Access to this full-text is provided by Springer Nature.
Content available from Ethical Theory and Moral Practice
This content is subject to copyright. Terms and conditions apply.
Vol.:(0123456789)
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-021-10239-8
1 3
Realism andPolitical Normativity
MattSleat1
Accepted: 20 September 2021 /
© The Author(s) 2021
Abstract
A prevailing understanding of realism, chiefly among its critics, casts realists as those who
seek a ‘distinctively political normativity’, where this is interpreted as meaning nonmoral
in kind. Moralists, on this account, are those who reject this and believe that political nor-
mativity remains moral. Critics have then focused much of their attention on demonstrating
that the search for a nonmoral political normativity is doomed to fail which, if right, would
then seem to fatally undermine the realist endeavour. This paper makes the case that cast-
ing the difference between realism and moralism in these terms is a mistake, one which
overlooks the substantial body of realist work which is clear that it has no such aspirations
to develop a nonmoral political normativity. The hope is that in drawing attention to this
mistake a line can be drawn under these unhelpful debates, and we can move on to more
fruitful constructive and critical discussions between realists and their critics.
Keywords Realism· Moralism· Political normativity
Much hay has been made in recent years of political normativity. This issue has come to be
seen as central to and characteristic of the ‘new’ political realism that has emerged within
the last decade or so. On a prevailing account, realists are those who seek a ‘distinctively
political normativity’, where this is interpreted as meaning nonmoral in kind, and critics
of realism have focused much of their attention on attempting to demonstrate that such
an ambition is doomed to fail. If this is right as a broad description of where much of the
debate between realism and its critics has ended up, then it would seem, to put it this way,
that the possibility of nonmoral political normativity is the hill on which realists must be
willing to die. For if it turns out that a nonmoral political normativity is impossible or inco-
herent then political realism itself seems fatally undermined.
This paper makes the case that casting the debate between realists and moralists in terms
of the prospects of a nonmoral political normativity is a mistake. It is a mistake which has
largely been the result of a misinterpretation of realism’s ambitions by its critics, and in
* Matt Sleat
m.sleat@sheffield.ac.uk
1 Department ofPolitics andInternational Relations, University ofSheffield , Sheffield, USA
Published online: 28 October 2021
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice (2022) 25:465–478
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
1 3
the first section we shall examine Jonathan Leader Maynard and Alex Worsnip’s ‘Is There
a Distinctively Political Normativity?’ (2018), which explicitly casts the realism/moral-
ism debate in these terms, to demonstrate such misunderstandings at work.1 To be fair to
such critics, and as we shall see in the second section, there is a strand of realist thought
which does seek a nonmoral political normativity and so has sought to do battle on those
grounds. But that represents a very particular understanding which does not characterise
realism per se and, very importantly, it is not the strand critics target in their discussions.
More ‘mainstream’ realism, so to speak, is very clear that the commitment is to a notion
of political theory that gives politics ‘greater’ autonomy from morality, an ambition which
(however expressed and understood by individual realists) does not depend on demarcat-
ing moral and nonmoral political normativities. Indeed, realists have often been explicit
that such a demarcation is not part of their project. In the final section, we shall revisit
Bernard Williams’ realist theory, often taken to be the main influence in this realist quest
to identify a nonmoral political normativity, to show that the origins of the realist/moral-
ist distinction turned not on the demarcation of different normativities but on how politi-
cal theory understands the relationship between morality and political practice. Though
Williams’ work has been hugely influential, realism is a ‘distinctive family’ of approaches
related by variations on recognisably realist claims about the distinctiveness or autonomy
of politics. Critics therefore ought to engage with particular realist arguments rather than
force realism into a false unity around a commitment that very few actually hold. As such,
the debates around nonmoral political normativity have been a largely unnecessary and
unhelpful detour which has detracted attention, both constructive and critical, from poten-
tially more fruitful debates.
1 Nonmoral Political Normativity
According to Leader Maynard and Worsnip, and in one of the most recent and fully-devel-
oped critiques of realism, realists contend ‘that political normativity is its own distinctive
kind of normativity, independent of moral normativity. A key source for this view is found
in the political writings of Bernard Williams, subsequently developed by several others’
(2018, p. 757). Whereas moralists take political normativity to be a form of moral norma-
tivity, realists believe, Leader Maynard and Worsnip claim, that political normativity is not
a kind of moral normativity at all, but is an independent, distinctive, nonmoral normativity
in its own right (2018, p. 759). And the purpose of their paper is to demonstrate that ‘the
attempt to place a distinctively political, nonmoral normativity at the core of that [realist]
agenda—at least on the basis of the arguments thus far offered—is a mistake’ (2018, p.
757).
Having framed the debate between realists and moralists in these terms, Leader May-
nard and Worsnip admit frustration that they have been unable to find clear arguments from
realists in favour a distinctive and nonmoral political normativity (2018, pp. 759, 786).
They do nevertheless identify two claims which they take as (unsuccessful) realist attempts
at a demarcation of morality from politics with the purpose of underpinning that distinctive
nonmoral political normativity. The first is that realists sometimes ‘implicitly characterise
1 A similar argument to Leader Maynard and Worsnip’s can be found elsewhere. See, for example, Erman
and Möller (2015, Forthcoming); Miller (2016), Estlund (2017).
466 M. Sleat
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
1 3
the moral domain as including only the principles that govern private interactions between
individuals’(2018, p. 760). Politics is therefore nonmoral because, by definition, it deals
with the interactions of political rather than private agents. The second and related claim is
that there are principles, concepts, considerations, values, and actors, which are distinctive
of the political domain, and political normativity is nonmoral because it deals specifically
with those principles, concepts, etc. (2018, pp. 760–63).
Given that the aim of these passages is to evidence how realists themselves understand
or frame their disagreement with moralists in terms of nonmoral and moral political nor-
mativities, surprisingly few references are provided to corroborate this claim. There are
five references to only four sources,2 three of which were published in or before 2010.3
That might be sufficient if these sources did indeed show that this is how realists (not
just these particular realists) contrast their approach to moralism. Unfortunately, they do
not corroborate Leader Maynard and Worsnip’s claim insofar as it is hard to see that the
authors are attempting to make the sort of demarcation between a nonmoral and a moral
political normativity at all.
Mark Philp’s paper ‘What is to be Done? Political Theory and Political Realism’ (2010)
appears twice in these references. The argument of Philp’s paper is that liberal ideal theory
is a poor guide for the evaluation of political conduct because it tends to focus more on
identifying and analysing the scope and implications of values and principles, and we need
to attend also (not instead) to the practicalities of political action and choice. He stresses
that amending our focus in that way can still underpin a normative theory of politics. But
at no point does he seek to make a distinction between a nonmoral political and a moral
normativity. Indeed, if we attend to Philp’s monograph on this topic published three years
before the paper, we find an explicit endorsement at the beginning of the book of the
thought that
… the relationship between moral philosophy and politics is not deductive, … many
of the abstract values found in moral philosophy and much liberal political theory are
profoundly inflected by their interpretation, implementation, and realisation in politi-
cal action. This view accords the political process a substantial degree of autonomy
and an identity and character of its own. Politics, and political conduct in this view,
needs to be understood largely, although not entirely, on its own terms, and those
terms concern the political virtues and qualities of the actors involved (Philp, 2007,
p. 4 - emphasis added).
Evaluating political conduct requires ‘identifying the standards that are intrinsic and
internal to it [politics], together with some sense of the conditions under which those stand-
ards may come to have, or may lack, ethical weight’ (Philp, 2007, p. 2—emphasis added).
Such nuanced pronouncements seem hard to square with Leader Maynard and Worsnip’s
2 Excluding the passing reference to Hans J. Morgenthau who, as an IR realist, lies somewhat beyond the
scope of their paper and this.
3 2010 being relevant here as this was when the special issue of the European Journal of Political Theory
was published which did much to inaugurate the revival of interest in realist thought. Indeed, two of the
referenced pieces – those by Newey and Philp – are from that special issue. Similarly, in their contribution
to this special issue, Erman and Möller also cite four papers from that EJPT issue (including those by Philp
and Newey) as evidence of the realist commitment to a nonmoral political normativity (Forthcoming, p. 2).
It is unfortunate that both that paper and the one under discussion here pays relatively little attention to the
substantial body of realist work published after 2010 given, as we shall shortly see, much of this is explicit
and clear that the development of a nonmoral political normativity is not an ambition.
467Realism and Political Normativity
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
1 3
interpretation of Philp as seeking to show that as ‘private morality is unquestionably a part
of morality, then, political normativity cannot be a part of morality’ (2018, p. 777).
Glen Newey’s ‘Two Dogmas of Liberalism’ is also referenced in support of their
account of how realists understand their project. It is true that part of Newey’s concern
in that paper is to resist the thought that ‘the norms which justify an individual in acting
a certain way carry over to the sphere of collective action’ (2010, p. 450). But that is part
of a broader attack specifically on what he calls ‘Kantian reductivism’ which (he believed)
attempts to reduce political normativity to morality and in particular retain the notion that
morality trumps reasons of all other kinds at either the individual or collective level. What
the argument does not and is not supposed to show is that because morality applies to the
private domain so political normativity must be nonmoral. At the most it would show that
political normativity cannot be moral in that Kantian reductive sense. Indeed, Newey is
clear that even if he is right about this that would not demand ‘a wholesale abandonment of
Kantianism, in attempting to construct a serviceable notion of political normativity’ (2010,
p. 450). In fact, the more realistic (‘holistic’) view that he goes on to develop in the sec-
ond half of the paper is explicitly Kantian insofar as ‘One has to regard oneself as free in
relation to acts of authorisation as a condition of being incorporated with others’ (2010,
p. 458). Political holism rejects ‘strong foundationalism, as a set of (say, moral) norms,
resting on intuitively compelling premises, which determine basic political and civil rights
and obligations, the design of key institutions and procedures, and the distribution of basic
goods’ (2010, p. 459). This is perfectly consistent with the project of his monograph, After
Politics, where he is clear that he is criticising the methodological assumption of the ‘sov-
ereignty of morality’ which says ‘that moral considerations take precedence over others,
and therefore the task of political philosophy is to attempt the project of political design
guided by what theory takes to be its fundamental moral commitment or value – justice,
autonomy, rights, equality, and so on’ (2001, pp. 106–07). Does rejecting the strong foun-
dational claims of moral norms equate with a nonmoral form of political normativity?
Newey does not say. Even if it does, Newey does not think his political holism follows
from the rejection of Kantian reductivism (it is explicitly ‘asserted’ in the place of the two
dogmas of liberalism he rejects) (2010, p. 459). One thus suspects distinguishing between
a moral and a nonmoral political normativity was not quite his concern as Leader Maynard
and Worsnip suggest.4
4 The final reference Leader Maynard and Worsnip provide is to a very brief piece by Rob Jubb and Enzo
Rossi (2015) As we shall see in the following section, this piece and Rossi’s work more generally can legiti-
mately be understood in terms of attempting to demarcate a nonmoral political normativity. Hence we can
leave discussion of it until then. However, it is worth saying that it is far from clear that Leader Maynard
and Worsnip are right to present Jubb and Rossi’s argument against moralism as turning at all on corporate-
to-individual-reductivism. The only passage on the page they reference which could potentially be seen as
relevant here would seem to be the following: ‘Indeed, in a sense realists seem to be less cynical than mor-
alists. They believe our politics, if far from perfect, is not straightforwardly tyrannical, and hope to use its
combination of coercion and consent to generate norms to govern it. Moralists on the other hand demand
that politics accord with their private moral views and tend to see it as an arena of brute force when it does
not, denying that the act of providing an order itself has a normativity’ (457 – emphasis added). If this is
the passage they are referring to then it is hard to read this as regarding corporate-to-individual-reductiv-
ism because ‘private’ here clearly does not refer to relations between private individuals but something like
personally-held views of what should be done politically, a reading that Leader Maynard and Worsnip also
seem to accept (footnote 42, p. 771). As such, though we can say that Jubb and Rossi are advocating non-
moral political normativity it is not for the reasons Leader Maynard and Worsnip ascribe to them.
468 M. Sleat
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
1 3
The second but related claim Leader Maynard and Worsnip ascribe to realists in their
attempt to render substantive the distinction between moral and nonmoral political norma-
tivity is that the latter must deal specifically with the principles, concepts, considerations,
values, and actors which are distinctive of the political domain. This is indeed a staple real-
ist claim, and a passage from Williams’ ‘From Freedom to Liberty: The Construction of
a Political Value’ is used to demonstrate this (political philosophy, he says, ‘must use dis-
tinctively political concepts, such as power, and its normative relative, legitimation’ (2005,
p. 77)). Does Williams intend that claim about the specificity of the political domain
to ground a nonmoral political normativity? It is certainly true that Williams wanted to
explore how one could construct freedom as a political value in that paper. But he is careful
as to how he presents the task.
In the sense that concerns these discussions, freedom is a political value … I am
going to suggest that this point itself, when it is properly understood, has a very sig-
nificant effect on the kind of construction we should be trying to achieve. In par-
ticular, we must take seriously the point that because it is a political value, the most
important disagreements that surround it are political disagreements. What kinds or
registers of politics are involved, what the relevant understandings of politics will be,
will depend on which disagreements are at issue – those within our own societies,
for instance, or those with other societies. But our overall construction of freedom
as a political value must allow for the fact that it is a political value to be central and
intelligible (2005, pp. 76–7).
Note two things: Firstly, Williams says nothing here about trying to demarcate a politi-
cal from a moral normativity, let alone a nonmoral political from a moral political norma-
tivity. Secondly, he is clear that he is trying to bring to the fore the significance of what
it means to think of freedom as a political value. There is no implication that this can or
that we should even want this to exhaust all that can be said of freedom as a value. Indeed,
it is consistent with his general genealogical approach that we are not going to be able to
offer even a coherent understanding of freedom which does not take into account its ethical
developments and dimensions throughout history. It is far from clear, therefore, that cit-
ing this passage or paper is sufficient to show that Williams was engaged in an attempt to
demarcate a nonmoral political normativity from morality.5
Whatever Philp, Newey and Williams were trying to do in the passages Leader Maynard
and Worsnip cite, it was not what they claim they were trying to do. That they found it dif-
ficult to identify clear accounts of the terms of a dispute between those who think political
normativity is nonmoral on one side and those who think it is moral on the other is prob-
ably because that does not capture the nature of the disagreement in the first place. Like
explorers who find that the topography of a region bears little resemblance to their map and
blame the mountains and rivers for being in the wrong place, the difficulty with their enter-
prise is that they start with a mischaracterisation of realism and then express bafflement
that they cannot find a precise statement by any realists of a position that they do not hold.
5 A greater appreciation of Williams’ broader thought gives us good reason to suspect that he would not be
engaged in such a project of demarcating normativities at all, a point we shall return to in the final section.
469Realism and Political Normativity
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
1 3
2 Distinctively Political Normativity astheIrreducibility ofPolitics
toMorality
Though Leader Maynard and Worsnip set themselves the question ‘is there a distinctively
political normativity?’, they interpret ‘distinctively’ to mean independent such that a politi-
cal normativity must be nonmoral to qualify and then find that realism falls short. Clearly,
and by definition, it is a sufficient condition for a political normativity to be distinctive
from morality that it be nonmoral. But it is not a necessary condition and the notion of
distinctiveness need not imply that. Things can be distinctive but still in various ways simi-
lar, and in that sense there is no requirement of full separateness. We might say ‘That is a
distinctively Wagnerian opera’ without meaning that it has no comparable characteristics
with an opera by Verdi or Puccini. In the same way, political normativity can be distinctive
without being nonmoral. That is an obvious point. Hence it raises the question why critics
have assumed that talk of political normativity indicates a commitment to nonmoral politi-
cal normativity. Leader Maynard and Worsnip are not alone in thinking that this is a realist
commitment. Where has this idea come from?
The first thing to say is that there is an important sense in which they are right: it is
true that there is one strand of realist thought which does seek to carve out a distinctively
nonmoral political normativity, just not the strand that is the target of most criticisms. In
our overview of the state of the realist debate published in 2014, Enzo Rossi and myself
distinguish between two ways in which a realist theory can still be normative depending on
how you understand the relationship between politics and morality. The stronger version
demands full autonomy from morality, claiming ‘that it is possible to derive normative
political judgments from specifically political values – a position resting on the view that
not all values are moral values, plus the more controversial claim that such political val-
ues can and should guide politics, whereas moral values are ill-suited to that task’ (Rossi
and Sleat, 2014, p. 690).6 This stronger version is more inspired by the work of Raymond
Geuss than Williams (recall Leader Maynard and Worsnip claim that the latter was the ‘key
source’ of the aspiration for a distinctive nonmoral political normativity), is closely aligned
to critical theory, and now strongly associated with the ‘radical’ realists.7 A prominent
member of these radicals is Rossi himself who has explicitly equated moralism with the
view that ‘normative standards that appropriately regulate personal interactions should also
regulate political life’ and realism with a normativity whose source is nonmoral (Rossi,
2019).8 But while this represents a rather energetic strand of contemporary realist work it
is nevertheless both somewhat idiosyncratic and certainly unrepresentative of realism as a
whole. Critics have a target, then, if they wish to critique a realism which is committed to
nonmoral political normativity, but it is a quite specific one and would need to be repre-
sented as such in a way that it currently is not.9
This stronger version of realism is contrasted by Rossi and myself with a weaker variant:
6 As they go on to note: ‘Whether and how either or both components of that claim can be sustained is an
issue high on the agenda of realists and of their critics. The controversy largely turns on whether moral nor-
mativity is eliminable from political philosophy’.
7 See, for example, Geuss, 2008, 2014.
8 See also Jubb and Rossi (2015), Prinz (2016), Prinz and Rossi (2017), Raekstad (2018).
9 For instance, in their contribution to this special issue, Erman and Möller cite Rossi’s work, including the
piece discussed above co-authored with Jubb, as evidence of a general realist commitment to politics as ‘an
autonomous, independent domain with its own evaluative standards’ (Erman and Möller, Forthcoming, p.
2).
470 M. Sleat
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
1 3
there is a place for morality in politics but [it] seeks, in Williams’ words to expli-
cate ‘an approach which gives greater autonomy to distinctively political thought’.
On this view, there is not such a stark contrast between politics and morality, and
indeed morality may have a role to play in providing a source of political normativ-
ity, yet it remains important to appreciate the manner in which politics remains a dis-
tinct sphere of human activity, with its own concerns, pressures, ends and constraints
which cannot be reduced to ethics (nor law, economics, religion, etc.) (2014, p. 690).
Advocates of the weaker thesis more often talk in terms of politics being ‘distinct’ from
morality, or of it being ‘irreducible’ to morality. They might still also emphasise the ‘autonomy’
of politics, though they do not mean by that the sort of full or complete autonomy from morality
we find with the stronger version of the thesis. As Alison McQueen points out, autonomy in this
context often just means something like politics not being reducible to other fields or domains
(2018, p. 246).10 To take some illustrative examples from the realist literature:
While this [claim that politics is a distinct sphere of human activity] can often be
somewhat overstated as demonstrating the ‘autonomy of the political’ from all other
domains, morality, economics, law, etc., such that politics has its own completely
unique internal logic, the claim is better stated that there must be some space within
a theoretical account of politics that can recognise the distinctiveness of the political
sphere, that it does have its own character, purposes and means, while also acknowl-
edging that it sits in a series of complex relationships with other human activities.
What realism rejects is any understanding of politics in which the distinctiveness of
politics is overlooked (Sleat, 2014b, p. 32).11
[R]ealists are committed to the idea that we should not reduce political philosophy
(or politics) to moral philosophy (or morality) because they stress the “distinctive-
ness and autonomy of the political from other spheres” (Hall, 2017, p. 284).12
[Realism is] a family of approaches to the study, practice, and normative evaluation
of politics that (a) affirms the autonomy (or, more minimally, the distinctiveness) of
politics; (b) takes disagreement, conflict, and power to be ineradicable and constitu-
tive features of politics; (c) rejects as ‘utopian’ or ‘moralist’ those approaches, prac-
tices, and evaluations which seem to deny these facts; and (d) prioritizes political
order and stability over justice (or, more minimally, rejects the absolute priority of
justice over other political values) (McQueen, 2017, p. 297).13
10 See also Sleat (2018, pp. 6, 7). The use of terms such as ‘external’ may also have been unhelpful in
this regard (a term Williams did not use to discuss the relationship between politics and morality, inciden-
tally), and was sometimes employed, especially in early realist work, so as to distinguish political realism
as a form of theorising which excludes anything that cannot be cast as ‘internal’ to politics or which sought
the legitimation of political power in somehow exclusively political and nonmoral reasons which Erman
and Möller dubbed ‘hyperautonomy’ (see for instance Galston, 2010, p. 387; Sleat, 2010, p. 495, 2014a,
pp. 315, 321; Erman and Möller, 2015, p. 227). That this is based on a misreading of Williams has been
authoritatively demonstrated, and the term is more appropriately used to draw attention to the realist claim
that certain values, principles, or standards can be understood as arising from within the practice of politics
itself and/or that the relationship between politics and morality in political theory ought not to be conceived
as simply the application of a set of moral principles to political practice (see Hall, 2015).
11 See also Sleat (2013, pp. 63–66; 2014a, p. 315; 2016c, pp. 253–54; 2016b, p. 173; 2016a, p. 68, 2018).
12 See also Hall and Sleat (2017, p. 278), Hall (2020, p. 9).
13 See also McQueen (2020) (first published and available online in 2016).
471Realism and Political Normativity
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
1 3
Most realist work falls into this ‘weaker’ category. Indeed, we might think of it as the
‘mainstream’ realist position.14 And, as such, we find the literature littered with claims and
arguments to the effect that politics must have some (greater) autonomy from morality,
whether expressed in terms of autonomy, distinctiveness and/or irreducibility (them not
being synonymous with one another) alongside an acknowledgement of the relevance of
morality to our normative thinking about politics. That this goes almost totally unacknowl-
edged by those who prefer to cast realists as if they all shared the stronger ambition of a
nonmoral political normativity is therefore surprising.
There are, of course, different ways in which the claims and arguments associated with
this weaker version of realism can and have been made (compare Philp and Newey above,
for instance, both of whom Rossi and myself list, contra Leader Maynard and Worsnip,
as advocates of this weaker form of autonomy). But the point for our purposes is simply
that however the weaker thesis is expressed and understood, it both represents something
like the mainstream realist position and cannot plausibly be interpreted as involved in the
endeavour of establishing the grounds for a nonmoral political normativity. We might still
want to ask just how distinct political thought needs to be in order to be meaningfully dis-
tinctive as political thought if full autonomy is not the aim. But then it is not clear that
there is going to be any independent threshold that needs to be met and against which we
can assess such distinctiveness, and hence the endeavour looks somewhat misguided and
unnecessary.15 The more interesting question is whether realists can demonstrate that their
approach generates some interesting insights about politics which would be unavailable to
us otherwise (a point we shall return to shortly).
3 The Realist Family
If we were to tell a genealogy of the debate between realism and its critics there is good
reason to suspect it would begin with either a misunderstanding to the effect that realism
wanted to develop a nonmoral way of thinking about politics (specifically in relation to
legitimacy) or over-emphasising the significance of the remarks of those who did make
such claims as representative of realism as a whole. These were then systematised into
claims about the sources of moral and political normativity which came to be accepted by
advocates and critics as central to the distinction between realism and moralism. Realism
thus became the quest for distinctively political normativity; moralism the rejection that
nonmoral political normativity is coherent or possible. And as these terms, realism and
moralism, were introduced by Williams it surely matters that this was not how he initially
cast that distinction.
The contrast that Williams draws between political moralism and political realism turns
on how political theory understands the relationship between morality and political prac-
tice. In rejecting moralism he says that we reject ‘the basic relation of morality to poli-
tics as being that represented either by the enactment model or by the structural model’
(2005, p. 8—emphasis in the original) in which political theory formulates the principles,
concepts, ideals, etc. that we then seek to express through political action (enactment) or
sets down the moral conditions of co-existence under power that politics must recognise
14 That Williams’ work too falls into this category will be discussed in the following section.
15 A point also made by Jubb (2019, p. 362). 27/09/2021 20:10:00.
472 M. Sleat
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
1 3
in practice (structural) (2005, p. 1). We should reject this model because it is wrong to
view those moral principles or conditions as independent of or prior to political practice.
Rather we need to appreciate that they are historical developments whose existence, and
our commitment to them, is deeply entwined with the politics that they seek to speak to.
The difficulty with moralism is that it fails to recognise how political morality actually is.
Or, put differently, what is wrong with political moralism is not that it represents a form of
political theory that ‘starts’ outside of politics, but that it thinks it does. Once we properly
recognise the entanglement of politics and morality, we will see that when we come to the
question of the foundations of liberalism for instance, that liberal values or principles can-
not ground the liberal state because they are, in an important sense, products of the liberal
state and the same contingent historical forces that created it (2005, p. 8).16 This recogni-
tion of the historical contingency of liberal values (as with all values) is potentially deeply
destabilising and can undermine our confidence in them. In order to stabilise our confi-
dence in those values Williams suggests that we can turn our attention to the ways in which
they address genuine human needs as represented in the ‘first political question’ (to be free
from the terror, torture, cruelty, etc. associated with disorder and instability) and in such a
way that makes sense to us as a form of legitimate order, which is to say that it provides an
acceptable answer to the basic legitimation demand (BLD), given the universal truth about
politics that ‘might is not right’ (i.e. it can be understood as a solution to that problem and
not just the perpetuation of cruelty through force). Assuming this is possible and the basic
legitimation demand can be met, and Williams thought it could at least in the case of the
liberalism of fear, then we have reason to remain confident in liberal values despite recog-
nition of their historical contingency.17
There is an important sense in which the first political question and the BLD are politi-
cal. They speak to some of the ends that we standardly think politics pursues, the means
that it employs, and the issues that these give rise to (that the use of force in the creation of
order can become tyrannical). To be sure, Williams thought that we could understand the
basic demand that a regime provide a legitimation of its rule in ways that do not presume
some particular moral principle or value (e.g. as we are autonomous persons the state needs
to demonstrate that its constitutional essentials are such that I could reasonably accept,
reject, be expected to accept, etc.), and, in that sense, it does represent an evaluative dimen-
sion of politics that we can see as coming from within the practice of politics itself. Is it
moral? Williams is ambivalent whether we call it moral or not: ‘If it is, it does not repre-
sent a morality which is prior to politics’ (2005, p. 5). What matters is that it does not rep-
resent the ‘basic relation of morality to politics’ that characterises political moralism. He
was not at all interested in strongly demarcating between political and moral normativities.
17 This paragraph draws heavily on the excellent analyses of Williams by Hall and Sagar (Hall, 2014, 2015,
2020; Sagar, 2016; Hall and Sleat, 2017). Of course, all of this can be disputed on its own terms. But that so
many critical engagements with Williams focus almost exclusively on ‘Realism and Moralism in Political
Theory’, possibly extended to possibly one or two further essays from In the Beginning was the Deed, as
if that is sufficient to understand his thinking on realism is difficult to comprehend given a) he is a thinker
renowned for leaving much for the reader to do in piecing together his views from across many different
writings; b) Hall, Sagar, Owen (2018), and others have published several authoritative pieces which provide
and make clear the necessity of placing Williams’ realism in the broader context of his ethical thinking.
16 Hence it is likely that many realists are going to be deeply sceptical of the ecumenical position advocated
by Erman and Möller in their contribution to this special issue that accepts a role for both moral and politi-
cal values and norms as part of the ‘justificatory grounding’ of political theories. The problem here will not
be the ecumenicism of values (which we have seen realists readily endorse) but that they do not think either
moral or political values can provide justificatory grounding for political practices they are the product of.
473Realism and Political Normativity
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
1 3
In fact, such an ambition seems profoundly at odds with Williams’ philosophical approach
such that it seems not just strange but incongruous to attribute such an endeavour to him.
The term ‘normativity’ does not appear much in Williams’ work. He talks instead in Eth-
ics and the Limits of Philosophy, for instance, of ‘considerations’ that apply to the Socratic
question of ‘How should I live?’. He explicitly rejects the thought that we need to decide
whether this question is to be given a moral or nonmoral answer, though we can ask ‘what
should I do from an ethical point of view?’, or from an economic perspective, and so on,
but ‘At the end of all that, there is the question “what should I do, all things considered?”
There is only one kind of question to be asked about what to do, of which Socrates’ is a
very general example, and moral considerations are one kind of consideration that bear on
answering it’ (2011, pp. 6–7). And there is, he thought, no value in defining what counts as
a specifically ‘ethical’ consideration (‘It does no harm that the notion is vague’). It is the
particular demands of morality, the Peculiar Institution, which requires a sharp demarca-
tion between the moral and nonmoral. Without that demand, however, we can see that there
are a range of considerations which fall under the notion of the ethical, and recognise why
that range cannot be clearly delimited (2011, pp. 7–8).
For Williams, moralism and realism are differentiated by how they conceive the rela-
tionship between morality and political practice. Where moralism assumes a ‘basic rela-
tionship’ between morality and political practice in which the political theorist conceives
of themselves as developing the moral principles, values, concepts, etc. that politics is to
then either enact or which will structure the limits of politics’ rightful exercise of power,
realism seeks a more complex account of that relationship and, in doing so, gives appro-
priate space and weight to that which is distinctive about political practice in our theories.
There are, as Hall and myself have pointed out (2017), numerous routes one can take to
reach realist conclusions, and clearly not all realists are signed up to Williams’ particu-
lar account. All share, however, a dissatisfaction with ways in which contemporary politi-
cal theory conceives of the relationship between political practice and morality, and have
critiqued contemporary figures such as G.A. Cohen, David Estlund, Robert Nozick, and
John Rawls, as well as raised concerns about the terms of debates or positions such as
revisionist just war theory and luck egalitarianism, on these grounds. And all seek a way
of doing political theory which is more appropriately sensitive to what is distinctive about
politics as a human activity. They differ, naturally, as to precisely what a more realistic the-
ory should look like, the concepts it should use, the questions it should ask, and quite how
the normative prescriptions of theory should be filtered through or aligned to the realities
of politics. The fact of the matter is that one cannot talk about ‘realism’ at a level of gen-
erality too long before one has to start making distinctions between different ‘realisms’.18
McQueen is surely right that realism is best conceived as a distinctive family of approaches
that share the commitments she listed and we quoted in section two: the distinctiveness
of politics; disagreement, conflict, and power as ineradicable and constitutive features of
politics; rejection of ‘utopianism’ and ‘moralism’; the priority of order. It is distinctive
because there are clearly other approaches and positions that reject or do not share these
18 It is telling in that regard that in the several overviews of realist thought that have been published in
recent years, including those of a more critical nature, part of what they do is set out competing typologies
of realism, between, for instance, strong and weak realisms (Rossi and Sleat, 2014), detachment and dis-
placement (Baderin, 2014), new and old (Nardin, 2017), ordo-, contextual, and radical (Rossi, 2019).
474 M. Sleat
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
1 3
commitments19; it is a family because those commitments can be developed and expressed
in different ways (2017, p. 297). It is understandable that this might make realism a frus-
tratingly ‘moving target’ for its critics, but the right response to that would be to engage
with particular arguments rather than impose a false coherence around a single unifying
argument which all realists are supposed to be signed up to.20
Thinking about realism as a family helps us also get a better view of the sort of insights
that a realist approach to political theorising can generate. Here the proof is clearly in the
eating rather than in the recipe, and one cannot do much more than point at particular inter-
ventions and invite critics of realism to engage with those and judge for themselves the
merits of the approach. To highlight just an illustrative few where the authors have explic-
itly characterised their arguments as realist or in keeping with realist themes: Samuel Bagg
offers an explicitly realist defence of democracy against the recent slew of epistemic chal-
lenges by shifting the emphasis away from thinking about competitive elections and uni-
versal suffrage as bestowing authority on the demos as the wisest possible sovereign but
on to how democracy denies power to various elites and helps resists state capture. The
best way of responding to democracy’s epistemic critics is to emphasise power over wis-
dom (2018); Robert Jubb provides a realist defence of non-intrinsic egalitarianism on the
grounds that it is compatible with acknowledging the ubiquity of disagreement about val-
ues and interests in politics and, furthermore, that such egalitarianism might be a require-
ment of legitimacy for us ‘now and around here’ (Jubb, 2015); Alison McQueen defends
the motivational power of fear in prompting responses to global climate change (forthcom-
ing); Bernardo Zacka employs an ethnographic approach to provide a richer understanding
of the various psychological and institutional pressures faced by ‘street-level bureaucrats’,
the plural considerations they must remain sensitive to, and how these often pull in differ-
ent directions (2017);And both Andrew Sabl and myself(2013) sketch out very different
views of what a more realistic liberalism wouldlook like, the former stating that it would
emphasise:
a focus on agents, their decisions, and their strategic contexts or situations; a sense
of the pervasive and permanent relevance of interests, conflicts and power to politics
and to political theory; respect for instrumental rationality and comfort with hypo-
thetical imperatives; a love of ugly facts and political complexity; an awareness that a
crucial part of being powerless is standing especially in need of institutional – rather
than philosophical – restraints on power; and an insistence that, given that no set of
political reasons will seem ‘legitimate’ to everyone, state action rests partly on the
authority of institutions rather than the persuasiveness of arguments, and citizen poli-
tics uses pressure [sic] (strikes, boycotts, shaming and ostracism) as well as reasons
(2017, p. 349).21
19 Another familiar critique of realism denies its distinctiveness: its central commitments are so vague or
general that there seem to be few theorists who would not qualify as realists. If that were true then it would
be quite peculiar that realism has found itself the subject of much substantive critique, some of it based on
fair or judicious readings of realist arguments. Moreover, and as mentioned earlier, realists have undertaken
much work to demonstrate their distinctiveness through critical engagement with central figures in contem-
porary political theory.
20 For a discussion along the same lines see Hall, 2020, pp. 170–74.
21 Other examples would include Philp on corruption (2018) and care for the aged (2016), Bell on poverty
(2018), Newey on toleration (2013), Bull on mercy (2019), Hall on political integrity (2018), Bellamy on
constitutionalism (2007) and democratic leadership (2018), Galston on the ‘darker passions’ (2018), and
Sagar on how economic reality has to constrain theoretical accounts of freedom (2019).
475Realism and Political Normativity
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
1 3
There is also plenty of work being done by those who have not (and maybe might not)
align themselves with realism but which nevertheless represents good examples of the sort
of themes or approaches that realists have been endorsing. They might not call themselves
‘realists’ but we can see that they might still bear some familiarly realist family resem-
blances. These would include, for instance, Teresa Bejan’s defence of ‘mere’ civility as a
vital virtue in helping us live together in conditions of permanent difference and disagree-
ment (2017); Jeremy Waldron’s insistence on the importance of the study of institutions
as ways in which we house, frame, and manage our disagreements about social ideals and
orchestrate what is to done about whatever aims we can agree upon (2016), and; Jacob T.
Levy’s arguments against ideal theory (2016) and prevailing forms of teleological thinking
in contemporary political theories (2020).22
Of course, realists may not have succeeded in showing that we should reject the prevail-
ing accounts of the relationship between morality and politics which it finds so problematic
in contemporary political theory. Nor might it have a compelling account of how political
theory should go on in a more realistic key. But it matters what realists’ arguments are and
are not being put in the service of. In this regard the debate about a distinctive nonmoral
political normativity has been an unfortunate and unnecessary distraction.
Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License,
which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long
as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Com-
mons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article
are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the
material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not
permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly
from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http:// creat iveco mmons. org/ licen ses/ by/4. 0/.
References
Baderin A (2014) Two forms of realism in political theory. Eur J Polit Theory 13(2):132–153
Bagg S (2018) ‘The power of the multitude: answering epistemic challenges to democracy. Am Polit Sci
Rev 112(4):891–904
Bejan T (2017) Mere civility: disagreement and the limits of toleration. Harvard University Press, New York
Bell D (2018) Security and poverty: on realism and global justice. In: Sleat M (ed) Politics recovered: realist
thought in theory and practice. Columbia University Press, New York, pp 296–319
Bellamy R (2007) Political constitutionalism: a republican defence of the constitutionality of democracy.
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Bellamy R (2018) The paradox of the democratic prince: Machiavelli and the neo-Machiavellians on ideal
theory, realism, and democratic leadership. In: Sleat M (ed) Columbia University Press, New York. pp
166–93
Bull M (2019) On mercy. Princeton University Press, Oxford
Erman E, Möller N (2015) Political legitimacy in the real normative world: the priority of morality and the
autonomy of the political. Br J Polit Sci 45(1):215–233
Erman E, Möller N (Forthcoming) Distinctively political normativity in political realism: unattractive or
redundant. Ethical Theory Moral Pract
Estlund D (2017) Methodological moralism in political philosophy. Crit Rev Int Soc Polit Philos
20(3):385–402
22 We could also include in this list Bernard Yack’s work on nationalism (2012), Rahul Sagar on secrecy
and whistleblowing (2014), Mark Pennington on ‘robust political economy’ (2011), and John McCormick’s
‘Machiavellian Democracy’ (2011).
476 M. Sleat
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
1 3
Galston W (2010) Realism in political theory. Eur J Polit Theory 9(4):385–411
Galston W (2018) Anger, humiliation, and political theory: bringing the darker passions back in. In: Sleat M
(ed) Columbia University Press, New York. pp. 93–113
Geuss R (2008) Philosophy and real politics. Princeton University Press, Oxford
Geuss R (2014) A world without why. Princeton University Press, Oxford
Hall E (2014) Contingency, confidence, and liberalism in the political thought of Bernard Williams. Soc
Theory Pract 40(4):545–569
Hall E (2015) Bernard Williams and the basic legitimation demand: a defence. Polit Stud 63:466–480
Hall E (2017) How to do realistic political theory (and why you might want to). Eur J Polit Theory
16(3):283–303
Hall E (2018) Integrity in democratic politics. Br J Polit Int Relat 20(2):395–408
Hall E (2020) Value, conflict, and order: Berlin, Hampshire, Williams and the realist revival in political
theory. University of Chicago Press, Chicago
Hall E, Sleat M (2017) Ethics, morality and the case for realist political theory. Crit Rev Int Soc Polit
Philos 20(3):278–295
Jubb R (2015) The real value of equality. J Polit 77(3):679–691
Jubb R (2019) On what a distinctively political normativity is. Polit Stud Rev 17(4):360–369
Jubb R, Rossi E (2015) Political norms and moral values. J Philos Res 40:455–458
Leader Maynard J, Worsnip A (2018) Is there a distinctively political normativity? Ethics 128:756–787
Levy JT (2016) There is no such thing as ideal theory. Soc Philos Policy 33(1/2):334–353
Levy JT (2020) Contra politanism. Eur J Polit Theo 19(2):162–183
McCormick JP (2011) Machiavellian democracy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
McQueen A (2017) Political realism and the realist “Tradition.” Crit Rev Int Soc Polit Philos
20(3):296–313
McQueen A (2018) The case for kinship - classical realism and political realism. Politics recovered:
realist thought in theory and practice. Columbia University Press, New York, pp 243–269
McQueen A (2020) Political realism and moral corruption. Eur J Polit Theory 19(2):141–161
McQueen A (2021) The wages of fear? Toward fearing well about climate change. Philosophy and cli-
mate change. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Miller D (2016) In what sense must political philosophy be political? Soc Philos Policy 33(1–2):155–174
Nardin T (2017) The new realism and the old. Crit Rev Int Soc Pol Philos 20(3):306–319
Newey G (2001) After politics: the rejection of politics in contemporary liberal philosophy. Palgrave,
Basingstoke
Newey G (2010) Two dogmas of liberalism. Eur J Polit Theo 9(4):449–465
Newey G (2013) Toleration in political conflict. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Owen D (2018) Realism in ethics and politics: Bernard Williams, political theory, and the critique of
morality. Politics recovered: realist thought in theory and practice. Columbia University Press, New
York, pp 73–92
Pennington M (2011) Robust political economy: Classical liberalism and the future of public Policy.
Edward Elgar, Cheltenham
Philp M (2007) Political conduct. Harvard University Press, New York
Philp M (2010) What is to be done? Political theory and political realism. Eur J Polit Theo 9(4):466–484
Philp M (2016) Justice, realism, and family care for the aged. Soc Philos Policy 33(1/2):413–433
Philp M (2018) Politics and the “Pure of Heart” realism and corruption. In: Sleat M (ed) Politics recov-
ered: realist thought in theory and practice. Columbia University Press, New York, pp 194–217
Prinz J (2016) Raymond Geuss’ radicalization of realism in political theory. Philosophy & Social Criti-
cism 42(8):777–796
Prinz J, Rossi E (2017) Political realism as ideology critique. Critical Review of International and Social
Political Philosophy 20(3):334–348
Raekstad P (2018) Realism, utopianism, and radical values. Eur J Philos 26(1):145–168
Rossi E (2019) Being realistic and demanding the impossible. Constellations 26:638–652
Rossi E, Sleat M (2014) Realism in normative political theory. Philos Compass 9(10):689–701
Sabl A (2017) Realist liberalism: an agenda. Crit Rev Int Soc Pol Phil 20(3):349–364
Sagar P (2016) From scepticism to liberalism? Bernard Williams, the Foundations of Liberalism and
Political Realism. Political Studies 64(2):368–384
Sagar P (2019) Liberty, nondomination, markets. Review of Politics 81(3):409–434
Sagar R (2014) Secrets and leaks: the dilemma of state secrecy. Princeton University Press, Oxfordshire
Sleat M (2010) Bernard Williams and the possibility of a realist political theory. Eur J Polit Theo
9(4):485–503
Sleat M (2013) Liberal realism: a realist theory of liberal politics. Manchester University Press, Manchester
477Realism and Political Normativity
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
1 3
Sleat M (2014a) Legitimacy in realist thought: between moralism and “Realpolitik.” Political Theory
42(3):314–337
Sleat M (2014b) Realism, liberalism and non-ideal theory or, are there two ways to do realistic political
theory? Political Studies 64(1):27–41
Sleat M (2016a) The politics and morality of the responsibility to protect: beyond the realist/liberal
impasse. International Politics 53(1):67–82
Sleat M (2016b) The value of global justice: realism and moralism. Journal of International Political
Theory 12(2):169–184
Sleat M (2016c) What is a political value? Political philosophy and fidelity to reality. Soc Philos Policy
33(1–2):252–272
Sleat M (2018) Politics recovered - on the revival of realism in contemporary political theory. In: Sleat M
(ed) Politics recovered - realist thought in theory and practice. Columbia University Press, New York,
pp 1–25
Waldron J (2016) Political political theory. Harvard University Press, New York
Williams B (2005) In the beginning was the deed: realism and moralism in political argument. Princeton
University Press, Oxford
Williams B (2011) Ethics and the limits of philosophy. Routledge, London
Yack B (2012) Nationalism and the moral psychology of community. University of Chicago Press, Chicago
Zacka B (2017) When the state meets the street: public service and moral agency. Belknap Press, London
Publisher’s Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and
institutional affiliations.
478 M. Sleat
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
Terms and Conditions
Springer Nature journal content, brought to you courtesy of Springer Nature Customer Service Center
GmbH (“Springer Nature”).
Springer Nature supports a reasonable amount of sharing of research papers by authors, subscribers
and authorised users (“Users”), for small-scale personal, non-commercial use provided that all
copyright, trade and service marks and other proprietary notices are maintained. By accessing,
sharing, receiving or otherwise using the Springer Nature journal content you agree to these terms of
use (“Terms”). For these purposes, Springer Nature considers academic use (by researchers and
students) to be non-commercial.
These Terms are supplementary and will apply in addition to any applicable website terms and
conditions, a relevant site licence or a personal subscription. These Terms will prevail over any
conflict or ambiguity with regards to the relevant terms, a site licence or a personal subscription (to
the extent of the conflict or ambiguity only). For Creative Commons-licensed articles, the terms of
the Creative Commons license used will apply.
We collect and use personal data to provide access to the Springer Nature journal content. We may
also use these personal data internally within ResearchGate and Springer Nature and as agreed share
it, in an anonymised way, for purposes of tracking, analysis and reporting. We will not otherwise
disclose your personal data outside the ResearchGate or the Springer Nature group of companies
unless we have your permission as detailed in the Privacy Policy.
While Users may use the Springer Nature journal content for small scale, personal non-commercial
use, it is important to note that Users may not:
use such content for the purpose of providing other users with access on a regular or large scale
basis or as a means to circumvent access control;
use such content where to do so would be considered a criminal or statutory offence in any
jurisdiction, or gives rise to civil liability, or is otherwise unlawful;
falsely or misleadingly imply or suggest endorsement, approval , sponsorship, or association
unless explicitly agreed to by Springer Nature in writing;
use bots or other automated methods to access the content or redirect messages
override any security feature or exclusionary protocol; or
share the content in order to create substitute for Springer Nature products or services or a
systematic database of Springer Nature journal content.
In line with the restriction against commercial use, Springer Nature does not permit the creation of a
product or service that creates revenue, royalties, rent or income from our content or its inclusion as
part of a paid for service or for other commercial gain. Springer Nature journal content cannot be
used for inter-library loans and librarians may not upload Springer Nature journal content on a large
scale into their, or any other, institutional repository.
These terms of use are reviewed regularly and may be amended at any time. Springer Nature is not
obligated to publish any information or content on this website and may remove it or features or
functionality at our sole discretion, at any time with or without notice. Springer Nature may revoke
this licence to you at any time and remove access to any copies of the Springer Nature journal content
which have been saved.
To the fullest extent permitted by law, Springer Nature makes no warranties, representations or
guarantees to Users, either express or implied with respect to the Springer nature journal content and
all parties disclaim and waive any implied warranties or warranties imposed by law, including
merchantability or fitness for any particular purpose.
Please note that these rights do not automatically extend to content, data or other material published
by Springer Nature that may be licensed from third parties.
If you would like to use or distribute our Springer Nature journal content to a wider audience or on a
regular basis or in any other manner not expressly permitted by these Terms, please contact Springer
Nature at
onlineservice@springernature.com
Available via license: CC BY 4.0
Content may be subject to copyright.