discussion. In what follows, we will simply assume that in every example the
speaker has a deceptive intent, without taking a stance on whether lying requires attempted
deception. For an overview, Don Fallis. “What is Deceptive Lying?”. In Michaelson, Eliot and
Andreas Stokke, Lying. Language, Knowledge, Ethics, and Politics, 25-42. (Oxford University Press, 2018).
4
Emanuel Viebahn, “The lying-misleading distinction: a commitment-based approach”, The Journal
of Philosophy 118, 6 (2021): 289319.
SAYING, COMMITMENT, AND THE LYINGMISLEADING DISTINCTION
2
In a series of recent papers,
5
Emmanuel Viebahn has challenged this intuitive
picture, arguing that the traditional view is subject to several counterexamples, such
as the following:
TOMATOES
Ada is a keen gardener but has had an exceptionally bad crop of tomatoes.
Ada wants Bill to think that her crop was in fact great, so when she meets
Bill and he asks how her crop of tomatoes has been, she utters:
(3) I’ve got tomatoes coming out of my ears.
Implicature: I’ve had a great crop
MERCEDES
Harry wants Rosa to think that his friend John is wealthy. In fact, John is
not wealthy and does not own a car, as Harry knows very well. Harry asks
Rosa:
(4) Did you know that John owns a Mercedes?
Presupposition: John owns a Mercedes
According to Viebahn, Ada and Harry did not just mislead: they both lied since
both communicated, in a rather unequivocal way, something that they believe to be
false. Not everyone will share this intuition, but let us concede it for the sake of the
argument. If (3) and (4) are genuine lies (“non-literal lies”, as Viebahn calls them),
6
the traditional, says-based conception of the lying-misleading distinction is
inaccurate, for it incorrectly classifies them as merely misleading.
7
What, then, could ground the lying-misleading distinction? Viebahn suggests that
whether one lies depends on whether the speaker is committed to knowing the
relevant proposition. He defines lying as follows:
(VD) VIEBAHNS DEFINITION
A lies to B if and only if there is a proposition p such that:
(L1) A performs a communicative act C with p as content;
(L2) with C, A intends to communicate p to B;
(L3) with C, A commits herself to p; and
(L4) A believes that p is false.
Within this definition, it is condition L3 that is meant to play the role of
differentiating between cases of lying and cases of merely misleading. Viebahn
expounds L3 as follows:
5
Emanuel Viebahn, ibid.; “Non-literal lies,” Erkenntnis 82, 6 (2017): 13671380; “Lying with
Presuppositions,” Noûs, LIV, 3 (2020): 731751.
6
Viebahn reserves the term ‘non-literal lies’ for lies conveyed by implicature, not including
presuppositional lies. For ease of exposition, we will use ‘non-literal lies’ to refer to both.
7
Viebahn considers several other examples, suggesting that we can lie with presuppositions, irony,
loose talk, questions and perhaps even pictures. See Viebahn, “Non-literal lies”; “Lying with
Presuppositions”; “Lying with pictures.” The British Journal of Aesthetics 59, 3 (2019): 243-257.
Forthcoming in The Journal of Philosophy
3
(Comm) COMMITMENT IN LYING:
In performing a communicative act C with a proposition p as
content, a speaker A commits herself to p (in the sense relevant for
the lying-misleading distinction) iff A cannot consistently dismiss an
audience challenge in response to C to defend (or justify) that she
knows p.
8
According to this view, the reason why the doctor’s statement in version B (“I saw
him yesterday and he was fine) is merely misleading is not that the doctor has implied
(rather than said) that the son is still fine today. What matters is rather that the
doctor is not committed to the claim that the son is fine. If challenged (e.g. “Do you
know for sure that he is fine today?), the doctor may consistently dismiss the
question by replying: “I only claimed that he was good yesterday. I never claimed that
he is fine today. According to (Comm), this means that the doctor is not committed
to the relevant proposition, and so is not lying. The same cannot be said of the
doctor in Version A, who could not consistently dismiss the challenge in this way: he
is committed to p, and therefore lying (since L1, L2 and L4 are also met ex hypothesi).
Crucially, unlike traditional says-based views, VD classifies “non-literal lies” as lies.
9
Take the Tomatoes example. If we challenge Ada the farmer by asking “Did you
really have a good crop of tomatoes?”, Ada cannot consistently deny that she meant
to claim that she had a good crop. According to Viebahn, if Ada replied: “I never
said that I had a good crop, I only said that I had tomatoes coming out of my ears”,
her reply would not be consistent with her communicative commitments.
Therefore, (Comm) is satisfied, and VD classifies her utterance as a lie.
For those who want to classify non-literal lies as lies, Viebahn’s definition may seem
appealing. However, in this paper we point out some serious problems with this
proposal. We will show that, even if one accepts Viebahn’s desiderata (namely, that
a good definition should capture ‘non-literal lies’ as lies), VD still fares worse than
its predecessors when it comes to differentiating between lying and misleading. We
conclude by outlining a simpler and more promising alternative.
I. Commitment and the lying/misleading distinction
I.1 The definition is underdetermined
Viebahn’s definition is supposed to provide us with a criterion to systematically
distinguish lying from merely attempting to mislead. To achieve its intended goal,
the criterion needs to be determinate and informative: it must provide us with a clear
method to determine whether an utterance is a lie or if it is merely misleading. It is
not obvious, however, that Viebahn’s proposed view meets this basic desideratum.
8
Viebahn, “The lying-misleading distinction”, 307 (our emphasis).
9
According to Viebahn, at least we will come back to this point shortly.
SAYING, COMMITMENT, AND THE LYINGMISLEADING DISTINCTION
4
To see this, note that according to (Comm), a speaker is committed to p if she cannot
consistently dismiss a challenge to defend that she knows that p. Since commitment is
what ultimately distinguishes lying from merely misleading (condition L3 in VD),
the notion of a ‘consistent dismissal’ is central to Viebahn’s positive proposal.
Lacking a precise account of what a consistent dismissal is, VD would not meet the
basic desideratum of determinacy.
What is then “a consistent dismissal”? According to Viebahn, it is “a dismissal that
does not involve denying that one took on a justificatory responsibility one in fact
did take on, and that does not involve denying that one performed a speech act one
in fact did perform.”
10
More schematically:
(C) A dismissal is consistent iff
(i) the speaker denies having taken on a justificatory responsibility
JR, and they did not take on JR
or
(ii) the speaker denies having performed the speech act SA, and
they did not perform SA
To meet the desiderata identified above (informativeness, determinacy), (C) should
clarify under which conditions a speaker can consistently dismiss a challenge.
However, (C) only appears to do so. To know whether (i) or (ii) is true, we need to
know whether their second conjunct is true (the first conjunct may well be true ex
hypothesi). But whether the second conjunct is true is what we wanted to explain in
the first place. This may not seem obvious, so let us see why.
Whether the second conjunct of (i) is true depends on whether the speaker took on
a justificatory responsibility to defend that they know that p in other words, it
depends on whether the speaker is committed to knowing p. But (C) was supposed
to clarify under which condition the speaker is committed to knowing p. Rather than
clarifying under which conditions the speaker is committed to the proposition, (i)
presupposes that we know under which conditions the speaker is so committed.
This seems circular, and does not provide us with a clear criterion to determine
whether the speaker is committed to the proposition in the sense relevant to VD,
against our desiderata.
A similar problem arises for (ii). Whether the second conjunct of (ii) is true depends
on whether the speaker has performed the relevant speech act, namely an
assertion.
11
But whether the speaker has asserted the relevant proposition is exactly
what (C) was meant to establish: condition (C) is meant to rule out utterances that
10
“The lying-misleading distinction”, 305 (fn 43).
11
Viebahn specifies that “the notion of commitment in [VD] is to be understood as the commitment
in assertion”, so that only by denying that you have asserted the proposition you can show that you
are not committed (in the relevant sense) to the proposition. (Viebahn, “The lying-misleading
distinction”, 307, cf. also example (16) at p. 305).
Forthcoming in The Journal of Philosophy
5
are not assertions, and therefore not lies.
12
Since also here the explanans figures in
the explanandum, the worry of circularity extends to (ii) too. Plugging (C) into L3
would not give us a systematic criterion to determine whether the speaker is lying
or misleading, against our desiderata.
Perhaps Viebahn’s definition can be amended to avoid these worries. Condition (i)
may be made more determinate by pairing it with an independent criterion to
determine if the speaker is indeed committed to respond to adequate challenges,
such as the ones defended in the relevant literature by Brandom, MacFarlane, and
like-minded authors.
13
But this would not help much, because (C) is disjunctive: it
requires that either (i) or (ii) is satisfied. As long as a disjunct (namely, ii) is
underdeterminate, the resulting definition also is. One could drop (ii) to avoid this,
but this would leave us with little of Viebahn’s original proposal.
All this supports the initial suspicion that (as it is presented) VD is underdetermined:
it does not offer, alone, a systematic criterion to differentiate lies from misleading
utterances. This is not an insurmountable problem: with substantive amendments,
(C) could be made more determinate. As we are about to see, however, these
revisions would not lead very far: VD is subject to a wide array of counterexamples,
which undermine the very rationale that motivates Viebahn’s proposal.
I.2 The definition is too broad
A known objection to commitment accounts of assertion is that they rule in asserted
propositions that are merely presupposed, or that are logically entailed, by what the
speaker said.
14
Usually, this problem is solved by requiring that the speaker says what
they assert.
15
This solution is not available to Viebahn, who wants his definition to
rule in non-literal lies. By allowing presuppositions to count as lies, VD can
accommodate the intuition that Harry’s question (4) is a presuppositional lie (and not
merely misleading).
But there are less desirable side-effects of abandoning the requirement that the
12
Viebahn, ibid.
13
See, for example, Brandom, Robert. Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive
Commitment. (Harvard University Press, 1994), MacFarlane, John. Epistemic Modalities and Relative
Truth(2003), Shapiro, Lionel. Commitment Accounts of Assertion. In The Oxford Handbook of
Assertion (Oxford University Press, 2020), 7397, and Marsili, Neri, “The Definition of Assertion”
(2020). Available at SSRN. DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3711804. Of course, this revision spoils Viebahn’s
proposal of much of its originality. Insofar as VD is meant to move beyond these views, this solution
seems unsatisfying.
14
Mitchel Green, “Assertions”. In: Sbisà, Marina, and Ken Turner (eds.) Pragmatics of Speech Actions,
Vol. II of the Handbook of Pragmatics (2013); Neri Marsili, “Normative Accounts of Assertion:
From Peirce to Williamson, and Back Again.” Rivista Italiana Di Filosofia Del Linguaggio, 11230
(2015). Matthew Cull, “When Alston Met Brandom: Defining Assertion.” Rivista Italiana Di Filosofia
Del Linguaggio 13: 3650 (2019).
15
For some complications that may nonetheless persist, see Cull, ibid.
SAYING, COMMITMENT, AND THE LYINGMISLEADING DISTINCTION
6
speaker says something. One is that now nothing prevents logically entailed
propositions from being classified as lies. To illustrate, imagine that Rodrigo tells
Anastasia that “P”, and that (later in the same conversation) he also says that
“P->Q”. Rodrigo is now committed to Q too, because what he said so far entails
Q.
16
But Rodrigo has not asserted that Q, and therefore (even if he believes Q to be
false), he cannot possibly have lied by undertaking a commitment to Q. Viebahn’s
account incorrectly predicts that Rodrigo could lie by undertaking a commitment to
Q, since VD does not require that lies must be said.
17
Illustrating how Q meets the conditions set by VD may help clarify this point.
Rodrigo believes that Q is false ex hypothesi, and we already saw that he is committed
to Q, so conditions (L3) and (L4) are met. A speaker who claims that “P” and that
“P->Q” may in principle perform the latter speech act with the intention to
communicate that Q is true, so L2 can also be met.
18
As for (L1), we need to keep
in mind that Viebahn interprets it very leniently, since he wants to untangle lying
from what is said. He specifies that for (L1) “it does not matter how the content is
introduced”
19
in the conversation – as long as it is introduced by a communicative
act. In our example, the proposition is introduced by a communicative act
(Rodrigo’s second statement). Hence, also (L1) is met. The result is that VD
incorrectly counts Q as a lie.
In response, it could be suggested that a narrower understanding of L1 (or L2) is all
we need to rule out these counterexamples.
20
But it is at least doubtful that this kind
of revision will do the trick. Presuppositions and logical entailments are connected
linguistic phenomena (for example, factive verbs both presuppose and logically entail
that what falls under their scope is true), so that any solution that rules out logical
entailments threatens to rule out also presuppositional lies. This is not necessarily
16
Green, “Assertions”, section 3; Marsili “Normative accounts of Assertion”, p.117; Cull “When
Alston met Brandom”, p.37.
17
This requirement is included (and the worry avoided) by other commitment-based accounts of
lying; see, for example, Marsili. Lying, Speech Acts, and Commitment. Synthese, 2020.
18
Note that Viebahn interprets this constraint quite loosely, and allows that an “intention to put p
forward as information” is sufficient for (L2) to be met. See The Lying-Misleading Distinction, p. 301.
19
Viebahn, Ibid.
20
A referee notes that VD only specifies under which conditions “A lies to B”, and takes no stance
concerning which proposition A is lying about. Presumably, Rodrigo has lied about some proposition:
since he believes “Q” false, he should believe that either “P” or “P->Q” is false; uttering one of
them, he lied. VD’s verdict that Rodrigo lied is then correct. While this is a charitable interpretation,
we worry that it proves too much. Presumably, a good definition should be able to identify when (and
how many times) a speaker has lied in a given temporal slice. If I lied at t1 but not at t2, a definition
that predicts that I lied in both occasions makes an indisputably incorrect prediction. Now, suppose
that Rodrigo believes that P is false and that P->Q is true. When Rodrigo asserts P at t1, he lies.
Later in the conversation he may utter some other lies, and some other truths. Crucially, however,
when at t2 he asserts P->Q, he is not lying. But VD would have it that he lied once again. If we are
right that a good definition should be able to determine at which stage of a conversation a speaker
lied, VD is still in trouble.
Forthcoming in The Journal of Philosophy
7
an unsolvable problem, but it is another tough challenge for Viebahn’s view one
that is not faced by saying-based accounts.
I.3 The definition is too narrow
Viebahn’s definition is also too narrow. A first reason is that speakers are rarely
expected to show that they know what they assert, as required by (Comm).
21
Commitment accounts are usually phrased in terms of a commitment to the truth of
a proposition, rather than knowledge of the proposition.
22
There is a reason for this.
Exceptions aside, conversations aim to settle whether something is the case, not
whether each speaker knows that what they said is true.
To illustrate, imagine that Amadeus asserts that snakes are ovoviviparous, and Barbie
responds that she agrees. Since Barbie agreed that snakes are ovoviviparous, it would
be odd
23
for her to proceed to press Amadeus with further questions, and demand
that Amadeus now demonstrates that he knows (and not merely believes truly) that
snakes are ovoviviparous. If Barbie demanded that Amadeus prove that he knows
that snakes are ovoviviparous right after agreeing with him that they are, Barbie
would be overstepping, and her conversational move would be perceived as odd.
This suggests that making an assertion does not automatically commit you to
demonstrate (if challenged) that you know that what you asserted is true.
24
More generally, it seems that (exceptions aside) challenges are only available to the
audience until it is agreed that p is true in the conversation. If this is right, the
recipient of an assertoric claim has no pro tanto entitlement to demand proof that the
speaker knows that what they said is true. Viebahn’s view then faces a difficulty: it
classifies virtually nothing as a lie, since only in exceptional cases (for example, oral
exams, high stakes scenarios) assertors are committed to also show that they know
that what they asserted is true. This, in turn, means that we are rarely committed to
21
As a reminder: “a speaker A commits herself to p […] iff A cannot consistently dismiss an
audience challenge in response to C to defend (or justify) that she knows p” (The Lying-misleading
Distinction”, 307, our emphasis).
22
Searle, Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language; Alston, William P. Illocutionary Acts and
Sentence Meaning (Cornell University Press, 2000); MacFarlane, John. “What Is Assertion?” In
Assertion: New Philosophical Essays (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011); Marsili, “The Definition
of Assertion”.
23
There are some circumstances in which Barbie’s reply may not be odd. If Barbie is a teacher
interrogating a student, or if Barbie’s life depends on settling whether snakes are ovoviviparous, it
may be appropriate for her to press Amadeus further. We are not denying here that in some contexts
the justificatory burden can be more demanding. We are only arguing that the default justificatory
burden falls short of having to prove that one knows the proposition one asserts, and that this
generates problems for VD.
24
To acknowledge this rather straightforward point is not to argue against the influential (but
controversial) hypothesis that knowledge is the norm of assertion. Proponents of this view claim
that only known assertions are appropriate, but need not accept the stronger thesis (advocated by
Viebahn) that, at any point in a conversation, assertors are expected to demonstrate that they know
what they say, if challenged to do so
SAYING, COMMITMENT, AND THE LYINGMISLEADING DISTINCTION
8
any proposition in the sense required by (Comm) – so that very few utterances are
classified as lies by VD.
Perhaps one can bite the bullet here, and argue that (despite appearances) speakers
are indeed committed to demonstrate that they know what they assert if challenged.
Alternatively, one could revise the definition by decoupling the notion of
commitment from knowledge. But this difficulty sums up to the ones identified
above: the inability to rule out logical entailments, and the more daunting worry of
underdetermination. Vibeahn’s proposed alternative to says-based definitions
comes at a significant cost.
II. A middle ground: commitment to inflated Gricean saying
Is there a better way to define lying? To answer the question, let us quickly
recapitulate the desiderata set by Viebahn. In addition to capturing all standard cases
of (literal) lying, a good definition should:
(D1) Rule in deceptive substitutional implicatures
(D2) Rule out additive (non-substitutional) implicatures
(D3) Rule in presuppositional lies
(D1) and (D2) invoke a distinction between substitutional and additive implicatures.
While in additive implicatures the speaker communicates something in addition to
what they literally say, in substitutional implicatures the speaker cannot be
interpreted as intending to communicate what they literally say – so that they must
be taken to communicate the implicated content instead of the literal one.
25
In Version B of Dying Woman, for example, the doctor intends to communicate that
the son is still fine in addition to what he literally said (namely, that the son is fine).
This is an additive implicature. In Tomatoes, Ada does not intend (and could not
rationally intend) to communicate what she literally said – namely, that tomatoes are
coming out of her ears. She only aims to communicate that she has a good crop.
Here the implicated content ‘replaces’ what Ada has literally said: it is a substitutional
implicature.
About these examples, Grice
26
would say that while the doctor says that he saw the
25
In passing, Viebahn suggests that perhaps some additive implicatures can be lies, but never specifies
which implicatures he has in mind. Lacking a more precise qualification, we shall accept (D2). A
qualified version of (D2) like “Rule out some additive implicatures” would be too indeterminate to
guide our inquiry, and exploring which definition could meet (D2) is interesting regardless of
Viebahn’s opinions on the lying/misleading distinction. For more on the distinction see Jörg
Meibauer, “Implicature,” in Jacob L. Mey, ed., Concise Encyclopedia of Pragmatics (Elsevier, 2009), 365
78, or Alexander Dinges, “Innocent Implicatures,” Journal of Pragmatics, lvii (2015): 5463.
26
While we take on a Gricean insight here, we not thereby subscribing to a Gricean theory of what
‘meaning’ requires, or what an assertion is. We would prefer to steer clear of Gricean R-intentions
Forthcoming in The Journal of Philosophy
9
patient, Ada only ‘makes it as if to say’ that she has tomatoes coming out of her ears.
Grice’s terminology (‘makes it as if to say’) highlights an intuitive point: that in
substitutional implicatures, the speaker cannot rationally be regarded as intending to
communicate what they literally said (for example, that one has tomatoes coming
out of one’s ears). This leaves whoever attempts to interpret the utterance with a
‘blank’ or a ‘vacuum’ that needs to be filled: unless the speaker is trying to
communicate something other than what they literally said, it is not possible to make
sense of their communicative act. The implicature (I had a good crop) comes in to fill
that communicative vacuum, ‘substituting’ the literal message. Not so for additive
implicature. In the additive cases, the implicature conveys additional information that
complements the speaker’s primary message, rather than substituting it.
These remarks suggest a simple way to draw the distinctions required by D1 and
D2. Let us introduce the term ‘inflated saying’ to refer to either what the speaker
said, or whatever comes in to fill the blank when the speaker only makes it as if to say
something (that is, the substitutional implicature). By plugging this notion of
‘inflated saying’ into a standard says-based account of the lying/misleading
distinction, we will get all the right predictions about D1 and D2. We can then define
lying as follows, where says* stands for our notion of inflated saying, and asserts*
stands for one’s favorite ‘assertion-condition’
27
for lying:
Inflated lying:
S lies iff
(a) S says* that p
(b) S does not believe that p
(c) S asserts* that p
This definition is able to capture substitutional implicatures like Tomato, since Ada
says* that she had a good crop, in the inflated sense of ‘saying’. And it rules out
misleading implicatures, like the doctor’s statement in version 2, since the
implicature that the patient is fine today is conveyed in addition to what the doctor
literally says, not instead of it.
What about presuppositions? Like additive implicatures, presuppositions convey
specifically, because incorporating them in the definition would introduce an intention to deceive of
some kind (see Jörg Meibauer, “Lying and Falsely Implicating.” Journal of Pragmatics 37, 9 (2005):
137399), whereas we would like to remain neutral here as to whether lying requires attempted
deception.
27
For instance, “S intends to warrant that p” “S represents herself as believing p”, “S proposes p to
become common ground”, or “S commits herself to p” These views are defended, respectively, by:
Thomas L. Carson, The Definition of Lying. Noûs 2 (2006): 284306; Fallis, Davidson Was
Almost Right About Lying. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91, 2 (2013): 33753; Stokke, Lying and
Insincerity; Marsili, Lying, Speech Acts, and Commitment. Condition (b) may itself be in need of
some revisions, as noted in Neri Marsili, “Lying by Promising: a Study on Insincere Illocutionary
Acts”, International Review of Pragmatics, 8, 2 (2016): 271-313, and Marsili, “Lying and Certainty,” in
Jörg Meibauer, The Oxford Handbook of Lying, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018), pp. 170-182,
SAYING, COMMITMENT, AND THE LYINGMISLEADING DISTINCTION
10
information in addition to what the speaker literally says. But unlike additive
implicatures, this additional layer of meaning is presupposed, not implied. If one
thinks that also presuppositions should be classified as lies, the definition could be
broadened further, by substituting (a) with (a’)
(a) S says* or presupposes that p
Here (a’) involves a disjunction, and the familiar worry about introducing
disjunctions in definitions is that the resulting definition may be conflating two
distinct phenomena into one.
28
In reply, we note that it is indeed plausible that the
disjunction here tracks a different layer of meaning (presupposed, rather than said)
and a different kind of lying (‘backdoor lying’, as Langton
29
calls it). If we are indeed
dealing with two communicative phenomena that fall under the same label (‘lying’)
in ordinary language, using a disjunction to capture both phenomena is
unproblematic.
Note, further, that Viebahn’s account equally relies on disjunctions (to define
consistent denials in C). Crucially, however, every other weakness of VD is avoided
here. The worry about underdetermination does not arise;
30
there is no risk of
incorrectly ruling in logical entailments (cf. §2.2); and there is no risk of incorrectly
ruling out most assertions (because of the problematic connection drawn between
commitment and knowledge, cf. §2.3).
L-M is offered as a solution to meet the desiderata set by Viebahn. As such, it is a
conditional proposal: if one accepts D1-3, L-M is a promising view. But if one rejects
them, a different view will be needed. Perhaps, then, a few words can be spent to
say how plausible these desiderata are.
We think that it is important to acknowledge that our intuitions about the
lying/misleading distinction are not all that convergent. Philosophers notoriously
disagree about particular cases. And from recent empirical studies, it emerges that
also laypeople often have diverging intuitions about the lying/misleading
distinction.
31
Given the widespread disagreement about what a definition should classify as lies,
28
Kingsbury, Justine, and Jonathan McKeown-Green. “Definitions: Does Disjunction Mean
Dysfunction?” Journal of Philosophy, 2009.
29
Langton, Rae. “Lies and Back-Door Lies (Book Review).” Mind, 2020.
30
As long as an account of assertion is plugged into (c), which is what we require.
31
Specifically, in these studies only insincere assertions and presuppositional lies are confidently and
consistently classified as lies. Lie-ratings for particularized implicatures are often around the
midpoint. See Viebahn, Emanuel, Alex Wiegmann, Neele Engelmann, y Pascale Willemsen. Can a
question be a lie? An empirical investigation. Ergo (forthcoming), Reins, Louisa M. & Wiegmann,
Alex. “Is Lying Bound to Commitment? Empirically Investigating Deceptive Presuppositions,
Implicatures, and Actions”. Cognitive Science 45, 2 (2021); Meibauer, Jörg; Alex; Wiegmann, y Pascale
Willemsen. forthcoming. Lying, Deceptive Implicatures, and Commitment. Ergo, forthcoming.
Forthcoming in The Journal of Philosophy
11
it would be wrong-headed to insist that one set of desiderata is definitely preferable
to another. If (as most scholars assume) a definition of lying is meant to track our
ordinary-language intuitions, a good definition should acknowledge that some cases
of lying are less straightforward than others – rather than postulating a sharp
boundary between lying and misleading, as most contemporary accounts do.
32
How could a definition accommodate the intuition that the distinction between lying
and misleading is graded? Answering this question goes beyond the ambitions of
this paper.
33
Our point here is merely that (D1-3) may fall short of identifying the
complex set of desiderata that a good definition should meet. For our purposes, we
rest content with having established the following: that Viebahn’s own account fails
to meet the desiderata he set for a definition of lying, and that a revised ‘says-based’
approach can succeed where Viebahn has failed, simply by broadening what one
means by ‘saying’.
32
See, for instance, Saul, “Lying and Misleading”, p.66; Stokke, Lying and Insincerity, chapter 5, and
Viebahn’s own VD.
33
This much can be said, however: plausibly, developing such a view will require relaxing condition
(i), replacing it with a condition that can be met to a higher or lesser degree.
... (3-M) My history professor told me that (3-F) Napoleon had never been trained to be an artillery officer 21 As argued in recent work, this distinction is not quite the same as the distinction between what is said and what is implicated (cf. Marsili & Löhr, 2022;Pepp, 2022;Timmermann & Viebahn, 2020;Viebahn, 2017Viebahn, , 2021. 22 By "felicitous" denial I mean one that does not misfire. ...
... For an overview,Mahon (2015). For discussion of some complications regarding the requirement that the speaker has to believe that what they say is false, seeMarsili ( , 2016Marsili ( , 2018; for some reservations about the idea that the speaker must make an explicit statement, seeViebahn (2017Viebahn ( , 2021, but cf.Marsili and Löhr (2022) andPepp (2022) for a reply. 2 I am using 'falsities' for ease of exposition here, but technically we are dealing with 'believed-falsities': it isn't the literal of a joke or a metaphor that creates a problem for Lying-Nec, but rather the fact that they are believed to be false by the speaker. 3 Different authors phrase this condition in slightly different ways. ...
Article
Full-text available
Can fictions lie? According to a classic conception, works of fiction can never contain lies, since their content is not presented as true, nor is it meant to deceive us. But this classic view can be challenged. Sometimes fictions appear to make claims about the actual world, and these claims can be designed to convey falsehoods, historical misconceptions, and even pernicious stereotypes. Should we conclude that some fictional statements are lies? This article introduces two views that support a positive answer, and two that support a negative one. After examining various ways in which fictions can deceive, it concludes in favour of the view that fictional statements can mislead, but never lie.
... While I have no space to discuss this complication here, I am confident that PAC can deal with this difficulty (either by applying existing accounts of semantic underdetermination, or by loosening condition (a3), or both). 24 To rule in "non-literal lies" (Viebahn 2017; Reins and Wiegmann 2021), condition (a-i) could be expanded along the lines proposed by Marsili and Löhr (2022). Idem for non-literal assertions. ...
... This is just what our definition of group lying requires, once we replace Lackey's PA (which doesn't fulfil this requirement), with PAC (which requires that the speaker literally assert a proposition). This solution matches a growing number of accounts of individual lying that drop the intention to deceive condition in favour of a commitment-based assertion condition (Marsili 2014;2020a;2021b;Leland 2015;Viebahn 2017;2021;Marsili and Löhr 2022, cf. also Carson 2006Saul 2012). Of course, the insincerity condition (G-INSINCERE) will play a crucial role in the resulting definition of group lying (it will have to discriminate, alone, between lies and sincere assertions). ...
Article
Full-text available
Groups, like individuals, can communicate. They can issue statements, make promises, give advice. Sometimes, in doing so, they lie and deceive. The goal of this paper is to offer a precise characterisation of what it means for a group to make an assertion and to lie. I begin by showing that Lackey's influential account of group assertion is unable to distinguish assertions from other speech acts, explicit statements from implicatures, and lying from misleading. I propose an alternative view, according to which a group asserts a proposition only if it explicitly presents that proposition as true, thereby committing to its truth. This proposal is then put to work to define group lying. While scholars typically assume that group lying requires (i) a deceptive intent and (ii) a belief in the falsity of the asserted proposition, I offer a definition that drops condition (i) and significantly broadens condition (ii).
... Our story is made in a different context to mitigate such a critique. 13 For a critique of Viebahn's view, see e.g., Marsili and Löhr (2022), and Pepp (2022). However, some commitment-based definitions of lying may be able to accommodate the cases. ...
Article
Full-text available
The widely accepted view states that an intention to deceive is not necessary for lying. Proponents of this view, the so-called non-deceptionists, argue that lies are simply insincere assertions. We conducted three experimental studies with false explanations, the results of which put some pressure on non-deceptionist analyses. We present cases of explanations that one knows are false and compare them with analogical explanations that differ only in having a deceptive intention. The results show that lay people distinguish between such false explanations and to a higher degree classify as lies those explanations that are made with the intention to deceive. Non-deceptionists fail to distinguish between such cases and wrongly classify both as lies. This novel empirical finding indicates the need for supplementing non-deceptionist definitions of lying, at least in some cases, with an additional condition, such as an intention to deceive.
Article
Full-text available
Our concern in this paper is with definitions that are not conjunctive. In particular, our concern is with definitions of things of a kind K which allege that there is a bunch of conditions, each of which is sufficient, but not necessary, for bestowing K-hood. Definitions of this kind, call them “disjunctive,” are often proposed for kinds of things that interest us, but they usually draw fairly muted applause. Many treat them as provisional, to be endured, rather than celebrated. Surely, it is thought, they do not provide all one might want from a definition. Because of water, art and other cases which apparently problematise the boundary between practice-mandated and theoretically-posited kinds, there will doubtless continue to be disagreements about the credentials of disjunctive definitions. Even so, we think we have gone some way towards offering a reasonable justification for the on-going debates and some apparatus for formulating the issues. This is an author’s accepted version of an article published in the Journal of philosophy.
Lies and Back-Door Lies (Book Review)
  • Rae Langton
Langton, Rae. "Lies and Back-Door Lies (Book Review)." Mind, 2020.