PreprintPDF Available
Preprints and early-stage research may not have been peer reviewed yet.

Abstract

Ignorance, viewed as a social construction, appears to be a contributing factor to the failure of individuals and societies not attaining their highest potential. Delusions, pluralistic ignorance and self-deception are often products of aberrant cognitive processes that comprise ignorance. The motivation supporting these cognitive forms seems to be both self-destructive and self-sustaining; thereby, creating a cyclical perceptual cognitive product that can result in long-term detriment. Biased inferences, cognitive load, goal orientation, heuristics, knowledge accessibility, and schemata appear to be involved in the creation and perpetuation of delusions, pluralistic ignorance, and self-deception. Due to the bereft state of ignorance, the stemming perceptual output might be remedied by a societal construction that stimulates advanced cognitive skill and rewards mature critical analysis. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.
2013 Report: Ignorance
Shiseida Sade Kelly Aponte
Arizona State University
Author’s Note
This report has been created by the independent empirical analysis of the student,
Shiseida Sade Kelly Aponte. In no way shall there be reproduction of any part of
this academic work without proper citation or explicitly expressed permission from
Shiseida Sade Kelly Aponte. If there are any questions, comments, suggestions, or
concerns, please contact Shiseida Sade Kelly Aponte.
Abstract
Ignorance, viewed as a social construction, appears to be a contributing factor to
the failure of individuals and societies not attaining their highest potential.
Delusions, pluralistic ignorance and self-deception are often products of aberrant
cognitive processes that comprise ignorance. The motivation supporting these
cognitive forms seems to be both self-destructive and self-sustaining; thereby,
creating a cyclical perceptual cognitive product that can result in long-term
detriment. Biased inferences, cognitive load, goal orientation, heuristics,
knowledge accessibility, and schemata appear to be involved in the creation and
perpetuation of delusions, pluralistic ignorance, and self-deception. Due to the
bereft state of ignorance, the stemming perceptual output might be remedied by a
societal construction that stimulates advanced cognitive skill and rewards mature
critical analysis.
Ignorance can be defined as a deliberate or naturally occurring lack of knowledge,
whose deficiency manifests different forms of aberrant cognitive processes. The
aberrant cognitive processes consist of false mental models whose attributions,
dispositional factors, inferences, heuristics, schemata and valence quality have
evolved to favor information that operates in accordance with the deficiency
despite contextual information attesting to the contrary (e.g. chronic outcome
focus, confirmation bias, false consensus effect, prediction error). Non-normative
cognitive outputs appear to be motivated by survival functions that support a
cohesive, comprehensive reality, whose interpretation operates in tandem with the
needs of existence(, such as the definition of self, esteem, identity ideals, and
social goals). As such, when information appears to conflict with the needs of
existence, an individual can become motivated, either consciously or
subconsciously, to form a false belief or a system of false beliefs to retain the
sense of psychological homeostasis. Such a motivation is dependent upon whether
basic needs have been reliably satisfied; accurate identification of needs,
together with consistent need gratification, enables the organism to effectively
manage more complex cognitive loads. Delusions, pluralistic ignorance and self-
deception are some of the types of erroneous output that result from the aberrant
cognitive processes, stemming from chronically afflicted motivation and comprising
the state of ignorance
Delusions emanate from a system of false beliefs that usually arise in the form of
elaborate false narratives, based on inaccurately interpreted factual or
incomprehensible nonfactual information. These delusions can be so intricately
incorporated into the belief system that they persist even amid stark confrontation
with facts. Delusional content can be so convincing that the afflicted individual
continuously integrates information into their false narrative, despite direct
confrontation with reality. Due to the ineffectively regulated cognitive processes
involved in delusional narratives, in addition to concurrent psychological factors
that incapacitate normative functioning, behavioral and mental functioning can be
sufficiently unsuitably adapted to warrant the need for psychological treatment.
Pluralistic ignorance often involves a collectively shared or individual delusion,
such that participation in a false reality continues despite insight or personal
beliefs that should lead one to behave otherwise. Within the collective,
individuals are aware of something amiss, but misjudge the perceptions of others
and, to avoid the potential consequences of violating consensual norms, they
continue to participate in the false belief without disruption. Self-deception is a
type of delusional belief, however more modest in its output than delusions;
typically consisting of untruths that serve an adaptive function. Used as a defense
mechanism, self-deception serves to compensate or explain the loss of dignity and
violation of self-governing principles that can occur when confronting reality.
Delusions are common in the clinical population (i.e. patients, unsuitably adapted
persons yet diagnosed), while pluralistic ignorance and self-deception are rather
frequent in non-clinical populations (e.g. business, economics, education,
entertainment, mass communications, marketing) often involving delusional factors
that are known to be a consensual norm, irrational, uncertain or untrue. As such,
one might logically consider the significance of the cognitive, cultural and social
industries who appear to propagate and maintain the propounded "logical"
manifestation of these distorted cognitive outputs without understanding the extent
of their implications. For, inaccurately construed perceptions, through lower
standards of ethical analysis and poor decision processes, are often haphazardly
imposed and/or not easily regulated; thus, it is plausible to conceive of positing
ignorance as a probable (and pertinent) stochastic social issue.
In summary, ignorance often involves the deliberate false consensus of data,
inaccurate understanding of information, or unintentional absence of knowledge.
Impaired belief formation, selective perception, and uninformed analysis often
results from aberrant cognitive processes that produce ignorance. Different forms
of ignorance involve delusions, pluralistic ignorance and self-deception. Delusions
are often pathological, while pluralistic ignorance and self-deception are,
typically, mundane, with a cumulative pernicious effect if the organism does not
learn to critically analyze information. Due to the prevalence of delusional
beliefs in the public sphere of influence, it seems imperative to effectively
address the construction of society with this information in mind, particularly
considering the fact that such consideration would be of most benefit when seeking
to prevent the conditions which hinder the human organism from attaining it highest
potential.
References
Allison, S. T., Mackie, D. M. & Messick, D. M. (1996). Outcome biases in social
perception: Implications for dispositional inference, attitude change,
stereotyping, and social behavior. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 28,
53-93.
Bandura, A. (1989). Social cognitive theory. In R. Vasta (Editor), Annals of Child
Development. Vol. 6. Six Theories of Child Development (p. 1-60). JAI Press.
Bonhoeffer, D. (1951). 'On Stupidity'. In Letters and Papers (p. 9-11). The
Dietrich Bonhoeffer Works.
Bortolotti, L. & Mameli, M. (2012). Self-deception, delusion and the boundaries of
folk psychology. Humana Mente, 20, 203–221.
Brendl, C. M. (1996). Principles of judging valence: What makes events positive or
negative? Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 28, 95-160.
Buckley, M. R., Harvey, M. G. & Beu, D. S. (2000).The role of pluralistic ignorance
in the perception of unethical behavior. Journal of Business Ethics, 23, 353-364.
Croissant, J. L. (2014). Agnotology: Ignorance and absence or towards a sociology
of things that aren't there. Social Epistemology: A Journal of Knowledge, Culture
and Policy, 28(1), 4-25.
Douglas, N. L. (2000). Enemies of critical thinking: Lessons from social psychology
research. Reading Psychology, 21(2), 129–144.
Kiran, C. & Chaudhury, S. (2009). Understanding delusions. Industrial Psychiatry
Journal, 18(1), 3–18.
Kramer, R. M. (1999). Trust and distrust in organizations: Emerging perspectives,
enduring questions. Annual Review of Psychology, 50, 569–598.
Krauss, R. M., Chen, Y. & Chawla, P. (1996). Nonverbal behavior and nonverbal
communication: What do conversational hand gestures tell us? Advances in
Experimental Social Psychology, 28, 389-450.
Maslow, A. H. (1943). A theory of human motivation. Psychological Review, 50(4),
370–396.
Miyazono, K. (2015). Delusions as harmful malfunctioning beliefs. Consciousness and
Cognition, 22, 561-573.
Prentice, D. A. & Miller, D. T. (1996). Pluralistic ignorance and the perpetuation
of social norms by unwitting actors. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology,
28, 161-209.
Riophe, R. (2011). The ethics of willful ignorance. Georgetown Journal of Legal
Ethics, 24(1), 187-224.
Schiebinger, L. & Proctor, R. N. (2008). Agnotology: The Making and Unmaking of
Ignorance. Stanford University Press.
Shepherd, S. & Kay, A. C. (2012). On the perpetuation of ignorance: System
dependence, system justification and the motivated avoidance of sociopolitical
information. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 102(2), 264-280.
Smithson, M. (1985). Toward a social theory of ignorance. Journal for the Theory of
Social Behaviour, 15(2), 151–172.
Uleman, J. S., Newman, L. S. & Moskowitz, G. B. (1996). People as flexible
interpreters: Evidence and issues from spontaneous trait inference. Advances in
Experimental Social Psychology, 28, 211-279.
ResearchGate has not been able to resolve any citations for this publication.
Article
Full-text available
Delusional beliefs are typically pathological. Being pathological is clearly distinguished from being false or being irrational. Anna might falsely believe that his husband is having an affair but it might just be a simple mistake. Again, Sam might irrationally believe, without good evidence, that he is smarter than his colleagues, but it might just be a healthy self-deceptive belief. On the other hand, when a patient with brain damage caused by a car accident believes that his father was replaced by an imposter or another patient with schizophrenia believes that “The Organization” painted the shops on a street in red and green to convey a message, these beliefs are not merely false or irrational. They are pathological. What makes delusions pathological? This paper explores the negative features because of which delusional beliefs are pathological. First, I critically examine the proposals according to which delusional beliefs are pathological because of (1) their strangeness, (2) their extreme irrationality, (3) their resistance to folk psychological explanations or (4) impaired responsibility-grounding capacities of people with them. I present some counterexamples as well as theoretical problems for these proposals. Then, I argue, following Wakefield’s harmful dysfunction analysis of disorder, that delusional beliefs are pathological because they involve some sorts of harmful malfunctions. In other words, they have a significant negative impact on wellbeing (=harmful) and, in addition, some psychological mechanisms, directly or indirectly related to them, fail to perform the jobs for which they were selected in the past (=malfunctioning). An objection to the proposal is that delusional beliefs might not involve any malfunctions. For example, they might be playing psychological defence functions properly. Another objection is that a harmful malfunction is not sufficient for something to be pathological. For example, false beliefs might involve some malfunctions according to teleosemantics, a popular naturalist account of mental content, but harmful false beliefs do not have to be pathological. I examine those objections in detail and show that they should be rejected after all.
Article
Full-text available
The study of ignorance, or agnotology, has many similarities with studies of absence. This paper outlines a framework for agnotology which is shaped by interdisciplinary studies of both ignorance and absence, and identifies properties such as chronicity, granularity, scale, intentionality, and ontology in relation to epistemology as useful for studying ignorance. These properties can be used to compare various case studies. While not all problems of ignorance are problems of absent knowledge, those that are can gain by an examination of the literatures on absence and the concept of the privative. The lack of symmetry in explanation and representation are methodological challenges to studying ignorances and absences.
Article
Full-text available
This chapter investigates the ways in which readily inferences about others occur when inferences are not the focal task. The evidence and issues from spontaneous trait inference (STI) are also discussed in the chapter. STI occurs when attending to another person's behavior produces a trait inference in the absence of explicit intention to infer traits or form an impression of that person. Seven different paradigms have been employed to detect and investigate spontaneous trait inference: (1) cued recall under memory instructions; (2) cued recall of distractors; (3) recognition probe; (4) lexical decision; (5) delayed recognition; (6) word stem completion; and (7) relearning. Informational conditions review the ways in which the trait-relevant information presented in STI studies is systematically varied and its effects. The treatment of cognitive conditions focuses on the efficiency of STI and its minimal demands on cognitive capacity. The motivational conditions are divided into: proximal and distal goals. The chapter also explores whether STI refers to actors or merely to behaviors and the consequences of STI based on awareness, priming, prediction, and correspondence bias.
Article
Brendan McMahon gives a brief overview on the basics of psychoanalytical theories of child development.
Article
Pluralistic ignorance begins with a discrepancy between public actions and private sentiments, typically produced by widespread behavioral adherence to a social norm. Pluralistic ignorance is a pervasive feature of social life and is found to characterize the dynamics of social situations, social groups, and social movements. Group identification is the root cause for many cases of pluralistic ignorance—that individuals often act out of a desire to be good group members but interpret others' similarly motivated behavior as reflecting personal beliefs and opinions. This chapter presents two cases of pluralistic ignorance: (1) concerning the attitudes of college students toward alcohol use on campus and (2) concerning the gender stereotypes held by elementary school children. Mean responses of students in percentage are graphically represented in the chapter. Pluralistic ignorance describes the case in which virtually every member of a group or society privately rejects a belief, opinion, or practice, yet believes that virtually every other member privately accepts it. The term “pluralistic ignorance” is something of a misnomer, for in these cases, group members are not, in fact, ignorant of one another's private sentiments; rather, they think they know, but are mistaken.
Article
The positivity or negativity of events is a major parameter for theorizing in diverse areas of psychology––namely, altruism, conflict, attitudes, impression formation, or conditioning. This chapter explores the impact of positivity or negativity of an event on experience and behavior, such as emotional experience or decision behavior. The positivity or negativity acquired in direct connection with some events might also vary little among or within individuals when the valences of these events are extremely positive or extremely negative. Much less attention has been devoted to factors that initially cause an event to be positive or negative, and investigators often regard it as self-evident that the valence (i.e., the positivity or negativity) of an event is fixed, as if it were an inherent property of the event. Several variables have implications for the experienced intensity of emotions––the valence quantity of an event, the importance of high-identity goals, the likelihood of an event, and the representation of an event as the presence versus the absence of a feature.
Article
Reagan's triumph was very much... a rousing vote of confidence in him and his politics. [Newsweek, shortly after Ronald Reagan defeated President Jimmy Carter with 50.7% of the popular vote in 1980 (Goldman, 1980)].
Article
This chapter explores how gestures contribute to comprehension, how gesturing affect speech and what can be learned from studying conversational gestures. The primary function of conversational hand gestures is to aid in the formulation of speech. Gestures can convey nonsemantic information. The study of speech and gestures overlaps with the study of person perception and attribution processes. The significance of gestures can be ambiguous and will affect the meanings and consequences to the observed gestures. A topology of gestures is adopters, symbolic gestures, and conversational gestures. Different types of conversational gestures can be distinguished as—namely, motor movements and lexical movements. Conversational hand gestures have been assumed to convey semantic information. Several studies that attempt to assess the kinds of information conversational gestures convey to naive observers and the extent to which gestures enhance the communicativeness of spoken messages are described in the chapter.
Article
This article examines changes in definitions of critical thinking. The most frequently cited definition of critical thinking points to the importance of belief, yet there is a dearth of research and theory in the reading arena concerning the construct of belief. Social psychologists have investigated belief, however, and have found evidence for two belief theories which are useful in understanding the complexity and problematic nature of teaching students to think critically. Two strands of social psychology research are explored. One strand provides evidence for the notion that people find it much easier to believe than to disbelieve. Theother strand of research suggests thatonce beliefsare formed, they are extremely resistant to change. How these tendencies are able operate simultaneously in humans, as well as implications for the development of critical thinking are discussed.