ArticlePDF Available

A preliminary framework for understanding the governance of novel environmental technologies: Ambiguity, indeterminateness and drift

Authors:
  • ICFG | Perspectives Climate Research

Abstract

We propose a conceptual framework to explain why some technologies are more difficult to govern than others in global environmental governance. We start from the observation that some technologies pose transboundary environmental risks, some provide capacities for managing such risks, and some do both. For “ambiguous” technologies, potential risks and risk management capacities are uncertain, unknown or even unknowable. Governance systems are indeterminate towards ambiguous technologies, as existing norms, rules, scripts and routines do not imply default solutions under institutional focal points. Indeterminateness can lead to institutional drift, with risks accordingly remaining unmitigated and risk management capacities remaining unexploited. We use the cases of solar geoengineering, gene drive systems and bioinformatics for illustrating this framework. As technological ambiguity may often be irresolvable, we conclude that it might force us to confront the limits to anticipatory global decision-making on matters of long-term environmental sustainability.
Earth System Governance 12 (2022) 100134
Available online 15 February 2022
2589-8116/© 2022 The Authors. Published by Elsevier B.V. This is an open access article under the CC BY-NC-ND license
(http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/).
A preliminary framework for understanding the governance of novel
environmental technologies: Ambiguity, indeterminateness and drift
Florian Rabitz
a
, Marian Feist
b
, Matthias Honegger
c
, Joshua Horton
d
, Sikina Jinnah
e
,
*
,
Jesse Reynolds
f
a
Kaunas University of Technology, Kaunas, Lithuania
b
University of Cologne, Cologne, Germany
c
Perspectives Climate Research, gGmbH, Freiburg i.B., Germany and Utrecht University, Utrecht, the Netherlands
d
Harvard University, Cambridge, MA, USA
e
University of California, Santa Cruz, USA
f
University of California, Los Angeles, USA
ARTICLE INFO
Keywords
Institutions
Technology
Adaptation
Anticipation
ABSTRACT
We propose a conceptual framework to explain why some technologies are more difcult to govern than others in
global environmental governance. We start from the observation that some technologies pose transboundary
environmental risks, some provide capacities for managing such risks, and some do both. For ambiguous
technologies, potential risks and risk management capacities are uncertain, unknown or even unknowable.
Governance systems are indeterminate towards ambiguous technologies, as existing norms, rules, scripts and
routines do not imply default solutions under institutional focal points. Indeterminateness can lead to institu-
tional drift, with risks accordingly remaining unmitigated and risk management capacities remaining unex-
ploited. We use the cases of solar geoengineering, gene drive systems and bioinformatics for illustrating this
framework. As technological ambiguity may often be irresolvable, we conclude that it might force us to confront
the limits to anticipatory global decision-making on matters of long-term environmental sustainability.
1. Introduction
Technology is central to Global Environmental Governance (GEG).
Some technologies are sources of transboundary environmental or socio-
ecological risks, for instance cross-border pollution from chemical
manufacturing. Other technologies provide capacities for managing
such risks, for instance solar power or Carbon Capture and Storage
mitigating harmful impacts from climate change. Starting from this
distinction, we ask why some novel technologies appear inherently more
difcult to govern than others? Why are some technologies contested,
disputed and subject to years of deliberations, consultations, and in-
ternational negotiations that may yield little more than least-common-
denominator outcomes, whereas others appear to unproblematically
t into existing governance frameworks?
We develop a theoretical framework that is broadly situated in
cooperation theory (whereby states cooperate on novel technologies to
realize gains or to avoid losses) and utilize a problem-structural lens
(whereby the attributes of a given technology shape the associated
collective action problems and interact with other relevant factors such
as interests or norms; Jinnah et al., 2021). Novel technologies vary on a
spectrum of ambiguity from ambiguous to unambiguous (Rotolo et al.,
2015). Unambiguous technologies tend either to pose transboundary
risks or provide capacities for managing such risks. This facilitates
governance responses: for the former type, the default solution is risk
assessment and management in order to reduce or avoid transboundary
harm. For the latter, it is to facilitate technological development,
deployment or diffusion as a global public good. Conversely, ambiguous
technologies pose some risks and provide some management capacity,
although the extent to which they do so is unclear. Accordingly, they
cannot easily be classied as either a problem or a solution. Ambiguity
can result from scientic uncertainty as well as divergent stakeholder
norms and perceptions. Ambiguous technologies do not have an obvious
institutional solution but instead lead to governance indeterminateness,
with existing norms, rules, scripts and routines failing to provide clear
* Corresponding author.
E-mail addresses: Florian.rabitz@ktu.lt (F. Rabitz), m.feist@uni-koeln.de (M. Feist), Honegger@perspectives.cc (M. Honegger), Horton@seas.harvard.edu
(J. Horton), sjinnah@ucsc.edu (S. Jinnah), jessreyn@gmail.com (J. Reynolds).
Contents lists available at ScienceDirect
Earth System Governance
journal homepage: www.sciencedirect.com/journal/earth-system-governance
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.esg.2022.100134
Received 22 October 2021; Received in revised form 31 January 2022; Accepted 1 February 2022
Earth System Governance 12 (2022) 100134
2
answers to the regulatory challenge. Failing to resolve this indetermi-
nateness results in institutional drift: the [n]eglect of institutional
maintenance in spite of external change,which results in slippage in
institutional practice on the ground(Streeck and Thelen 2005: 31). In
other words: the indeterminateness of governance systems towards
ambiguous technologies drives political inaction and negligence. We
propose that this framework is sufciently exible and open-ended to be
compatible with a variety of larger theoretical perspectives in Interna-
tional Relations. We rst develop its different conceptual elements and
subsequently highlight its explanatory power for three major instances
of ambiguous technologies in GEG. We conclude with some consider-
ations on the implications of ambiguity for GEG as well as for cooper-
ation theory more broadly.
2. Novel technologies and governance responses
Novel technologies can present sources of transboundary risks and/
or provide capacities for the management of such risks. Transboundary
risks entail environmental harm as well as adverse socio-ecological
impacts that result from novel technologies either creating novel types
of inequity or reinforcing existing ones. We choose the term risks to
denote that such negative effects are probabilistic rather than deter-
ministic. Risk management capacities are technology-based or
technology-supported ways for assessing, managing or eliminating risks.
Such capacities can serve to reduce the environmental footprint of
human societies or assist them in adapting to harmful environmental
changes, regardless of whether these have anthropogenic or natural
origins. The purpose of relevant international institutions varies
depending on whether a given technology is a source of transboundary
risk or whether it offers risk management capacity. For the former
category, this purpose is to avoid or reduce adverse transboundary ef-
fects, with institutional design typically having to account for negative
externalities and upstream-downstream problems (Mitchell and Keil-
bach 2001). For the latter category, the purpose of international in-
stitutions is to supply risk management capacities as a global public
good, which can entail either the technology itself or its effects (such as
the global benets from domestic renewable energy sources). The sup-
ply of global public goods faces various specic governance challenges
that notably differ from those associated with the avoidance or reduc-
tion of adverse transboundary effects (Barrett 2007, National Academic
of ScienceEngineering and Medicine, 2021). Novel technologies that
constitute sources of risk require different governance approaches than
novel technologies that offer risk management capacities; these ap-
proaches are not substitutable. In other words, institutional design must
be t for purpose. We note that international institutions can provide
various other functions in regards to novel technologies, for instance
regarding monitoring, enforcement or nancial and technical assistance.
However, we consider such functions as secondary, in the sense that they
support the primary institutional functions of realizing gains or averting
losses.
3. Ambiguity, indeterminateness and drift
Governance systems thus generally address technological risks from
the perspective of reducing or avoiding transboundary harm and tech-
nological risk management capacities from the perspective of global
public goods. The boundary between the two categories is often fuzzy,
meaning that some technologies will predominantly fall into one cate-
gory yet partially also into the other. Wind power, for instance, provides
risk management capacities in terms of avoiding climate change, yet also
poses some limited risks for some migratory species of birds. Solar power
similarly has strong public goods characteristics in combination with
some limited risks in its supply chain. Conversely, coal power technol-
ogy and associated carbon dioxide emissions have some very limited
benecial effects (e.g. possibly on plant growth) although their harmful
impacts are obviously incomparably greater.
Some technologies, in other words, predominantly constitute sources
of risk or predominantly provide risk management capacities. These
technologies are unambiguous in the sense that they have obvious
governance implications. This greatly simplies political responses.
Once certain ozone-depleting substances were found to cause signicant
transboundary harm that far outweighed their limited economic utility,
the international institutional response amounted to a comprehensive
global phase-out of production and consumption (differences across
substances and in country-specic obligations notwithstanding; Parson
2003). This is not to trivialize the challenge of effective international
cooperation on such and other matters of transnational harm. In cases
like this, institutional responses might still be hampered by problems of
collective action and the distributional implications of regulation. The
same applies to international cooperation for ensuring that the benets
associated with a technology which primarily provides risk management
capacities will be supplied as a public good. Yet in these cases, the
overall objectives of existing governance frameworks are relatively
straightforward: while governments and other stakeholders might
disagree on operational details, international institutions reect the
fundamental normative consensus that, in principle, transboundary
harm should be reduced or avoided and public goods should be pro-
moted for the benet of the global community.
Yet there are other technologies that present uncertain, unknown or
even unknowable mixtures of these two factors: they may have some
public good characteristics and may cause some harm, yet the balance
between the two cannot readily be discerned. Such technologies are
ambiguous in the sense that it is unclear whether they should be
considered as a problem or as a solution. This ambiguity results from two
interlinked factors. First, novel technologies can come with signicant
scientic uncertainties regarding their costs, benets, risks, feasibility,
scalability and so forth. Such uncertainty is in part an unavoidable fact
of life (Jasanoff 2007) yet can increase to the point where the relative
benets of different international regulatory choices become difcult to
ascertain (Dimitrov 2003). Second, ambiguity may also result from
differences in norms and perceptions. Differences in risk tolerance, so-
cial discount rates or social values can lead to differences in how states
evaluate the relative benets and drawbacks of a given technology.
Some states might perceive a novel technology as a game changer
whereas others hold a more cautious attitude. Perceptions will also
differ when technological impacts are likely to be asymmetrical, for
instance when some states are prone to face relatively large risk or
expect relatively large benets from technological risk management
capacities.
The lack of an obvious and default way of responding to these
ambiguous technologies implies governance indeterminateness: existing
norms do not clearly dene relevant standards of appropriate behavior;
transaction costs impede identifying ways of applying or adjusting
existing operational rules to enable cooperative gains; or decision-
makers lack behavioral scripts and cognitive routines for rapidly pro-
cessing the technological challenge and devising an adequate course of
action. Differences in the larger ontological and epistemological outlook
imply differences in how we understand the specic causes of indeter-
minateness. However, its mere existence as a relational property of
governance systems, in regards to an ambiguous technology, appears
consistent with a wide range of theoretical approaches in International
Relations. Regardless of how we conceive of its causes, the consequence
of indeterminateness is to complicate governance responses as a result of
divergent technology assessments, a lack of agreed default solutions as
well as the risk of regulatory mismatch from unknowingly choosing a
governance approach that later turns out to be inconsistent with the
technology in question. Indeterminateness can thus lead to a situation of
institutional drift, that is, the failure of institutions to adapt to important
changes in their respective functional domains (Streeck and Thelen
2005; Rabitz 2019a). As above, the link connecting indeterminateness to
drift can be approached from different theoretical vantage points. A
rationalist perspective, for instance, might emphasize how governments
F. Rabitz et al.
Earth System Governance 12 (2022) 100134
3
with vested interests in the status quo may use indeterminateness as a
pretext for inaction until improved scientic knowledge will supposedly
enable meaningful regulatory choices at an undened point in the
(distant) future (Helm 1998). Sociological accounts might emphasize
how indeterminateness obscures the normative implications of inter-
national rules and thus prevents consensus on desirable behavioral re-
sponses from emerging. We suggest that the explanatory power of our
framework is independent from such larger questions and, in the
following three sections, briey show how it sheds light on the gover-
nance challenges of three major instances of ambiguous technology in
GEG.
4. Solar geoengineering
Solar geoengineering (sometimes called solar radiation modica-
tion), principally through the injection of aerosols into the stratosphere,
is a proposed method for reducing climate change and the associated
risks through the partial reection of incoming solar energy (Reynolds
2019). A global solar geoengineering program via stratospheric aerosol
injection seems to require a fraction of the costs associated with climate
impacts (Barrett 2008), and its benecial temperature effects would also
manifest quickly. While there is close to zero commercial interest in the
technology, a variety of modelling exercises highlight its apparent
technical feasibility and efcacy for partially limiting the global rise in
temperatures and thereby contributing to sustainable development.
These potential benets co-exist with signicant potential risks,
including the chance of environmental harm (by damaging the ozone
layer or by disrupting regional precipitation patterns) and
socio-environmental challenges that are being discussed under labels
such as moral hazard, slippery slopesor the termination problem,
among others. While a detailed discussion is well beyond the scope of
this paper, the magnitude, or in some cases even the very existence, of all
these risks and opportunities is a matter of substantial dispute (Reynolds
2021). Solar geoengineering is thus an ambiguous technology.
This ambiguity translates into governance indeterminateness. Again,
cutting short a voluminous literature, there is no obvious focal point
providing default rules, procedures, scripts and heuristics for resolving
the issue in its entirety. For instance, it remains unclear whether solar
geoengineering would, or should, constitute an essential tool for
achieving the temperature targets of the 2015 Paris Agreement on
climate change; whether it would have negative impacts on global
biodiversity goals or whether it might rather serve to protect biodiver-
sity from climate impacts (McDonald et al., 2019); or the extent to which
research and deployment would, or should, be subject to the precau-
tionary principle, considering both the risks of the technology itself and
the risks which the technology is intended to manage (Reynolds 2019).
Despite a plethora of proposals for how governance could be constructed
for this issue (e.g. Chhetri et al., 2018; National Academic of Scien-
ceEngineering and Medicine, 2021), governance responses have been
minimal so far, primarily amounting to three non-binding governing
body decisions under the Convention on Biological Diversity (CBD).
With existing governance frameworks thus being largely indeterminate,
governance questions pertaining to research into and potential deploy-
ment of solar geoengineering technology remain unaddressed. This has
resulted in institutional drift with potential risks remaining unmitigated
and risk management capacities unexploited.
5. Gene drive systems
Gene drive systems are a proposed technique for biasing patterns of
biological reproduction (NASEM 2016). They would allow for genetic
modications to be driven through entire target populations. For
species with short reproductive cycles, they would thus enable rapid
population replacement (i.e. switching wild types to transgenic species)
or even eradication (Esvelt et al., 2014). In principle, gene drives allow
for unprecedented biological control at the ecosystem scale. In addition
to combatting vector diseases such as malaria, they might be highly
effective for protecting vulnerable ecosystems from biological invasions
and for proong agricultural systems against pests. As gene drives are
likely to diffuse widely and potentially uncontrollably, including in a
transboundary context, they present biosafety risks that are likely
signicantly greater than those associated with conventional Geneti-
cally Modied Organisms (GMOs). The magnitude, nature and man-
ageability of these risks is a matter of ongoing dispute. No clearly
appropriate risk assessment methodologies presently exist for gene
drives (see Dolezel et al., 2020). Various technological solutions to the
biosafety problem are currently being explored, such as methods for
reversing the effects of gene drive releases or for limiting geographic
spread, although these might also end up introducing new problems,
including from unpredicted interactions among system components.
Gene drives being an ambiguous technology that might either
endanger biodiversity or provide an effective tool for its conservation,
global biodiversity governance is so far indeterminate (Rabitz 2019). Do
gene drives pose a threat to the CBDs conservation objective or a po-
tential tool for its implementation? How do gene drives t into the
obligation on CBD parties to control or eradicateinvasive alien species
(Article 8. h), considering that drives might either be a tool for control or
eradication, or might constitute invasive alien species themselves? How
would the provisions of the CBDs Cartagena Protocol on Biosafety
(notably regarding risk assessment and Advance Informed Agreement)
apply to gene drives? So far and as with solar geoengineering, the CBD
has merely passed a series of nonbinding governing body decisions on
the wider categories of synthetic biologythat emphasize and reiterate
the need for case-by-case risk assessment and precautionary
decision-making. As the negotiations for the CBDs post-2020 Global
Biodiversity Framework unfold, it looks increasingly unlikely that
parties will adopt more detailed and stringent regulation at the 15th
Conference of the Parties, to be held in 2022. While a robust interna-
tional regulatory framework is absent, pilot projects are moving rapidly
towards initial open eld experiments, constituting a textbook denition
of institutional drift.
6. Bioinformatics
The fusion between biotechnology and information technology leads
to an increasing use of digitalized genetic sequences for research and
development across the life sciences, notably including agriculture and
pharmaceuticals. The increasing efciency of DNA sequencing and
digital storage solutions is giving birth to vast digital genomic libraries,
the content of which can be analyzed at a hitherto unprecedented scale
via new applications in machine learning and big data analytics. Bio-
informatics holds signicant potential for improving human well-being,
as well as for environmental sustainability, conservation and food se-
curity (Gaffney et al., 2020). At the same time, the gradual displacement
of physical samples with digitalized electronic sequences in the
contemporary life sciences is raising questions regarding the fair and
equitable sharing of benets resulting from the utilization of genetic
resources, a core objective of the CBD, the International Treaty on Plant
Genetic Resources for Food and Agriculture (ITPGRA) and other in-
struments (Lawson et al., 2019). This objective is based on the ethical
principle that the countries, communities or other organizations that
have cultivated and conserved genetic resources should participate in
commercial and other benets that are derived from their utilization.
Bioinformatics is an ambiguous technology because, on one hand,
the unfettered access to genetic sequence data could facilitate research
and development with pay-offs for environmental sustainability: by
stimulating innovation in green technologies and by contributing to
biodiversity conservation (Halewood et al., 2018). On the other, the
technology potentially undercuts fair and equitable benet-sharing: the
utilization and transfer of genetic sequence data is notoriously difcult
to monitor, which aggravates the compliance problem in ABS,
commonly and broadly referred to as biopiracy (Rabitz 2015). This
F. Rabitz et al.
Earth System Governance 12 (2022) 100134
4
would raise questions of social justice and prevent benets from being
channeled into projects for nature conservation. Yet the nancial vol-
ume which could be leveraged through benet-sharing from genetic
sequence data is uncertain, as is the extent of spin-off benets from
innovation on the basis of such data. We neither know which monetary
(and other) resources benet-sharing could mobilize for nature conser-
vation; nor do we know the degree to which benet-sharing and its
associated compliance procedures would hamper innovation in the life
sciences.
The CBD and the ITPGRFA generally require the sharing of benets
from the utilization of physical genetic resources. The extent to which
they do (and should) apply to genetic sequence data is an explosive
political issue which has already wrecked a multi-year reform process
under the ITPGRFA and has become a major sticking point in the ne-
gotiations on the CBDs post-2020 Global Biodiversity Framework
(Rohden and Scholz 2021). The indeterminateness of governance
frameworks has contributed to institutional drift: while biotechnological
research and development increasingly shifts towards genetic sequence
data, questions of access and benet-sharing remain unresolved. In
practice, this means that the biotechnology industry (in predominantly
developed countries) continues utilizing genetic sequence data without
appropriate international and national regulations that would ensure
the fair and equitable sharing of benets with the stakeholders (pre-
dominantly from developing countries) that have cultivated and
conserved the corresponding physical specimens. This highlights the
distributional implications of indeterminateness and drift.
7. Conclusions
The growing relevance of technology for GEG requires an appro-
priate conceptualization of their relationship. We have here provided a
preliminary conceptual approach that centers on technological ambi-
guity as a key factor inuencing governance responses. Our framework
is sufciently exible and open-ended to be compatible with a variety of
theoretical traditions, such as rationalist or sociological approaches to
international cooperation and institutions. In other words, we do not
aim to provide a competing account but rather propose a middle-range
conceptualization which can be integrated into different ontological and
epistemological frameworks in order to (hopefully) enable a more ne-
grained analysis of novel technologies in GEG.
As we propose, and as the cases of solar geoengineering, gene drives
and bioinformatics highlight, ambiguous technologies pose substantial
governance challenges and tend to be met with political inaction,
negligence or indecisiveness. This appears to be the case outside of the
environmental sphere as well. Contemporary developments in Articial
Intelligence, machine learning and big data, for instance, may offer vast
improvements to human well-being while simultaneously raising major
questions on issues such as algorithmic discrimination, civil rights im-
plications of facial recognition software or the status of lethal autono-
mous weapon systems under international humanitarian law. There and
elsewhere, the indeterminateness of governance systems towards
ambiguous technology implies a threat of systematic under-regulation.
As ambiguity can result not just from scientic uncertainty but also
from divergent norms and perceptions, expert advice is no silver bullet
and might even be detrimental if the existence of genuine differences in
values or in technology assessment criteria is treated as a mere lack of
scientic information (Jasanoff 2007). Somewhat schematically,
governance choices for ambiguous technologies boil down to restrictive
regulation (thus reducing or avoiding harm but possibly missing out on
critical capacities for the management of environmental risks) or
enabling regulation (thus seeking to unlock management capacities but
possibly incurring harm in the process). Neither sound science nor
precaution offers an easy way out of this dilemma: as both can lead to
enabling regulation for technologies that turn out to predominantly
constitute sources of risk, or inappropriately restrictive regulation for
technologies that might otherwise have provided important capacities
for reducing anthropogenic impacts on nature or for making human
societies more resilient to environmental changes. Crucially, there is no
solid basis for preferring either approach ex ante. A powerful illustration
of this problem is the debate on solar geoengineering: given the systemic
political failure in the global efforts for climate change mitigation,
foregoing a potential future use of solar geoengineering might be folly
yet developing or deploying such measures might just as well turn out to
be dangerous. All of this raises the uncomfortable question whether
technological ambiguity presents a hard limit to what GEG can accom-
plish? This might seem to suggest there are situations that demand a
regulatory leap of faith that is, locking-in a regulatory choice on the
prohibition-facilitation spectrum without the possibility to resolve am-
biguities, and without the option of deferring to overarching principles
such as sound science or precaution as general heuristics. However, the
key lies in accepting ambiguity and embarking on a deliberative
governance pathway that ‘keeps an eyeon the evolving risk landscape,
builds up diverse decision-making capacities in appropriate governance
institutions, and maintains the requisite governance adaptability that
does not preclude future regulatory choices once such decisions
emerge as appropriate responses to the evolving risk landscape.
Declaration of competing interest
The authors declare that they have no known competing nancial
interests or personal relationships that could have appeared to inuence
the work reported in this paper.
Acknowledgements
We are grateful for the comments from the anonymous reviewers. We
are also grateful for inputs from Oskar Gstrein, Ina M¨
oller, Valentina
Nakic, Marielle Papin, and Karsten Schulz on prior versions of this
manuscript. Sikina Jinnahs contribution to this article was in part
supported by a fellowship from the Andrew Carnegie Corporation of
New York. Florian Rabitzcontribution to this article was supported by
the Research Council of Lithuania, project no. P-MIP-19-513, Institu-
tional Adaptation to Technological Change.
References
Barrett, S., 2007. Why Cooperate? the Incentive to Supply Global Public Goods. Oxford
University Press, New York.
Barrett, S., 2008. The incredible economics of geoengineering. Environ. Resour. Econ. 39
(1), 4554.
Chhetri, N., Chong, D., Conca, K., Gillespie, A., Falk, R., Gupta, A., Jinnah, S.,
Catriona, M.L.A.L., Thiele, L., Valdivia, W., Wapner, P., 2018. ACADEMIC WORKING
GROUP ON CLIMATE ENGINEERING GOVERNANCE.
Dimitrov, R.S., 2003. Knowledge, power and interests in environmental regime
formation. Int. Stud. Q. 47 (1), 123150.
Dolezel, M., Lüthi, C., Gaugitsch, H., 2020. Beyond limits - the pitfalls of global gene
drives for environmental risk assessment in the European Union. BioRisk 15, 1.
Esvelt, K.M., Smidler, A.L., Catteruccia, F., Church, G.M., 2014. Emerging technology:
concerning RNA-guided gene drives for the alteration of wild populations. Elife 3,
e03401.
Gaffney, J., et al., 2020. Open access to genetic sequence data maximizes value to
scientists, farmers and society. Global Food Security 26, 100411.
Halewood, M., et al., 2018. Using genomic sequence information to increase
conservation and sustainable use of crop diversity and benet-sharing. Biopreserv.
Biobanking 16 (5), 368376.
Helm, C., 1998. International cooperation behind the veil of uncertainty - the case of
transboundary acidication. Environ. Resour. Econ. 12 (2), 185201.
Jasanoff, S., 2007. Technologies of humility. Nature 450 (7166), 33.
Jinnah, S., Nicholson, S., Morrow, D., 2021. Splitting geoengineering governance: how
problem structure shapes institutional design. Global Policy 12 (S1), 819.
Lawson, C., Humphries, F., Rourke, M., 2019. The future of information under the CBD,
nagoya Protocol, plant treaty and PIP framework. J. World Intellect. Property 22
(34), 103119.
McDonald, J., McGee, J., Brent, K., Burns, W., 2019. Governing geoengineering research
for the great barrier reef. Clim. Pol. 19 (7), 801811.
Mitchell, R.B., Keilbach, P.M., 2001. Situation structure and institutional design:
reciprocity, coercion and exchange. Int. Organ. 55 (4), 891917.
National Academic of Science, Engineering and Medicine (NASEM), 2016. Gene Drives
on the Horizon: Advancing Science, Navigating Uncertainty and Aligning Research
with Public Values. National Academies Press, Washington, D.C.
F. Rabitz et al.
Earth System Governance 12 (2022) 100134
5
National Academic of Science, Engineering and Medicine (NASEM), 2021. Reecting
Sunlight: Recommendations for Solar Geoengineering Research and Research
Governance. National Academies Press, Washington, D.C.
Parson, E.A., 2003. Protecting the Ozone Layer: Science and Strategy. Oxford University
Press, New York.
Rabitz, F., 2015. Biopiracy after the Nagoya Protocol: problem structure, regime design
and implementation challenges. Brazilian Political Science Review 9 (2), 3053.
Rabitz, F., 2019a. Institutional drift in international biotechnology regulation. Global
Policy 10 (2), 227237.
Rabitz, F., 2019. Gene drives and the international biodiversity regime. Review of
European, Comparative & International Environmental Law 28 (3), 339348.
Reynolds, J.L., 2019. The Governance of Solar Geoengineering: Managing Climate
Change in the Anthropocene. Cambridge University Press, New York.
Reynolds, J.L., 2021. Is solar geoengineering ungovernable? A critical assessment of
governance challenges identied by the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate
Change. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Clim. Change 12 (2), e690.
Rohden, F., Scholz, A.H., 2021. The International Political Process Around Digital
Sequence Information under the Convention on Biological Diversity and the
20182020 Intersessional Period. Plants, People, Planet (online rst).
Rotolo, D., Hicks, D., Martin, B.R., 2015. What is an emerging technology? Res. Pol. 44
(10), 18271843.
Streeck, W., Thelen, K., 2005. Introduction. In: Streeck, W., Thelen, K. (Eds.), Beyond
Continuity: Institutional Change in Advanced Political Economies. Oxford University
Press, Oxford/New York.
F. Rabitz et al.
... While gene drives are unique in the domain of biotechnolo gy, they are only one example for various highpowered techno logical interventions that are currently advertised as response options to critical challenges of global sustainable development (Reynolds 2021, Rabitz et al. 2022. They accordingly raise fun damental normative questions about the management of natu ral environments as well as cultural concepts of nature (Neyrat 2019, BfN 2022, issues that have been debated long and contro versially in nature conservation and environmental ethics (e. g., Minteer 2018, Potthast 2019, Toepfer 2020. ...
... Parallels also exist between gene drives and solar radiation modification for climate engineering, a set of proposed methods for redirecting sunlight in order to slow down or halt global warm ing (see Irvine et al. 2016). These methods would reflect a small percentage of solar energy before it reaches the planetary surface, possibly allowing international temperature targets to be reached even if global efforts at greenhouse gas mitigation remain inad equate (Rabitz et al. 2022). Proposals for solar radiation modifi > These proposed technological solutions potentially divert atten tion away from more effective measures that target the causes of planetary environmental problems, such as overuse and pollution of natural resources. ...
... The ethical and governancerelated challenges raised by these technologies with great depth of intervention tend to be relative ly similar and frequently revolve around riskrisk tradeoffs in the presence of significant uncertainty: environmental challenges and potential technological solutions each pose distinct risks that are, to some extent, unknown or even unknowable, thus leading to complex decision problems (Reynolds 2021, Rabitz et al. 2022. ...
Article
Full-text available
Engineered gene drives are an emerging technology for the large-scale genetic modification of natural populations of species. They are controversial due to high levels of uncertainty about their risks and benefits. We analyze gene drives in their social, natural, and technolog- ical contexts. We discuss their depth of intervention and compare gene drives to “conventional” genetic modification techniques and to other novel high-impact technologies. While gene drives might overpromise and under-deliver solutions for problems of sustainable develop- ment, they also represent a paradigm shift in human technological interference with nature, thus requiring broad discussion in society.
... Although there are fewer results on indirect, socio-politically mediated risks, research on these shows a mix of promising and cautionary results (Parson & Ernst, 2013;Rabitz et al., 2022). In contrast to the NUA's presumption that SG would worsen inequality, several studies suggest SG might actually reduce global economic inequality (Harding et al., 2020;IPCC WGIII, 2022, at 2425. ...
... Without these, there is no basis for confident views on either SG's risk-benefit balance, or the feasibility of acceptably governing it. SG clearly presents governance challenges that will require substantial innovation and new capacity (Parson & Ernst, 2013;Rabitz et al., 2022). But new international governance capabilities have been created before to meet new needs (Parson, 2003;Sand, 2017), and a rich and growing literature is exploring concrete ways to meet the new governance needs of SG (Conca, 2019; Gupta & Möller, 2019;. ...
Article
Full-text available
A prominent recent perspective article in this journal and accompanying open letter propose a broad international “non‐use agreement” (NUA) on activities related to solar geoengineering (SG). The NUA calls on governments to renounce large‐scale use of SG, and also to refuse to fund SG research, ban outdoor experiments, decline to grant IP rights, and reject discussions of SG in international organizations. We argue that such pre‐emptive rejection of public research and consultation would deprive future policy‐makers of knowledge and capability that would support informed decisions to safely and equitably limit climate risk, sustain human welfare, and protect threatened ecosystems. In contrast to the broad prohibitions of the NUA, we propose an alternative near‐term pathway with five elements: assess SG risks and benefits in the context of related climate risks and responses; distinguish the risks and governance needs of SG research and deployment; pursue research that treats uncertainties and divergent results even‐handedly; harness normalization of SG as a path to effective assessment and governance; and build a more globally inclusive conversation on SG and its governance. These principles would support a more informed, responsible, and inclusive approach to limiting climate risks, including judgments on the potential role or rejection of SG, than the prohibitory approach of the NUA. This article is categorized under: Climate and Development > Social Justice and the Politics of Development Policy and Governance > Multilevel and Transnational Climate Change Governance Policy and Governance > National Climate Change Policy
... Carton (2019) too identifies close compatibility between large-scale carbon removal and the interests of carbon-intensive industries, arguing that removals are attractive for these industries because they help moderate the devaluation of fossil fuel assets (see also Hall & Davis, 2021). Taken together, this literature suggests that a combination of economic and political commitments to existing infrastructures and energy strategies is creating path dependencies that make non-CDR pathways seem unfeasible (Oomen, 2021;Rabitz et al., 2022;Sarnoff, 2020). ...
Article
Full-text available
Carbon dioxide removal is rapidly becoming a key focus in climate research and politics. This is raising concerns of “moral hazard” or “mitigation deterrence,” that is, the risk that promises of and/or efforts to pursue carbon removal end up reducing or delaying near‐term mitigation efforts. Some, however, contest this risk, arguing that it is overstated or lacking evidence. In this review, we explore the reasons behind the disagreement in the literature. We unpack the different ways in which moral hazard/mitigation deterrence (MH/MD) is conceptualized and examine how these conceptualizations inform assessments of MH/MD risks. We find that MH/MD is a commonly recognized feature of modeled mitigation pathways but that conclusions as to the real‐world existence of MH/MD diverge on individualistic versus structural approaches to examining it. Individualistic approaches favor narrow conceptualizations of MH/MD, which tend to exclude the wider political‐economic contexts in which carbon removal emerges. This exclusion limits the value and relevance of such approaches. We argue for a broader understanding of what counts as evidence of delaying practices and propose a research agenda that complements theoretical accounts of MH/MD with empirical studies of the political‐economic structures that may drive mitigation deterrence dynamics. This article is categorized under: The Carbon Economy and Climate Mitigation > Benefits of Mitigation The Social Status of Climate Change Knowledge > Sociology/Anthropology of Climate Knowledge Policy and Governance > Multilevel and Transnational Climate Change Governance
Article
The 2023 marine heatwave event unfolding globally is a stark reminder of the impacts of climate change on coral reefs. At the time of our writing, average global sea surface temperatures were the hottest ever recorded. Coral reefs throughout the Americas and the Caribbean were being exposed to unprecedented and prolonged thermal stress (22 degrees Celsius [°C] heating weeks in the Florida Keys), leading to extensive reef bleaching. Reefs in the Red Sea, Indonesia, and South East Asia were experiencing increasing heat stress in excess of NOAA’s (the National Oceanic and Atmospheric Administration's) alert level 2 (https://coralreefwatch.noaa.gov/product/vs/map.php). Coral reefs around the globe are degrading at an unprecedented rate, primarily because of climate change; however, other anthropogenic stressors, such as poor water quality, pollution, and overfishing, remain significant. The global live coral cover has been halved since 1950 (Eddy et al. 2021), with coral declines of more than 99% predicted at 2°C warming above the preindustrial mean global temperatures (IPCC 2018). At the current rate of emission reductions, this could potentially occur as early as the 2030s (Allan et al. 2023).
Article
Full-text available
Societal Impact Statement The international conservation of biological diversity is addressed under the Convention on Biological Diversity (CBD) and goals for the next decade will be discussed at the next Conference of the Parties. One issue under negotiation in the CBD is Digital Sequence Information (DSI), which has created tension between parties calling for preserving open access to DSI who also note its importance in addressing biodiversity and the UN Sustainable Development Goals and those parties calling for fair and equitable benefit sharing from DSI. This article introduces scientists to the current debate and political process on DSI within the CBD. Summary Most biologists take open access to sequence data for granted. This open system, while a hallmark of innovation and collaboration for the scientific community, is being called into question as some parties to the Convention on Biological Diversity (CBD) assert that this access undermines their sovereign rights over their genetic resources and corresponding benefit sharing. The governance of sequence data and potentially other types of biological data, known in international policy circles as “Digital Sequence Information” (DSI), a placeholder term invented by negotiators, could be dramatically altered and ultimately change the way scientific research and publishing on sequence data is conducted. Many sequence‐using scientists are unfamiliar with the international political processes around DSI even though it could lead to irreversible decisions that might have significant impacts on research. This paper bridges that gap by providing an overview of the ongoing political process with a focus on the most recent studies on DSI commissioned by the Secretariat of the Convention on Biological Diversity (SCBD) and what these studies forecast about the political debate. With this information in hand, the scientific community can hopefully better engage with the political process and proactively promote evidence‐based decisions or even solutions that can bridge the demand for benefit sharing with the scientific need for open access to DSI.
Article
Full-text available
Solar radiation modification (SRM) could greatly reduce climate change and associated risks. Yet it has not been well‐received by the climate change expert community. This is evident in the authoritative reports of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC), which emphasize SRM's governance, political, social, and ethical challenges. I find seven such challenges identified in the IPCC reports: that SRM could lessen mitigation; that its termination would cause severe climatic impacts; that researching SRM would create a “slippery slope” to its inevitable and unwanted use; that decisions to use it could be contrary to democratic norms; that the public may not accept SRM; that it could be unethical; and that decisions to use SRM could be unilateral. After assessing the extent to which these challenges are supported by existing evidence, scholarly literature, and robust logic, I conclude that, for six of the seven, the IPCC's claims variously are speculative, fail to consider both advantages and disadvantages, implicitly make unreasonable negative assumptions, are contrary to existing evidence, and/or are meaninglessly vague. I suggest some reasons for the reports' failure to meet the IPCC's standards of balance, thoroughness, and accuracy, and recommend a dedicated Special Report on SRM. This article is categorized under: • Integrated Assessment of Climate Change > Assessing Climate Change in the Context of Other Issues Abstract Cover of the IPCC's Special Report Global Warming of 1.5°C.
Article
Full-text available
Open access to genetic sequence data, often referred to as Digital Sequence Information, has been available since genome sequencing became possible and creates both monetary and nonmonetary value. Nonmonetary value is created when scientists access sequence data for discovery, collaboration, and innovation. Monetary value is created when genetic variability is leveraged to develop more robust and resilient crop plants, vibrant seed systems, more sustainable agriculture, and food security for consumers. Millions of dollars have been invested in curating and creating access to sequence databases and scientists from almost every country in the world have accessed these databases, free of charge. This access may now be threatened by well-meaning policy-makers who have not consulted with the scientific community. Monetizing or creating greater regulation of genetic sequence data would create barriers to innovation, partnering, and problem-solving.
Article
Full-text available
Gene drive organisms (GDOs) have been suggested as approaches to combat some of the most pressing environmental and public health issues. No such organisms have so far been released into the environment, but it remains unclear whether the relevant regulatory provisions will be fit for purpose to cover their potential environmental, human and animal health risks if environmental releases of GDOs are envisaged. We evaluate the novel features of GDOs and outline the resulting challenges for the environmental risk assessment. These are related to the definition of the receiving environment, the use of the comparative approach, the definition of potential harm, the stepwise testing approach, the assessment of long-term and large-scale risks at population and ecosystem level and the post-release monitoring of adverse effects. Fundamental adaptations as well as the development of adequate risk assessment methodologies are needed in order to enable an operational risk assessment for globally spreading GDOs before these organisms are released into environments in the EU.
Article
Full-text available
Coral reefs are highly vulnerable to the impacts of rising marine temperatures and marine heatwaves. Mitigating dangerous climate change is essential and urgent, but many reef systems are already suffering on current levels of warming. Geoengineering options are worth exploring to protect the Great Barrier Reef (GBR) from extreme warming conditions, but we contend that they require strong governance and public consultation from the outset. Australian governments are currently funding feasibility testing of three geoengineering proposals for the GBR. Each proposal involves manipulating ocean or atmospheric conditions to lower water temperatures and thereby reduce the threat of mass coral bleaching events. Innovative strategies to protect the GBR and field testing of these is essential, but current laws do not guarantee robust governance for field testing of these technologies. Nor do they provide the foundation for a more coherent national policy on climate intervention technologies more generally. Responsible governance frameworks, including detailed risk assessment and early public consultation, are necessary for geoengineering research to build legitimacy and promote scientific progress. Key policy insights • Marine heatwaves pose a serious threat to coral reefs, including Australia’s iconic Great Barrier Reef. • Australian governments have recognized the threats of warming waters, and are funding research of geoengineering options for the Great Barrier Reef. • The limited earlier field testing of geoengineering demonstrates the need for specific governance to manage risks, build legitimacy and maintain public support. • Australia requires a framework to govern geoengineering research and development before deployment of such technologies.
Article
This article adds conceptual discipline to a well‐rehearsed but largely intuitive argument within the climate engineering community that carbon dioxide removal (CDR) and solar radiation management (SRM) should be treated separately – ‘split’ rather than ‘lumped’ – in policy discussions. Specifically, we build the first, theoretically derived argument for ‘splitting’. We do this by engaging a set of theoretical insights from the international relations literature, having to do with the relationship between problem structure and institutional design. Centrally, we apply some key elements of problem structure – which allows us to compare policy issues along variables such as geographic scope, costs, and actor number and asymmetries – to the cases of SRM and CDR. By analyzing their problem structures, we demonstrate that SRM and CDR are different in ways that are likely to yield different state preferences for institutional design, and thus policy proposals that split SRM and CDR are more likely to be adopted by states. In short, we construct a theoretical argument for ‘splitting’ SRM and CDR governance in global policy discussions. Treating climate response options that have very different problem structures as though they are the same unduly limits the development of appropriate governance and, in particular, limits the ability of different parts of the international governance architecture to pick up relevant aspects of solar radiation management and carbon dioxide removal governance.
Article
Gene drives are genetic modifications designed for rapidly diffusing traits throughout a target population. They are currently being proposed as biological control agents to combat, for instance, invasive alien species and disease vectors. They also raise concerns regarding their potential adverse effects on biological diversity. This text assesses gene drive governance under the Convention on Biological Diversity (CBD) and its Cartagena Protocol on Biosafety. While gene drives are directly relevant for the objectives of both agreements, their regulatory frameworks have not kept up with the pace of technological change. The focus of this article is on the analysis of gaps and inconsistencies within both agreements. It highlights numerous elements of the CBD and the Cartagena Protocol that raise challenges for gene drive governance, such as matters related to regulatory scope, transboundary movements, precaution and invasive alien species.
Article
The United Nations’ Convention of Biological Diversity (and the Nagoya Protocol on Access to Genetic Resources and the Fair and Equitable Sharing of Benefits Arising from their Utilization), the Food and Agriculture Organisation of the United Nations’ International Treaty for Plant Genetic Resources for Food and Agriculture, and the World Health Organisation of the United Nations’ (WHO) Pandemic Influenza Preparedness Framework all set out schemes for access and benefit sharing (ABS) some biological materials. This article addresses the apparent conflict between the general obligations in these agreements to disclose and exchange information and dealing with information as a resource derivative within the ABS transaction. This latter dealing is a closed domain for information under the ABS schemes where information is a resource derivative that is a part of the ABS transaction. Treating information as a resource derivative within the ABS transaction is likely to impose unnecessary and inefficient burdens on ABS transactions. After reviewing the recent developments, the article postulates a risk framework for valuing information as a part of the ABS transaction, or alternatively, a charge, tax, or levy to externalize the costs so that information remains available to be disclosed and exchanged promoting more and better science and research.
Article
Digitalization, genome editing and synthetic biology are presently leading to fundamental changes in the field of biotechnology. At the same time, international regulatory institutions have largely failed to adapt to those changes. This text evaluates the role of interests, knowledge and institutional factors for explaining nonadaptation, or ‘institutional drift’. Focusing on the domains of biosafety, biosecurity and genetic resources, the analysis highlights the explanatory power of knowledge and, to a lesser extent, interests, with institutional factors playing only a minor role. With global governance having to cope with profound changes in various technological fields, the text thus shows the broader importance of understanding the conditions under which international institutions do, or do not, adapt. In many policy fields, technological change outpaces the adaptive capacity of international institutions, thus raising increasingly difficult challenges for global governance as such.