Technical ReportPDF Available

Submission on Proposal P1055 Definitions of Gene Technology

Authors:
Centre for Integrated Research in Biosafety
School of Biological Sciences
Tel: +64 3 336 95597
Email: jack.heinemann@canterbury.ac.nz
Submission on Proposal P1055 Definitions of Gene Technology
Lay summary
INBI supports the effort to define gene technology in a way that captures all current and
future techniques. However, the proposed preferred definition is inadequate. In addition, we
note that Australia has already defined some techniques as not gene technology despite their
potential conformity to FSANZ's preferred definition.
1
We are therefore concerned that any
definition is pro forma and without substance.
We do not agree that a priori exclusions based on hypothetical and voluntary evaluations of
biological characteristics of some New Breeding Techniques products are sufficient to ensure
safe and responsible use of gene technology.
We propose that this is an opportunity to adopt both a risk-relevant definition and a risk
assessment framework that is risk-relevant by moving away from a list of arbitrary and
mutable technical terms based on named examples of gene technology and onto a critical
control points framework. The goal should be a regulatory system that is no less safe rather
than not more complicated. With changes in technology FSANZ cannot expect that risk
assessment gets simpler.
Summary
The intention to re-define gene technology for legislative purposes is welcome. Gene
technology requires a definition that is responsible to the valid societal expectation that it
can be used responsibly because the potential for harm can be maintained at an acceptable
level.
Unfortunately, the proposed definition is of a genre that will suffer the same premature aging
as the current definition. A new definition should describe the activities of gene technology
that relate to the risks it creates, not rely upon the assumption that underlying biological
terminology has the same meaning to everyone. We submit that FSANZ should consider what
makes gene technology a technology and look to regulate gene technology with lessons from
the successful use of critical control points for other technologies. With the adoption of a
future-ready and scientifically-consistent definition we believe that it is possible to group
uses and products according to categories that are defined by the critical control points that
determine when and what risk assessment is needed.
1
“techniques that use recombinant, synthesised or amplified nucleic acid to modify or create a genome”
2
We thank Food Standards Australia New Zealand for inviting responses to this proposal.
As we understand the proposal, FSANZ is seeking to revise the definitions of gene
technology in order to 1. improve regulatory clarity on what is and is not within scope, 2.
remain able to regulate already recognised techniques and adapt as techniques of genetic
engineering are described in novel new ways or when eventually fundamentally new
techniques may be invented, and to 3. organise products into risk groups that allow for case-
specific, efficient and effective risk assessment. The Centre for Integrated Research in
Biosafety (INBI) supports these objectives.
FSANZ understandably wants to future-proof the legislation and regulations. To do so
requires describing the technology through the fundamental characteristics that define why it
should be regulated and how to control its potential to cause harm. Unfortunately, the
analysis provided in Proposal P1055 does not do this but instead continues to use a list of
examples in a semantic approach for grouping techniques of gene technology. P1055 persists
in the failing approach of using undefined words that keep on morphing in meaning, both
through scientific advances and because some developers and researchers want to limit their
meanings to maximise deregulated space, which also minimises accountability for harm.
2
To future-proof legislation and regulations requires a vision for scope that covers how
genetically modified organisms are presently made and how the technology is changing how
they can be made. Describing techniques of gene technology by their biochemistry, whether
it be the reactions that lead to the insertion of a ‘transgene’ and the reactions that lead to
genome editing, provides little clarity for technology governance.
The difference in the scales at which different techniques and products can be used matters
for governance.
3
The characteristic of the technology that justifies social governance through
legislation is that it can amplify the rate and magnitude of harm by increasing the ease of
use, number of people using it, range of types of organisms and numbers of individuals it is
used on, and the number of environments where it can be applied. Every technique of gene
technology invented does this relative to conventional breeding, which is scale-limited by the
rate of spontaneous genetic change that can be acted upon by breeders and the generation
time of the organisms that they breed.
Chemical and radiation mutagenesis changed the rate of genetic change. In vitro mutagenesis
using chemicals or oligonucleotides increased the efficiency of creating desired changes.
Transgenesis further increased the rate of genetic change as well as efficiency of creating
desired changes. The “New Breeding Techniques” accelerate change by also increasing
efficiency but also through easier access to the reagents and reducing dependence on highly
trained personnel and expensive facilities (Heinemann et al. 2021).
2
For example, see the tortured attempt by COGEM (COGEM 2010) to find a way to define recombinant and
failure to achieve any scientific basis. Similar arbitrary and inconsistent reasoning is used to define epigenes out
of scope. Likewise, protein-nucleic acids (PNAs) and future chemicals derived from modified nucleic acids may
be arbitrarily defined as different from what the proposed regulations mean by nucleic acids.
3
For plain English summaries of this point, see: https://theconversation.com/calling-the-latest-gene-
technologies-natural-is-a-semantic-distraction-they-must-still-be-regulated-166352 and
https://abiggerconversation.org/genetic-technologies-safety-and-risk-correlate-with-scale-not-naturalness/.
3
The new dimensions of scale available to NBTs include among other things a new pipeline
for changing characteristics of organisms that are food, or are inseparable from our food. For
example, genome editing reagents can be applied as topical agents absorbed on contact, in the
digestive track or in lungs by inhalation. They can be used to create desired genetic changes
in real time over landscapes or product types, even in the grocery store (Heinemann 2019;
Heinemann and Walker 2019).
The model underlying P1055 is one where expensive laboratory facilities with highly trained
personnel are needed in order to create, identify, and then amplify a rare modified individual.
As a consequence, the developer secures a pure stock. Well before release into the
environment or use in food, the characteristics of the organism are described.
4
,
5
This is the
history of all the products upon which FSANZ has based its analysis in P1055. Extrapolations
to future-proofed regulation cannot be made from that history. The potential exists for all
techniques of gene technology and associated new methodologies to increase the potential for
any of them to cause harm if arbitrarily released from active regulatory oversight.
A technique can be defined out of scope but not as safe. We submit that FSANZ should focus
on the characteristics of technology that create risk and manage those characteristics with risk
assessment and other means, as appropriate. This would be a departure from the focus on
how techniques, biochemical reactions, genes, genomes and biological characteristics can be
described to sound more or less like something not made using gene technology.
1. Governance and legislative scope
1.1. What FSANZ refers to as a “legal definition for GM food based on old methods” is
not accurate.
6
The techniques referred to as NBTs are neither new techniques nor are
they new to food produced using gene technology. When the legal definitions were
adopted, there had been for decades tools for guided or site-directed DNA
modifications, the feature all described NBTs have in common (Heinemann et al.
2021). Indeed even the term “gene editing” was used in a 1980 review of
contemporary techniques of genetic engineering (Itakura and Riggs 1980). There are
documented cases of editing using oligonucleotides unassisted by nucleases (such as
Cas9, which is a new catalyst) in the late 1980s and early 1990s in both yeast and
mice (Heinemann et al. 2021).
4
However, the difference between the current pipeline of making an organism in containment and assessing its
characteristics prior to release or use as food and in situ use of the NBTs is a critical control point that is
relevant to what categories products would fall into for risk assessment. Thus, not the NBT used but controls on
where it is used prior to evaluation would be the important regulatory trigger.
5
The techniques of genetic engineering have long been scale-limited by the need to use contained laboratories
to protect and find the rare individuals that have been altered by the techniques in vitro, which is partly because
of the inefficient uptake of exogenous nucleic acids, even transfer from Agrobacterium tumefaciens, and
proteinaceous mutagens such as double-stranded DNA nucleases (Heinemann et al. 2021). These
methodological constraints result in a development paradigm where individual GMOs are amplified in
containment and then in pure form are analysed for a pre-market risk assessment. Not all anticipated
applications of NBTs are similarly constrained and therefore do not result in a single, pure GMO from which it
is possible to credibly assert similarity of biological and chemical characteristics (Heinemann and Walker
2019).
6
From the FSANZ consultation documents. “New breeding techniques or NBTs are a diverse collection of new
techniques for genetic modification that have emerged over the last decade or more.”
4
1.2. We acknowledge that routine use of site-directed tools in plants and livestock animal
species was limited prior to the development of, for example, ZFNs, TALENs and
CRISPR/Cas. However, oligonucleotide mutagenesis was available for use. This is
not to say that creating genetically modified organisms in these species using such
reagents was easy, and that perhaps is why the ‘transgene’ methods dominated for
use in agriculture over those decades. However, it is inaccurate to say that in general
NBTs are based on fundamentally new methodologies. Calling them new does not
make them new.
1.3. One NBT that might be new is the use of double-stranded RNA to cause temporary
or heritable changes in gene expression (usually gene silencing) or to cause
recombination with heritable RNA elements, such as found in fungi (Heinemann
2019).
7
However, it is a site-directed nucleic acid technique as are other NBTs.
1.4. Therefore, we agree with the proposal to “revise and expand the process-based
definition for ‘gene technology’ to capture all methods for genetic modification other
than conventional breeding”. This should include both chemical and radiation
mutagenesis and gene silencing if for no other reason than in the latter technique the
double-stranded RNA can recombine with heritable RNA elements in fungi and it
can in some organisms cause heritable changes (Heinemann 2019).
2. How to categorise for risk
2.1. In general we agree that:
2.1.1. NBTs may result in foods with biological and chemical characteristics similar
to those that arise from spontaneous processes in nature that are then amplified
under a supervised process such as conventional breeding, and that NBTs may
result in foods that do not have similar biological and chemical characteristics.
2.1.2. NBT foods can be regulated “in a manner that is commensurate with the risks
they pose.”6
2.2. We do not agree that similarities in biological and chemical characteristics are
sufficient to determine safety without a risk assessment. While some of these
changes will not result in adverse effects, a compulsory pre-market risk assessment
helps to reduce the chances that those that could cause adverse effects will enter the
food system. Deregulation of any technology potentially grows its scale of use and
diversity of users. The more who use gene technology, the more likely an adverse
event or product will arise. Risk but not safety scales with deregulation.
2.3. Not all applications for approval of GM foods received by FSANZ and other
regulators around the world have either been accepted or progressed to a stage of
regulatory compliance. The pre-market risk assessment may be a - or the - reason
why there is no definitive proof of a harmful GM food approved by regulators so
7
We find it mildly curious that while this truly new technique with no history of safe use conforms to FSANZ’s
preferred new definition of gene technology – “techniques that use recombinant, synthesised or amplified
nucleic acid to modify or create a genome” – it is specifically defined by Australia as not gene technology.
5
far.
8
In the following paragraphs we provide examples of how regulation constrains
the scalability of harm.
2.3.1. Two foods with the same biological and chemical characteristics can have
different potential to cause harm. This is due to the differential caused by
social/legal conventions that determine what, if any, kind of intellectual property
rights they attract. For example, NBT products can be granted intellectual
property rights protections that are more powerful than products that have been
isolated by conventional breeding despite being judged to have the same
biological and chemical characteristics. The stronger the IPR, the greater the
likelihood the product will be favoured by the mega-concentrated food
production and distribution industries. Consequently, any undetected harm could
be more quickly and widely amplified and distributed by products made using
NBTs than those conventionally breed. They may also undergo different pre-sale
processing resulting in different chemical reactions and further disconnecting
them from the history of safe use.
2.3.2. Without a risk assessment, the number of biological and chemical
characteristics that are different is likely to be underestimated because only
characteristics related to intended or anticipated changes will be examined. Even
if an unbiased screen were routinely used, the public cannot be assured that an
‘apples and ~apples’ approach to comparator selection was used. For example,
FSANZ has previously used a characteristic of button mushrooms to argue the
equivalence with a characteristic in a GM maize despite the many
characteristics, including consumption patterns and food preparation, that are
different between conventional mushrooms and maize.
9
2.3.3. Deregulation may result in even more egregious examples of cherry picking
characteristics of different varieties, and sometimes very different species, for
comparison purposes.
2.3.4. Importantly, all comparisons lead to normative judgements, not absolute
certainty of safety. How similar is similar? How many characteristics have to be
similar for overall biological and chemical similarity? Different standards may
exist between regulators as well as between manufacturers. The US National
Academies warns us of the embedded uncertainty even in rigorous assessments.
8
For example: “In the first case, research was conducted on a soybean line genetically engineered to produce a
Brazil nut (Bertholletia excelsa) protein, which was a known allergen. Sera from patients allergic to Brazil nut
protein were available and tested positive for activity against the GE soybean protein. Because the segregation
from the human food supply of GE soybean with that protein could not be guaranteed, the project was halted
(Nordlee et al., 1996). The soybean variety was never commercialized(NASEM 2016). Note that the original
publication reported that the gene for the protein had already been inserted also into “tobacco, oilseed rape
(Brassica napus), the legume Vicia narbonensis, and beans (Phaseolus vulgaris)(Nordlee et al. 1996). “As a
result of this assessment, commercial interest in this transgenic soybean variety was abandoned. However, we
stress that such experiments in the hands of no[n] experts may pave the way to new mishaps” (emphasis added
to quote from Cantani 2006).
9
https://www.researchgate.net/publication/271206465_Submission_to_Food_Standards_AustraliaNew_Zealand_
on_A549_High_Lysine_Corn_Draft_Assessment_Recommendation
6
This uncertainty is not adequately addressed in proposals to exclude some
products from regulatory oversight.
There are many reviews and official statements about the safety of foods from GE crops
(for example, see Box 5-1)…With regard to the issue of uncertainty, it is useful to note
that many of the favorable institutional statements about safety of foods from GE crops in
Box 5-1 contain caveats, for example: ‘no overt consequences,’ ‘no effects on human
health have been shown,’ ‘are not per se more risky,’ and ‘are not likely to present risks
for human health.’ Scientific research can answer many questions, but absolute safety of
eating specific foods and the safety of other human activities is uncertain. (NASEM 2016)
2.4. To regulate a technology proportional to risk requires knowing how the harm can
scale. This knowledge may seem easier to obtain for food than for environmental risk
assessment, but that is not assured. For example, different home preparation
traditions including different mixtures of foods contribute to the complexity of
assessing risk. Recalling the quote above by the US NASEM which acknowledges
the uncertainties that characterise the science, “[p]roportionality can only be relevant
to what is reliably known and quantifiable (i.e. due to case-by-case basis); the
possible adverse effects of genome edited [NBT] plants are far from reliably
knowable, including risks through scaling and across time.”
10
2.5. Nevertheless, provided that FSANZ were able to confirm that those using NBTs on
food have completed a credible examination of the product for unintended changes
and associated unintended biological characteristics, it is theoretically possible to
place some products into different categories with different assessment requirements.
2.5.1. Disappointingly, this theoretical possibility is already undermined by the
industry itself. An “argument in favor of equivalence testing is that the onus to
do high-quality, well-replicated experiments with sufficient statistical power is
placed on to those who wish to demonstrate the safety of GMOs” (van der Voet
et al. 2019), but it also incentivises cheating, or at least sloppiness. The most
recent demonstration is that of Recombinetics’ cattle. Following the company’s
publicly expressed confidence in its approach to screening unintended changes it
was later found to have overlooked unintended transgene insertions. The
industry has not yet earned the trust society can expect of a regulator relying on
voluntary compliance.
The developer of hornless cattle has retracted its claims about precision and purity of the
genome modifications (Carlson et al., 2016; Van Eenennaam et al., 2019) after FDA
scientists found that they were not accurate (Norris et al., 2020). The company initially
said that: “We have all the scientific data that proves that there are no off target effects”
(quoted in Regalado, 2020), but it overlooked, among other changes, about 4,000 new
10
European Network of Scientists for Social and Environmental Responsibility
https://ec.europa.eu/info/law/better-regulation/have-your-say/initiatives/13119-Legislation-for-plants-produced-
by-certain-new-genomic-techniques/F2743463_en
7
nucleotides inserted during the application of the new techniques, including antibiotic
resistance genes. (Heinemann et al. 2021)
2.5.2. Unfortunately, we also see little evidence from the history of FSANZ that
without legislative or political compulsion it will use its own discretion to
improve the reporting standards from manufacturers. For example, it does not
require the use of techniques that provide comprehensive identification of
unintended changes in its risk assessments despite this being a recommendation
from both the research community (Agapito-Tenfen et al. 2018; Heinemann et
al. 2011) and the US National Academies:
It is the change in the actual characteristics of the plant, intended and unintended, that
should be assessed for risks. Recent developments in -omics technologies have made
thorough assessments of those characteristics of plants attainable in the near future. Even
in their current state of development, the technologies could enable a tiered approach to
regulatory testing in which any new variety shown to have no new intended traits with
health or environmental concerns and no unintended alterations of concern in its
composition would be exempted from further testing (Figure S-3). The costs of -omics
methods are decreasing, but even current costs are low relative to the cost of other
components of regulatory assessments. (NASEM 2016)
2.6. For these and other reasons (set out below):
2.6.1. INBI does support (Option 3) a “revised and expanded process-based
definition for ‘gene technology’”. We do not support the definition that
FSANZ prefers.
2.6.2. INBI does not support “Product-based pre-market safety assessment
exclusions for certain foods” based on exclusion criteria focussed on food
characteristics alone. We do not believe that the proposed non-regulatory
approaches are a satisfactory way to mitigate risk.
2.6.3. We submit that the proposed product-based exclusions are actually process-
based exclusions in disguise. FSANZ is proposing to deregulate processes that
result in products that have characteristics similar to other products that may
have been created using arbitrarily deregulated processes, for example chemical
and radiation mutagenesis or heritable double-stranded RNA treatments, and
never assessed for risk. The product-based exclusion is therefore likely to lead to
risk creep.
2.6.4. INBI supports Option 3 with the deletion of the sentences “revise the
definition for ‘food produced using gene technology’ to include specific
product-based criteria for excluding certain foods from pre-market safety
assessment and approval as GM food. Foods not meeting all relevant exclusion
criteria would require an application to FSANZ.” Those sentences could be
replaced with “Foods produced by NBTs require an application to FSANZ.”
8
3. Product-based voluntary approaches are not future-proof
3.1. This quote from a submission to the European Commission on its consultation on
regulation of new techniques demonstrates precisely the same problem with
FSANZ’s framing of risk. “Several OECD countries including Canada, the US,
Japan, Australia, and Colombia are adopting similar, pragmatic approaches. At their
base, they recognize that new genomic techniques are no riskier than conventional
breeding and therefore should be managed accordingly.”
11
3.2. In contrast, the Norwegian Society of Rural Women frame the risk appropriately by
saying: “We are not against GMOs in general, but genetic engineering differs from
traditional breeding and processing in both radicalism and pace.”
12
This is similar to
Nobel Laurette Sydney Brenner’s framing when he said that (radicalism) “there is
now available a method which allows us to cross very large evolutionary barriers and
to move genes between organisms which have never before had genetic contact” and
(pace) the “essence is that we now have the tools to speed up biological change and if
this is carried out on a large enough scale then we can say that if anything can happen
it certainly will. In this field, unlike motor car driving, accidents are self-replicating
and could also be contagious” (Brenner 1974).
3.3. Conventional breeding is limited by the spontaneous mutation rate, generation time
of the organism, species, size of the organism, power of applicable intellectual
property rights instruments, and number of breeders. NBTs have far fewer
limitations. Their difference in radicalism and pace is, after all, why they have value
and concomitantly how they can cause harm.
3.4. The fundamental characteristic of technology is that it allows people to do things
faster and in a more concentrated way (Heinemann et al. 2021).3 The fundamental
source of harm from technology is that people can do certain things faster and in a
more concentrated way. Deregulation increases the number of people using the
techniques and lowers the expertise required to use them. Therefore, the reason to
regulate technology is to control the potential for harm from its use by people. A
focus on products of a technological process is a way to control harm from a
technology but it is not the only way.
3.4.1. For example, chemical and radiation mutagenesis is a technology because it
allows changes to be made to genes and organisms faster than what occurs by
conventional breeding, the latter relying on the spontaneous mutation rate. The
use of chemical and radiation mutagenesis is considered a gene technology in
11
Submission to the European Commission on its consultation Legislation for plants produced by certain new
genomic techniques by the Canadian Canola Growers Association (Janelle Whitley) 22 October 2021.
https://ec.europa.eu/info/law/better-regulation/have-your-say/initiatives/13119-Legislation-for-plants-produced-
by-certain-new-genomic-techniques_en
12
Norwegian Society of Rural Women https://ec.europa.eu/info/law/better-regulation/have-your-
say/initiatives/13119-Legislation-for-plants-produced-by-certain-new-genomic-techniques/F2743498_en
European Network of Scientists for Social and Environmental Responsibility
https://ec.europa.eu/info/law/better-regulation/have-your-say/initiatives/13119-Legislation-for-plants-produced-
by-certain-new-genomic-techniques/F2743463_en
9
the European Union and New Zealand, but organisms made using these
mutagens are (mainly) exempted from regulation (DoH 2018b). In 2006
Australia defined chemical and radiation mutagenesis as not a gene technology
(DoH 2018a).
13
3.4.2. The decision to define chemical and radiation mutagenesis as not a gene
technology but transgenesis and NBTs as gene technology is scientifically
inconsistent. It exposes a lack of understanding of the underlying purpose of
regulation to control adverse effects of technology. The impact of doing so is,
however, limited. This is not because chemical and radiation mutagenesis has no
scalable potential to cause harm. It is because the reagents of chemical and
radiation mutagenesis are controlled by other legislative instruments that restrict
access and require that they be used by highly trained personnel in containment
facilities, and require registration of the products (Heinemann et al. 2021).
P1055 does not create these other controls for NBTs.
3.5. We do not believe that it is valid to compare what can be done using technology to
the history of spontaneous DNA changes that have occurred in the genomes of
organisms people eat over evolutionary time. First, both people and food have been
changing over evolutionary time. Mutations that arose spontaneously in nature
resulted in foods that may have been better, worse, or irrelevant to us. Our genetic
ancestors may also have evolved (genetically or through learning) to overcome the
effects of mutations that lessened the value of these organisms to us as food. Second,
foods produced using gene technology do not have evolutionary time lines. Our
highly concentrated food industries can inadvertently distribute something harmful to
large numbers of people in a short time unlike at any other period in human
evolution. Consequently we disagree with the conclusion that “Conventional food is
therefore a suitable benchmark for assessing the risks from NBT foods” or other
gene technology techniques.
3.6. FSANZ knows how little product it takes to contaminate the world food supply with
unapproved and therefore potentially unsafe food, which is why it no longer issues
split decisions with the Office of the Gene Technology Regulator. On the global
scale, production of Starlink and BT10 maize, LL rice, and Roundup Ready wheat
were miniscule. In some cases, only a few hectares. Yet these products spread
worldwide and a few, decades later, are still appearing. Even the scale of small scale
tinkerers becomes relevant to food safety. The worrying message from adoption of
P1055 is that tinkering is safe because the process is safe.
3.7. P1055 is not addressing non-genetic risks to food safety. Risk is also a function of
the concentration of the food production and distribution sector and its capacity to
13
Why Australia took this decision is not apparent to us. Proposal P1055 is a way to rectify this inconsistency
provided that it could be made inclusive of specifically deregulated gene technology techniques. If regulatory
expediency were the reason it was defined out of legislation, clearly that was not the only option because as
proposed in P1055, organisms made using chemical or radiation mutagenesis could be exempted from further
risk assessment rather than use arbitrary exclusions. We note that New Zealand has defined some chemical
mutagenesis as and some as not creating a GMO for purposes of risk assessment.
10
use monopoly power intellectual property rights – that conventional breeding has not
had – to ramp-up harm at unprecedented scale. If conventional foods were a suitable
benchmark for assessing the genetic risks from NBT foods (which we do not accept),
then FSANZ should consider that infectious disease (see Brenner’s quote, above) is
the other appropriate benchmark for assessing the modern risks from NBT foods.
3.8. Deregulation is de facto scale change in the mutation rate of both food and
inseparable organisms that occur in food.
14
The scale is increased in magnitude by
the number of people who use the tools and the number of organisms exposed. That
number can and will increase with products that allow such work in situ, through
topical applications (Heinemann and Walker 2019). In the proposed product-based
and voluntary compliance framework proposed, only the intended food organisms
will be evaluated. How many off-target effects of the inseparable fungi inadvertently
sprayed with a ZFN or a Cas9-guide mixture intended as a herbicide on a “farm” of
10,000 hectares is FSANZ suggesting that society accept as safe without review?
3.9. We offer a potential solution to this problem by suggesting that it is not the technique
of gene technology used that is determinative of the risk category. In the first
instance it is how the technique is used. We present that idea below but with this
caution. The intention of FSANZ may be to reduce the use and expense of risk
assessment, but that would only be possible if the technology had not changed.
Obviously, it has at least in its ability to scale. Therefore, as the US NASEM
observed, risk assessment may need to change for safety to stay the same or improve.
“[f]uture GE crops…could greatly expand the use of agricultural biotechnology in the
development of biofuels, forestry restoration, and industrial bioprocessing and thus
potentially lead to new risk-assessment and risk-management issues.” (NASEM 2016).
3.10. Exclusion criteria are not supported by us. However it may be possible to
group uses into categories defined by relevant critical control points. Two examples
follow.
3.10.1. A risk assessment category might apply to all development done in
containment and all development that was from chemical and radiation
mutagenesis. This category could include all genetically engineered livestock
and plants of the kind that already have been approved by FSANZ, and could
apply to all future development using NBTs this way. For practical purposes, the
members of this category could be split into sub-categories for risk assessment.
In category 1A are the products of chemical and radiation mutagenesis that
require no further assessment provided that they were also listed with the
International Atomic Energy Agency. This is because of other regulatory
restrictions on the use of chemical and radiation mutagens. In category 1B are all
other products that will be evaluated according to the requirements of law and to
evolving standards of international guidance, such as Codex Alimentarius.
Proposals for this should be developed and consulted by FSANZ, but we also
14
For example, microorganisms and bits of insects.
11
encourage adoption of -omics based techniques for hazard identification as
recommended by the US NASEM.
3.10.2. A different risk assessment category might apply to any outdoor use of gene
technology and to release of Living (genetically) Modified Organisms.
Therefore, it may require thorough and new approaches to risk assessment and
risk management which should be developed and consulted by FSANZ.
However, it may also be possible to further sub-categorise members of this set
with case-specific assessments.
4. Definition criteria
4.1. The USDA definition preferred by FSANZ is inadequate to cover some current and
also future/pending techniques or actually new technologies.
4.2. The length of the definition in Australian (and New Zealand) legislation as listed in
Table 2 of Supporting Document 3 illustrates the failures of its semantic approach to
defining gene technology. Australia has already inconsistently defined some
techniques as not being gene technology despite them potentially conforming to the
USDA definition. Thus, we do not believe that the USDA or any other definition
based on other undefined/contested terms either will be sufficient or future-proof.
4.3. Instead, we advocate a heuristic definition that describes the properties of gene
technology. We submit that a new draft definition should be developed for further
consultation.
4.3.1. The definition should not exclude technology that increases the scale of
potential harm with use.
15
4.3.2. The definition should not be limited to nucleic acids. The use of any agent
intended to accelerate the overall or specific mutation rate and rate of creating
new phenotypes should be included.
16
It is unclear why only one kind of agent
(nucleic acids) for introducing genetic change is identified by FSANZ as
relevant when the biological and other risks are the genes that are changed.
4.3.3. The definition should not be limited to the persistence of the causative agent,
nucleic acid or otherwise, in a product for the product to be within scope.
15
Advancements in nucleic acid delivery also allow proteins to be taken up in situ, including proteins that may
have mutagenic activities (Heinemann and Walker 2019). In this continuum resides what is commonly
understood to be genetic engineering, but does not necessary require the “use of recombinant, synthesised or
amplified nucleic acid to modify or create a genome” because of arbitrary definitions also used in practice for
the words “genome”, “recombinant”, “amplified” and “synthesise” as well as the ability to substitute other kinds
of molecules for nucleic acids to achieve the end result. Spraying protein mutators such as ZFNs or TALENs in
a formulation that allows them to be taken into cells can have the same outcome as spraying small chemical
mutagens or radioactive material. The latter is prevented by other legislation because of potential to cause harm
(Heinemann et al. 2021). The same potential harm should be recognised for mutagens that are proteins or other
non-nucleic acid molecules.
16
Note that treatments to alter traits en masse by manipulating genes is a pathway of scalable harm for long
lived perennial plants and even fresh fruits and vegetables post-harvest, even if the organism does not reproduce
(Heinemann 2019).
12
4.3.4. If the word genome is to be used, then it should be defined in a way that is
comprehensive for any molecular basis of inheritance of traits because
inheritance is a pathway to scalable harm. We should not, for example, be
arguing in the future about whether or not making changes to replicating RNA
elements in the cytoplasm of fungi is genetic engineering because of semantic
disputes over whether or not they are part of the “genome”.
4.3.5. The definition should capture all technology that can result in the change of
biological or chemical characteristics, phenotypes/traits by intervention in the
pathways and molecules that determine the biological or chemical,
phenotypes/traits of organisms, viruses and other replicating elements (e.g.,
plasmids, prions and epigenes). We should not, for example, be arguing in the
future about whether or not making life-long changes to gene expression in fruit
trees by application of double-stranded RNA is a gene technology.
Nāku iti nei, nā,
Dr Jack A Heinemann
Professor of Molecular Biology and Genetics
17
8 November 2021
17
This submission and any accompanying documents are provided in accordance with the University of
Canterbury Critic and Conscience of Society and Academic Freedom Policy (2018) as the author’s expert
opinion and not as statements of the opinion of the University of Canterbury. It was externally reviewed by an
expert in the field.
13
Bibliography
Agapito-Tenfen, S.Z.; Okoli, A.S.; Bernstein, M.J.; Wikmark, O.-G.; Myhr, A.I. Revisiting
risk governance of GM plants: the need to consider new and emerging gene-editing
techniques. Front Plant Sci 2018;9
Brenner, S. Evidence for the Ashby Working Party. Cold Spring Harbor Laboratory Library;
1974; https://search.wellcomelibrary.org/iii/encore/record/C__Rb2000070?lang=eng
Cantani, A. Benefits and concerns associated with biotechnology-derived foods: can
additional research reduce children health risks? Eur Rev Med Pharmacol Sci
2006:197-206
COGEM. The status of oligonucleotides within the context of site-directed mutagenesis.
COGEM advice and report.; 2010;
DoH. Technical Review of the Gene Technology Regulations 2001 Decision Regulation
Impact Statement. Department of Health; 2018a;
https://www1.health.gov.au/internet/ogtr/publishing.nsf/Content/A0E750E72AC140C
4CA2580B10011A68E/$File/Decision%20RIS.pdf
DoH. The Third Review of the National Gene Technology Scheme. Department of Health;
2018b; https://www1.health.gov.au/internet/main/publishing.nsf/Content/gene-
technology-review
Heinemann, J.A. Should dsRNA treatments applied in outdoor environments be regulated?
Environ Int 2019;132:104856
Heinemann, J.A.; Kurenbach, B.; Quist, D. Molecular profiling — a tool for addressing
emerging gaps in the comparative risk assessment of GMOs. Env Int 2011;37:1285-
1293
Heinemann, J.A.; Paull, D.J.; Walker, S.; Kurenbach, B. Differentiated impacts of human
interventions on nature: Scaling the conversation on regulation of gene technologies.
Elem Sci Anth 2021;9
Heinemann, J.A.; Walker, S. Environmentally applied nucleic acids and proteins for purposes
of engineering changes to genes and other genetic material. Biosafety Health
2019;1:113-123
Itakura, K.; Riggs, A.D. Chemical DNA synthesis and recombinant DNA studies. Science
1980;209:1401-1405
NASEM. Genetically Engineered Crops: Experiences and Prospects. Washington, DC: The
National Academies Press; 2016
Nordlee, J.A.; Taylor, S.L.; Townsend, J.A.; Thomas, L.A.; Bush, R.K. Identification of a
Brazil-nut allergen in transgenic soybeans. N Engl J Med 1996;334:688-692
van der Voet, H.; Goedhart, P.W.; Lazebnik, J.; Kessel, G.J.T.; Mullins, E.; van Loon, J.J.A.;
Arpaia, S. Equivalence analysis to support environmental safety assessment: Using
nontarget organism count data from field trials with cisgenically modified potato.
Ecol Evol, 2019;9:2863-2882
ResearchGate has not been able to resolve any citations for this publication.
Article
Full-text available
Biotechnology describes a range of human activities in medicine, agriculture, and environmental management. One biotechnology in particular, gene technology, continues to evolve both in capacity and potential to benefit and harm society. The purpose of this article is to offer a policy bridge from unproductive descriptions of gene technology to useful methods for identifying sources of significant biological and socioeconomic risk in complex food systems. Farmers and the public could be voluntarily and involuntarily interacting with new techniques of genome editing and gene silencing in entirely new ways, limiting the usefulness of previous gene technology histories to predict safety. What we believe is a more consistent, verifiable, and practical approach is to identify the critical control points that emerge where the scale effects of a human activity diverge between risk and safety. These critical control points are where technical experts can collaborate with publics with different expertise to identify and manage the technology. The use of technical terminology describing biochemical-level phenomena discourages publics that are not technical experts from contesting the embedded cultural perspectives and uncertainty in “scientific” concepts and prejudice the risk discourse by ignoring other issues of significance to society. From our perspective as gene technologists, we confront the use of pseudo-scale language in risk discourse and propose an escape path from clashes over whether risks that arise spontaneously (from nature) can be perfectly mimicked by gene technology to a discussion on how to best control the risks created by human activity. Scale is conceptually implicit and explicit in gene technology regulation, but there is no agreement about what scales are most useful to managing risk and social expectations. Both differentiated governance (risk-tiered) and responsible research and innovation models could accommodate the critical control points mechanism that we describe.
Article
Full-text available
In this article we summarize the development of vehicles for penetrating living cells, tissue and organisms with nucleic acids (DNA and RNA) and proteins that damage or repair DNA. The purpose in doing so is to provide an assessment of the potential for these technologies to unintentionally cause harm to human health or the environment or to be re-tasked with an intention to cause harm. Two new types of biological-molecule-based products are being developed for use in medicine, agriculture and food production or preservation. The first type are genetically modified organisms, such as those that express bio-pesticides. They produce molecules and that are difficult to alter at scale after release. Products of this type are usually evaluated by both food and environmental regulators. The second type comprises topical chemical or physical agents. Most of these are in pre-commercial testing phase. Topically applied products use nucleic acids and/or proteins wherein the active biological is transferred by contact, ingestion or inhalation. From a survey of the research and patent literature we suggest that chemical formulations and physical manipulations that can be used to ferry nucleic acid and protein cargo into cells, tissues or organisms could be assembled de novo or repurposed from existing commercial products and loaded with proteins and/or nucleic acids designed using publicly available genome sequences. Biological actives may evade risk assessment and regulatory review because they are often excluded from the category of hazardous chemicals and are actively being excluded as agents of genetic modification. This emerging gap in oversight could lead to either dual use appropriation or unintended harm to human health or the environment.
Article
Full-text available
The New Zealand Environmental Protection Authority (EPA) issued a Decision that makes the use of externally applied double-stranded (ds)RNA molecules on eukaryotic cells or organisms technically out of scope of legislation on new organisms, making risk assessments of such treatments in the open environment unnecessary. The Decision was based on its view that the treatment does not create new or genetically modified organisms and rests on the EPA's conclusions that dsRNA is not heritable and is not a mutagen. For these reasons EPA decided that treatments using dsRNA do not modify genes or other genetic material. I found from an independent review of the literature on the topic indicated, however, that each of the major scientific justifications relied upon by the EPA was based on either an inaccurate interpretation of evidence or failure to consult the research literature pertaining to additional types of eukaryotes. The Decision also did not take into account the unknown and unique eukaryotic biodiversity of New Zealand. The safe use of RNA-based technology holds promise for addressing complex and persistent challenges in public health, agriculture and conservation. However, by failing to restrict the source or means of modifying the dsRNA, the EPA removed regulatory oversight that could prevent unintended consequences of this new technology such as suppression of genes other than those selected for suppression or the release of viral genes or genomes by failing to restrict the source or means of modifying the dsRNA.
Article
Full-text available
New and emerging gene-editing techniques make it possible to target specific genes in species with greater speed and specificity than previously possible. Of major relevance for plant breeding, regulators and scientists are discussing how to regulate products developed using these gene-editing techniques. Such discussions include whether to adopt or adapt the current framework for GMO risk governance in evaluating the impacts of gene-edited plants, and derived products, on the environment, human and animal health and society. Product classification or definition is one of several aspects of the current framework being criticized. Further, knowledge gaps related to risk assessments of gene-edited organisms—for example of target and off-target effects of intervention in plant genomes—are also of concern. Resolving these and related aspects of the current framework will involve addressing many subjective, value-laden positions, for example how to specify protection goals through ecosystem service approaches. A process informed by responsible research and innovation practices, involving a broader community of people, organizations, experts, and interest groups, could help scientists, regulators, and other stakeholders address these complex, value-laden concerns related to gene-editing of plants with and for society.
Article
Assessing the risks of genetically modified organisms (GMOs) is required by both international agreement and domestic legislation. Many view the use of the “omics” tools for profiling classes of molecules as useful in risk assessment, but no consensus has formed on the need or value of these techniques for assessing the risks of all GMOs. In this and many other cases, experts support case-by-case use of molecular profiling techniques for risk assessment. We review the latest research on the applicability and usefulness of molecular profiling techniques for GMO risk assessment. As more and more kinds of GMOs and traits are developed, broader use of molecular profiling in a risk assessment may be required to supplement the comparative approach to risk assessment. The literature-based discussions on the use of profiling appear to have settled on two findings: 1. profiling techniques are reliable and relevant, at least no less so than other techniques used in risk assessment; and 2. although not required routinely, regulators should be aware of when they are needed. The dismissal of routine molecular profiling may be confusing to regulators who then lack guidance on when molecular profiling might be worthwhile. Molecular profiling is an important way to increase confidence in risk assessments if the profiles are properly designed to address relevant risks and are applied at the correct stage of the assessment.
Article
Chemically synthesized DNA has been used in many recombinant DNA studies. These uses have included the total synthesis and cloning of functional genes, the cloning and expression of natural genes, and editing of changing genes by directed mutation.
Benefits and concerns associated with biotechnology-derived foods: can additional research reduce children health risks?
  • S Brenner
Brenner, S. Evidence for the Ashby Working Party. Cold Spring Harbor Laboratory Library; 1974; https://search.wellcomelibrary.org/iii/encore/record/C__Rb2000070?lang=eng Cantani, A. Benefits and concerns associated with biotechnology-derived foods: can additional research reduce children health risks? Eur Rev Med Pharmacol Sci 2006:197-206
The status of oligonucleotides within the context of site-directed mutagenesis
COGEM. The status of oligonucleotides within the context of site-directed mutagenesis. COGEM advice and report.; 2010;
Technical Review of the Gene Technology Regulations 2001 Decision Regulation Impact Statement. Department of Health
  • Doh
DoH. Technical Review of the Gene Technology Regulations 2001 Decision Regulation Impact Statement. Department of Health; 2018a;
The Third Review of the National Gene Technology Scheme. Department of Health
  • Doh
DoH. The Third Review of the National Gene Technology Scheme. Department of Health; 2018b; https://www1.health.gov.au/internet/main/publishing.nsf/Content/genetechnology-review