ArticlePDF Available

Abstract

Wittgenstein’s new understanding of meaning as use has far reaching implications in religion and religious belief. The meaningfulness of language does not depend on the referent but on the actual use of it in the human context. The variety of language uses makes religious language legitimate, and the social character of language makes clear the role of training in religious belief. The characteristic features of religious belief can be summarized as follows: It is an unshakable commitment devoid of evidences and arguments, and it is reasonable only within its framework and grounded on the religious form of life. The rituals that are part of religious beliefs are symbolic and expressive. The existential concerns of human beings reveal a common spiritual nature enabling us to understand other religions and cultures as mirrored in our own humanity.
166 INTERFERENCE: Journal of Language, Literature, and Linguistics Vol.1, No.2, August 2020
LUDWIG WITTGENSTEIN:
LANGUAGE-GAME AND
RELIGIOUS BELIEF
Peter. O. O. Ottuh, Onos Godwin Idjakpo
Delta State University, Abraka, Delta State, Nigeria
Email: ottuhpeter@gmail.com
Abstract. Wittgenstein’s new understanding of
meaning as use has far reaching implications in
religion and religious belief. The meaningfulness
of language does not depend on the referent but
on the actual use of it in the human context. The
variety of language uses makes religious language
legitimate, and the social character of language
makes clear the role of training in religious belief.
The characteristic features of religious belief can
be summarized as follows: It is an unshakable
commitment devoid of evidences and arguments,
and it is reasonable only within its framework and
grounded on the religious form of life. The rituals
that are part of religious beliefs are symbolic and
expressive. The existential concerns of human
beings reveal a common spiritual nature enabling
us to understand other religions and cultures as
mirrored in our own humanity.
Keywords: Ludwig Wittgenstein; Language-Game;
Religious Belief.
INTERFERENCE
Journal of Language,
Literature, and
Linguistics
E-ISSN: 2721-1835
P-ISSN: 2721-1827
Submitted: November 2nd, 2020
Accepted : December 3rd, 2020
Ludwig Wittgenstein: Language-Game And Religious Belief Ottuh & Idjakpo (166-181) 167
INTRODUCTION
The linguistic analysis of the Tractatus results in the picture theory of
meaning. The structure of language reveals the structure of reality, for language is
founded on the bedrock of reality. We can observe a decisive change in
Wittgenstein’s philosophical reflection on language and meaning in the later period
of his thought. There is a move from a static view of language to a dynamic one as
an activity and as grounded upon something other than an independent reality.
Also, there is a shift from linguistic form to linguistic function in his transitional
period. In his later philosophy, language is not seen as directly referring to reality in
itself, but is viewed as an activity within a social context. It is founded on an
ungrounded way of action. It is life - form of life - which is not founded on
something more fundamental - that is the fundament. Form of life is the ground of
language and meaning. The logical form of the Tractatus is replaced by form of life
that bridges the gap among language, thought and reality.
In Wittgenstein's earlier philosophy, we have the image of a bedrock with a
stable foundation, but here we have an image of a riverbed with its flexibility. The
plurality of languages is not given once and for all, but new language-games come
into existence and others may disappear. This change in the theory of meaning in
the later period made a tremendous impact on his view of religion and religious
beliefs. The distinction of saying and showing in the early philosophy makes it clear
that religion belongs to the realm of showing and cannot be expressed. Whatever
can be expressed is expressed in propositions. Propositions express only fact;
religious belief is not a fact, therefore inexpressible. Later, under the impact of his
new theory of meaning, Wittgenstein changed his views on religion and religious
discourses. The meaning of religious propositions is to be understood in the
background of the language game and form of life.
This work attempts to trace Wittgenstein’s understanding of religious
belief on the basis of his revised view of language and its functioning. He maintains
that religion, religious belief and the meaning of religious statements have to be
determined in the background of specific language games and forms of life. For
Wittgenstein, the meaning of religious language involves utility within a context.
Every word is to be used in its original home to be meaningful (Shabbir 2010).
Therefore, the first part of this work deals with his notion of the language game and
form of life, and the following section will be an application of these notions to
religion and religious belief. The second section will deal directly with the nature of
religion and religious belief on the basis of Philosophical Investigations, some of
Wittgenstein’s lectures and notes in this regard.
THE CONCEPT OF THE LANGUAGE-GAME
Wittgenstein's later philosophy and his new theory of meaning are founded
on the concept of the language-game. Whatever the genesis of the concept
“language game,” it is introduced first in The Blue and the Brown Books and
frequently used in most of his later works. It is not, however, an easy task to give an
explicit idea of what the language-game is. Wittgenstein did not give any clear
exposition of it. The numerous examples given by the author do not explicate the
168 INTERFERENCE: Journal of Language, Literature, and Linguistics Vol.1, No.2, August 2020
concept, and scholars differ in their views. The language-game could be seen, as an
analogy to describe language. In his attempt to describe a complete language,
Wittgenstein describes the circumstance of the use for linguistic expressions. To
explain what language is, he brings forth the analogy of a game. The game analogy
has become a novel technique of philosophical analysis especially in linguistic
analysis (Tanney 1994: 997).
Can we compare language with a game? Though game and language are
divergent in many respects, there are some philosophically important points on
which they agree. Rules determine a game, and language is determined by its own
rules. This can be taken as a starting point in the comparison of language with a
game. The meaning of a word is not determined by the object it stands for, but is
determined by the rules governing its operation. Sentences are formed out of
words according to combinatorial rules, and their use in the speech act is specified
by the rules. The use of instruments is another inevitable characteristic of both a
game and language. Words are the instruments we use in language. Moreover, the
use of different words in different contexts gives rise to different meanings.
Therefore, setting is very important for language as for every game; without a
setting we cannot play a game. “Like any other game, a language-game is ‘played’ in
a setting” (Rono 2018). The use and purpose, role and function, are important
features that play a central role in Wittgenstein’s philosophy. The language-game
may be defined functionally as follows: “language game is a system of operational
rules, which necessarily determines the functions of linguistic signs through the
application of the rules” (Vinokurov 2018: 56). This opens up the necessity of
looking at the new understanding of meaning, linguistic functions and rule
following. Together they present a dynamic picture of language. Wittgenstein has
used the language-game in a variety of ways as in Philosophical Investigations:
Review the multiplicity of language-game in the following examples, and in
others: Giving order, and obeying them, describing the appearance of an object, or
giving its measurement, constructing an object from a description (a drawing),
reporting an event, speculation about an event, forming and testing a hypothesis,
presenting and presenting the results of an experiments in the tables and diagrams,
making up a story and reading it, play-acting singing catches, guessing riddles,
making a joke; telling it. Solving a problem in practical arithmetic, translating from
one language into another, asking, thanking, greetings, praying (Nagl 2017: 654).
Since language games are used as signs in contexts, there are innumerable
kinds of language games depending on the contextual use of words. There can be
different kinds of sentences, and the same sentence can have a different meaning in
different contexts. Multiple language games can be differently categorized, such as
pure and impure depending on the content and involvement of factors. In a pure
language game, according to Pitcher, Wittgenstein includes pure speech activities
such as telling a joke or reporting an event whereas in an impure language game
there are some extra-linguistic factors involved such as "builders game." However,
the distinction between these two kinds of language games is a matter of degree.
Language-games can also be categorized into real and imaginary language games
such as the imaginary builders game. They can be religious or non religious
Ludwig Wittgenstein: Language-Game And Religious Belief Ottuh & Idjakpo (166-181) 169
language-games. As K. C. Pandey maintains, there is no rigid compartmentalization
among these categories, and they can depend on each other. For example, the
religious language-game depends on the ordinary language game since the terms
and composition of the religious language-game happens in the background of day
to day life (Phillips 2017: 149).
Wittgenstein, in his later thought, tried to come out of his atomistic
thought on meaning to a coherent and holistic understanding of meaning. Frege's
idea of the context principle, that words have meaning within a sentence, was an
inspiration for Wittgenstein. However, Wittgenstein's holistic understanding of
meaning goes far beyond Frege's understanding of breaking the closed system of
propositions to a larger and broader setting of cultural practices and social behavior
that make up human life. Words find their meaning within their position in the
system. Words attain meaning within the language-game against the background of
human life (Mulhall 2011). If words are detached from any particular language-game
and its background, meaning will change. "A meaning of a word is a kind of
employment of it. For it is what we learn when word is incorporated into our
language ... when the language-game changes, then there is a change in concepts,
and with the concepts the meaning of words change” (Morra 2019: 5).
LANGUAGE-GAME AND FORM OF LIFE
Though the two important concepts of the language game and form of life
cannot be identified, there exists an affinity between them. It is important to note
that language cannot be imagined outside the human context. Meaning is rooted in
the context of human activity. Speaking of language is part of human activity. When
this theory of meaning is applied to religion, the meaning of religious language is
seen to be rooted in religious practices. The treatment of religious belief, as a
distinctive language-game, takes for granted religion as a form of life, which
Wittgenstein never identified though he is very close to it when he said, “Why
shouldn’t one form of life culminate in an utterance of belief in a Last Judgement?”
What is important, as basis, is form of life for Wittgenstein. For he says, “only in the
stream of thought and life do words have meaning” (Lerner 1995:173). “A smiling
mouth smiles only in a human face” (Kidd 2012: 583). The significance of something
depends on the surroundings. Religious belief has meaning within the surroundings
of religion. We have a belief only in the background of a system of beliefs. That
system of beliefs is what we call religion, which has become so natural by way of
practice. Wittgenstein cites that it is the practice which gives words their life.
“Practice gives the words their sense” (Lerner 1995:85). Therefore, a sense of
religious belief comes from use, not from assertions. Religious belief is grounded on
religious practices. Therefore, the search for the sense of religious belief leads to
the discussion of the situation in which it is used and how it is used and practiced.
'THEOLOGY AS GRAMMAR'
Wittgenstein has used a parenthetical remark in the Philosophical
Investigations "theology as grammar." This expression is to be understood in the
background of his later philosophy of language and grammar that are associated
with the concepts of the language-game and form of life. One could observe a
170 INTERFERENCE: Journal of Language, Literature, and Linguistics Vol.1, No.2, August 2020
development of thought about grammar in Wittgenstein from Tractatus to
Philosophical Investigations. For Wittgenstein, philosophical inquiries are
investigations into the grammar of language. Grammar in Philosophical
Investigations replaces logical symbolism of Tractatus. This change in approach is
not a result of a single leap. However, it is a gradual change in the significance of
grammar in the construction of Philosophical Investigations. The goal of Tractatus
was to set a limit to language and thought through logical symbolism. Wittgenstein
developed a calculus conception of grammar with its autonomy of rules to establish
the limits of language and thought in Philosophical Grammar and complimented it in
Big Typescript. He developed an anthropological view of grammar through The Blue
and the Brown Book to Philosophical Investigations (Phillips 2017: 140).
The concept of grammar is one of the key notions in his later thought. As
far as language is concerned, grammar is generally associated with the structure
(syntax) of language. However, Wittgenstein uses grammar as associated with
meaning (semantics) in his later thought. For him, grammar refers to an
investigation of content (semantics) rather than form (syntax). The concept of
language and grammar is best understood in relation to the use of language in a
particular context (Rono 2018: 60). The concepts of grammar, meaning and use are
intimately connected. Grammar describes the use of words, and the use of words
bring forth meaning (Shabbir 2010: 60). As opposed to the logico-syntatic use of
words of Tractatus, Wittgenstein describes use as an activity of speaking with words
in the context of extra-linguistic activities. The Logico-syntatic use of words is a
narrow use of words representing the way a word could or could not combine with
other words in the sentence. However, the use of words in a broader understanding
concerns the use of words in a particular context. It pertains to the use of language
in the context of various human activities (Tanney 1994: 23). Corresponding to the
two dimensions of use, Wittgenstein has distinguished two kinds of grammar i.e.
surface grammar and depth grammar.
THE NATURE OF RELIGIOUS BELIEF
The search for the nature of religious belief, we suppose, is all against the
very philosophy of Wittgenstein. He was a critic of essentialism, as we have seen,
one cannot identify a common property for different religions. “… But look and see
whether there is anything common to all for you look at them you will not see
something that is common to all, but similarities, relationship and a whole series of
them at that” (Tanney 1994: 66). At the same time, looking at how believers use
religious language enables Wittgenstein to describe some of its characteristic
features. This material is found in a series of lectures Wittgenstein gave at
Cambridge in 1938. The lecture notes are not available to us; however, the notes
taken by some of the students are at our disposal. Wittgenstein did not check the
accuracy of the notes, but they are the most complete source available to us on
Wittgenstein’s views on religious belief. Wittgenstein recognized that the
reductionist approach failed to feature the distinctive character of religious belief.
Wittgenstein points out the logical distinctiveness of religious belief that
distinguishes it from other areas, especially the scientific. The content of the
Lectures on Religious Belief can be summarized as follows:
Ludwig Wittgenstein: Language-Game And Religious Belief Ottuh & Idjakpo (166-181) 171
Religious belief is an unshakable commitment that guides one’s life and is
not based on evidence or arguments; it is incommensurable with atheistic thought
in the sense that the assertions of believers and nonbelievers do not contradict one
another; and although religious belief is not reasonable it is not unreasonable
(Tanney 1994: 369).
Let us consider each of these in detail. Another important source we could
rely on is the philosophical notes that Wittgenstein kept from the years 1929 to 1951,
with significant remarks on religion. A selection of it is published under the title
Culture and Value.
RELIGIOUS BELIEF AS AN UNSHAKABLE COMMITMENT
Religious belief is absolute, unlike hypotheses or opinion. It is absolute in
the sense that it is not dependent on anything else but itself. It is a commitment
which is not shaken by any contrary evidence. He says, very intelligent and well
educated people believe in the story of the creation in the Bible, while others hold it
as proven false, and the grounds of the latter are well known to the former”
(Phillips 2017: 336). It is not the intellectual and rational basis that makes the belief
firm. Even in the face of good evidence to the contrary the believer still holds the
belief that is what he calls firm belief that can make a difference in our lives. This is
characterized in Lectures as ‘unshakable belief.’
For Wittgenstein, religious beliefs are not matters of empirical fact. They
neither can be justified by an appeal to evidences, nor can they be criticized on the
ground of non-supporting evidences. For example, the religious utterance, ‘There
will be a last Judgment Day’ should not be approached as one that will occur in
future as if one approaches an empirical belief. One utters such a religious
statement to express his commitment to a certain way of seeing things and a
certain way of living. Thus, suppose somebody made this his guide line for this life:
believing in the Last Judgment. Whenever he does anything, this is before his mind
(Phillips 2017). Religious belief can be seen as a passionate commitment to a system
of reference. A system of reference is a system of concepts, and concepts play a
vital and fundamental role in the life of a religious believer. “It strikes me that a
religious belief could only be something like a passionate commitment to a system
of reference. Hence, although it’s belief, it’s really a way of living or a way of
assessing life. It’s passionately seizing hold of this interpretation” (Lerner 1995: 183).
This passionate commitment to a system of concepts involves a distinctive way of
leading one’s life (Phillips 2017). Religious belief involves a distinctive set of religious
concepts in describing and thinking about the world and life. It is a commitment to
those concepts to lead life in a certain way.
Certainty is considered as one of the characteristics of religious belief, and
this is not one of intellectual certainty but of love and trust. Commenting on the
entries in Culture and Value, Cyril Barrett compares the certainty of religious belief to
that of mathematical propositions. However, it is also different: The certitude of a
mathematical proposition depends on its intrinsic logical structure, whereas
religious belief lacks such intrinsic logical structure and extrinsic support (Arnswald
2009). It is a matter of heart and soul. The genuineness of religious belief is not
weighed by the intellectual caliber, but by action which the believer is prepared to
172 INTERFERENCE: Journal of Language, Literature, and Linguistics Vol.1, No.2, August 2020
perform on account of the belief. There are many entries of Wittgenstein's to
substantiate this,
So we have to content ourselves with wisdom and speculation. …But if I
am REALLY to be saved, what I need is certainty not wisdom, dreams or
speculation and this certainty is faith. And Faith is what is needed by my
heart, my soul, not my speculative intelligence. For it is my soul with its
passions, as it was with its flesh and blood, that has to be saved, not my
abstract mind (Díaz 2019: 33).
A significant element here in Wittgenstein's religious thought is that
religion is a realm of passion rather than intellect. Religion springs from emotive
lives and passions not from speculative mind. A similar citation can be seen as
"wisdom is cold and to that extent stupid (faith on the other hand is a passion)"
(Dienstag 1998:56). Though unshakableness is considered as one of the
characteristics of religious life, there is room for doubt. The man who believes in the
Last Judgment acknowledges that this is not a well-established fact. Belief is
possible where doubt is permissible. In fact, his religious belief may alternate with
doubt. This is something that differentiates religious belief from empirical belief.
Religious belief is unshakable in the face of doubt even to the extent of alternation
(Kidd 2012:145). The firmness and steadfastness in belief do not depend on the
grounds. This commitment could be further explained by the groundlessness of
religious belief.
RELIGIOUS BELIEF AS PICTURE
Wittgenstein explains the normative function of religious belief by
considering the role of pictures in life. In the earlier phase of his philosophy,
language is conceived as a picture of the reality. Propositions, as pictures of state of
affairs, are static; they are idle pictures. However, in his later philosophy,
Wittgenstein describes the dynamic role of pictures in our life and language. He
says: “One wants to say that an order is a picture of the action which was carried
out on the order; but also that it is a picture of the action which is to be carried out
on the order” (Graham 2014: 519). Here we can see the close connection between
the picture and the action to be carried out. A religious belief, taken as picture, is a
call to live by it and also to interpret the religious teaching in the light of that
picture. Therefore, the picture has a normative value.
It is correspondence that makes language a picture of reality in
Wittgenstein's earlier philosophy. Later, when he uses the technical term "picture"
to describe religious belief, he presupposes no correspondence; it may not refer to
any object or person. A corresponding reality is not a necessity in the case of
religious belief. What is important is the picture itself, and the role it plays in human
life. “The whole weight may be in the picture” (Wawrzyniak 2003:72). When
Wittgenstein uses the term picture for religious belief, he does not refer to the
referent but to the meaning. For example when we say “God,” we do not look for
the referent behind the word “God” or we don’t look for the proof for the
existence of the referent, but we look for the meaning of the word “God.” He also
says that the meaning can be arrived at by the role it plays in the life of the believer.
In Philosophical Investigations Wittgenstein brings forth his idea of a picture. "A
Ludwig Wittgenstein: Language-Game And Religious Belief Ottuh & Idjakpo (166-181) 173
picture tells me itself is what I'd like to say, that is it's telling me something consists
in its own structure in its own forms and colours" (Wittgenstein 1965: 523). This very
same thought is found in Lectures. A sentence expressing a religious belief is that 'It
says what it says. Why should you be able to substitute anything else? (Wittgenstein
1965: 71). A religious picture expresses itself. This thought is further carried out in
Remarks on Frazer while considering religious belief as expressive (Wittgenstein &
Granger 2012: 61).
Wittgenstein understands religious belief as being capable of controlling
human life in the sense that it is able to change one’s whole life. A particular belief
may be a guideline for life; it somehow regulates his life. An example will clarify it.
Suppose somebody made this guidance for this life: believing in the Last
Judgement. Whenever he does anything, this is before his mind. In a way, how are
we to know whether to say he believes this will happen or not? Asking him is not
enough. He will probably say he has proof. But he has what you might call an
unshakable belief. It will show, not by reasoning or by appeal to ordinary grounds of
belief, but rather by regulating for all in his life. (Wittgenstein & Granger 2012: 86).
Wittgenstein considered religious belief as using a picture to regulate one’s
life. The picture is always present there to guide one’s thinking. This picture
constitutes the framework for what makes sense of his experience of life (). A belief
becomes religious, therefore, when it has control over the life of the person who
believes it. In the Last Judgment, a future divine retribution is what Wittgenstein
calls a picture before a believer's mind controlling his actions when one is tempted
to do something evil. Wittgenstein's understanding of religious belief has gained a
moral character. Religious expressions serve some sort of moral purpose
recommending a commitment to a particular way of life (Vinokurov 2018: 71).
Wittgenstein used the technique of employing the pictures of God. The
picture, 'god created man', is not a description of any state of affairs. "That talk of
God is in some manner expressive of feelings, attitudes and emotions" (Vinokurov
2018: 75). The function of the utterance of faith is to express existential attitudes of
life and their practical use in guiding human actions. According to Wittgenstein,
religious belief is upholding certain pictures which help to give orientation and
guidelines his actions and attitudes. Commitment to such a picture is founded on
passion not in intellect and systematic understanding is insignificant (Kidd 2012). In
talking about the life-guiding role of religious beliefs, Wittgenstein makes an
important point that religion is more a matter of praxis than merely a matter of
intellect. This will be examined in more detail in the next section.
SYMBOLIC AND EXPRESSIVE NATURE OF RELIGIOUS BELIEFS
Philosophers of religion interpreted Wittgenstein's thought about religion
focusing around the language-game and form of life even before some of his notes
on religion were published. Wittgenstein's "Remarks on Frazer's Golden Bough" is
crucial for an understanding of his philosophy of religion, along with Culture and
Value and Lectures and Conversations on Aesthetics, Psychology and Religious Belief.
Wittgenstein, after reading James George Frazer's Golden Bough which accounts for
myth, magic and religion, wrote a series of comments on it. He criticized Frazer's
explanation of myth, magic and religion and offered his own conceptual account of
174 INTERFERENCE: Journal of Language, Literature, and Linguistics Vol.1, No.2, August 2020
myth, magical and religious practices. Here is an attempt to expose Wittgenstein's
thoughts on religion based on his criticism of Frazer. Frazer had a conceptual and
instrumental view of religion along with magic and myth whereas Wittgenstein
exposes a more symbolic and expressive nature of religion. His comments on Frazer
elaborate the symbolic nature of religion and the spiritual attitude towards life
expressed in these symbols. These symbols which are expressive are without
explanations especially scientific. The symbolic and expressive nature of religion
brings us the common spiritual nature of human beings. As we journey through
Wittgenstein's insights on religion from Tractatus where it is non-sensical to speak
about religion to Philosophical Investigations where religion is meaningful only
within the limit of the language-game, we come to a broader understanding of
religion as symbolic and expressive and the common spiritual nature of human
beings.
Frazer in his Golden Bough exposes his positivist view of historical progress.
Primitive people approached life by reasoning about its underlying causes and
trying to manipulate and influence them. This process of reasoning is done by myth,
magic and religion. These practices, according to Frazer, are faulty ways of
reasoning. "The views of natural causation embraced by the savage magician no
doubt appear to us manifestly false and absurd; yet in their day they were legitimate
hypothesize though they have not stood the test of experience" (Frazer 62). Such
reasoning is done by scientific theories in the modern era. Myth, magic and religion
are carried to the modern era because of the superstitions of the people. Frazer had
a positivist stand on myth, magic and religion; they are at the first stage of the
human search for knowledge, philosophy is at the second and science is at the final
stage. Wittgenstein was struck by Frazer's crude assumption that the religious
activities of ancient people were primitive forms of scientific endeavor - misguided
attempts to influence the outcome of natural events (Kidd 2012). However,
Wittgenstein has a strong criticism on this point and concludes error and progress
are not features of magic and religion but of science. "The distinction between
magic and science can be expressed by saying in science there is progress, but in
magic there isn't. Magic has no tendency within itself to develop" (PO 141). Science
and technology, which are based on instrumental practice, intellect and reasoning
tend towards progress and development. Religion, magic and myth are not of this
kind. One prays not because the prayer is based on a proven theory, nor does one
abandon an old prayer due to lack of explanation. For Wittgenstein, religion, magic
and myth are beyond intellectual reasoning and conceptual explanation that calls
for development and progress.
Myth, magic and religion are expressive and symbolic; they emerge from
cultural rituals, metaphors and symbolic narratives. Since they are expressive, they
differ from instrumental practices such us cooking or building huts. Being symbolic,
they defer from non-symbolic expressive practices, such as playing music. As
symbolic and expressive, they are more akin to ritualistic practices and these
symbolic and expressive practices cater to the human spirit. The conceptual
features that make these practices spiritual are the promotion of an attitude of
wonder at the mysterious nature of life, the manner in which they express symbolic
Ludwig Wittgenstein: Language-Game And Religious Belief Ottuh & Idjakpo (166-181) 175
actions, poetic language, powerful images, and finally the deep existential concerns
of human beings. These features make myth, magic and religion, transforming them
into inspiring a spiritual attitude towards life (Kidd 2012). Mulhall places prime
importance on action rather than doctrine concerning the spiritual nature of
religious practices. Waismann records Wittgenstein's remark regarding his view on
religion.
I can well imagine a religion in which there are no doctrinal propositions, in
which there is thus no talking. Obviously, the essence of religion cannot have
anything to do with the fact that there is talking, or rather: when people talk,
then this itself is part of a religious act and not a theory. Thus it also does not
matter at all if the words used are true or false or nonsense (Mulhall 201: 117).
There are other occasions where Wittgenstein strongly argues that
ritualistic practices and deeds gain priority in religious beliefs. In Culture and Value,
we learn "the origin and the primitive form of the language game is a reaction; only
from this can more complicated forms develop. Language - I want to say - is a
refinement, 'in the beginning was the deed'" (Nagl 2017: 31). While quoting Goethe,
Wittgenstein is not simply referring to the historical origin of the development of
language but, what lies at the bottom rather than how things were in the beginning.
What lies at the bottom is not propositions but actions (Morra 2019: 307). "Giving
grounds, however, justifying the evidence, comes to an end; - but the end is not
certain propositions striking us immediately as true, i.e., it is not a kind of seeing on
our part; it is our acting, which lies at the bottom of the language-game" (OC 204).
What lies at the grounds is acting and reacting not propositions even in religious
beliefs. Wittgenstein is offering primacy of acting and reacting in religious beliefs
over and above language that is used in celebrations.
Wittgenstein here is imagining a pure ritualistic type of religion not
supported by doctrinal propositions. Doctrinal principles are often theological
worldviews to support the rituals practiced. Wittgenstein imagines a religion
without such theological and metaphysical support to the rituals. The language
used in rituals is not part of doctrinal principles; however, it is symbolic and
expressive which is to be distinguished from the language used to ascertain
theological claim. Therefore, there is no reason to find foundations for religious
practices on any doctrinal or theological propositions, since they are expressions
and promotions of a personal spiritual attitude towards life. Wittgenstein is not
totally eliminating theological principles from religious practices; however, he
makes a clear distinction between the language used in religious practices and the
language used in doctrinal principles to assert those rituals. Religious practices are
ritualistic, and they are symbolic. The expressive use of symbols is an important
characteristic of religious practices as distinct from the instrumental use of signs
(Lurie, Human Spirit 161). Wittgenstein's point here is that rituals are not based on
any proven theory or beliefs. However, one can well understand a ritual in terms of
a theory (Morra 2019: 134).
The key to understanding Wittgenstein's account of rituals lies in his idea
that they are rooted in instincts. The natural disposition of human beings to react in
an expressive way and to create and observe rituals that can symbolically express
176 INTERFERENCE: Journal of Language, Literature, and Linguistics Vol.1, No.2, August 2020
the existential concern of human beings serves as the foundation of religious
symbols. Wittgenstein describes
When I am furious about something, I sometimes beat the ground or a tree
with my walking stick. But I certainly do not believe that the ground is to
blame or that my beating can help anything. 'I am venting my anger'. And all
the rites are of this kind. Such actions may be called Instinct-actions.... (RFGB
137-138)
Wittgenstein stresses the spontaneity of ritual action as the natural
behavior of a ceremonial animal. This particular passage elicited some
misunderstandings of Wittgenstein's thought about rituals. Some reduced his
thought to a mere expressivist account ascribing no meaning beyond the secondary
function of venting emotion to rituals. "Wittgenstein's point is not that all rituals are
automatic or of one kind, but that all meaningful rituals have some basis in our
natural way of seeing and reacting to the world. Ritual and ceremony - along with
song, dance panting and countless other forms of expressions are natural ways of
responding to aspects of the world that are meaningful and important to us"
(Lerner 1995: 176). A meaningful ritual is one that brings new and significant aspects
of life and the world to light, and thus helps a person to reorient his own life.
Religious rituals come out of the natural inclination to express our
concerns, not out of reasoning about cause and effect. They are created in relation
to the primitive natural expression of human existential concerns. In Philosophical
Investigations Wittgenstein expresses a similar concern regarding sensation words
as they are connected to primitive natural expressions of sensations. "Words are
connected with the primitive, the natural, expressions of the sensation and used in
their place" (Morra 2019: 189). It is the cultural community that creates the rituals.
Human beings have a natural disposition to create and observe rituals that can
express their everyday concerns. Hence, humans create symbolic practices that can
express their concern as for instances, anger, friendship etc. A right ritual can evoke
in a participant spiritually edifying way of birth, death, sex, love, other infinite
number of occasions that are deeply important to humans. Wittgenstein is not
bringing forth a formula for distinguishing meaningful rituals from meaningless
rituals. The meaning of rituals depends on the apt use of it in Wittgenstein's broader
context of his later philosophy.
By including the natural inclination and disposition feature into the rise of
religious rituals, Wittgenstein wanted to confront Frazer's claim that myth, magic
and religion are practices based on theoretical and instrumental ways of reasoning.
Wittgenstein ruled out Frazer's claim that religious rituals arise from erroneous
reasoning which is overcome by science in the historical advancement. The
practices based on theoretical reasoning are not symbolic and expressive according
to Wittgenstein. He labels such an explanatory theory opinion. Opinion is not the
foundation of any religious practices but attitudes. "No opinion serves as the
foundation for a religious symbol. And only an opinion can involve an error"
(Shabbir 2010: 442).
Primitive people did not act from opinions but from attitudes. Even though
they had opinions and sometimes acted upon them, these practices are not
Ludwig Wittgenstein: Language-Game And Religious Belief Ottuh & Idjakpo (166-181) 177
symbolic as in the case of religious rituals which are symbolic and expressive. "I
believe that the characteristic feature of primitive man is that he does not act from
opinions" (Shabbir 2010: 442). The primitive form of language games is not based
on theoretical reflections or opinions. "The origin and the primitive form of the
language-game is a reaction; only from this does the more complicated form grow.
Language-I want to say-is a refinement, in the beginning was the deed"
(Wawrzyniak 2003: 31). Wittgenstein makes a clear distinction between opinion and
attitude. "What is the difference between an attitude and an opinion? I would like to
say: the attitude comes before the opinion" (Shabbir 2010: 443). Opinions come out
of reasoning and reflections. They are rational and based on good reasoning. One
could be able to give solid philosophical or rational explanation to an opinion that
one holds. People may differ in opinions according to the rationale behind them.
They are open to discussion and debate. However, attitudes pertain to life and
concern living experiences. "Attitudes are related to ways of seeing and
experiencing various aspects of things, to desires, feelings, concerns, likes and
dislikes. They are ways in which we grasp the meaning of things that make up our
lives in a very personal, basic, immediate, and non-inferential fashion" (Wawrzyniak
2003: 176). The rich content of attitudes can be expressed in beliefs and
accompanying feelings and thoughts. "Isn't belief in God an attitude? (Shabbir 2010:
442). Faith in God, that pivotal part of religion and religious belief, can be
meaningfully understood as an attitude (Asuquo 2019). This attitude of belief in God
is supported later by rational thinking and theological formulations. Attitude and
opinion are mostly related to one another in human life. Wittgenstein wanted to
show that religion along with magic and myth arises out of attitudes concerning
human life not from opinions. Faith in religion is to have faith in what religion
symbolizes through ritual practices (Sasa 2018). This faith has the ability to
transform existential concerns into inspiring spiritual concerns. The effect of faith in
spiritual or religious practice is different from faith in instrumental practices.
Wittgenstein points to this difference; "I read among similar examples of a rain-king
in Africa to whom the people pray when the rainy period comes. But surely that
means that they do not really believe that he can make it rain, otherwise they would
do it in the dry periods" (Shabbir 2010: 447). "Kissing the picture of one's beloved.
That is obviously not based on the belief that it will have some specific effect on the
object which the picture represents. It aims at satisfaction and achieves it. Or rather:
it aims at nothing at all; we just behave this way and then we feel satisfied" (Shabbir
2010: 449). The point Wittgenstein makes is that religious practices are immune to
error, since they are different from other kinds of cultural or social practices which
may have an instrumental purpose. Religious practices are purely spiritual, and they
do not have any instrumental purpose. That is why people hold on to the primitive
ritualistic practices even when it does not fulfill any instrumental purposes
(Wittgenstein & Granger 2012: 62).
Wittgenstein, commenting on Frazer's intellectualistic, rationalistic and
scientific approach to the ritualistic practices, claims some sort of emotive and
expressive aspect of ritualistic practices. Some of the readings from his remarks on
Wittgenstein & Granger allude to this claim.
178 INTERFERENCE: Journal of Language, Literature, and Linguistics Vol.1, No.2, August 2020
Burning an effigy. Kissing the picture of one's beloved. That is obviously not
based on the belief that it will have some specific effect on the object which
the picture represents. It aims at satisfaction and achieves it. Or rather, it aims
at nothing at all; we just behave this way and then feel satisfied. But I certainly
do not believe that the ground is to blame or that my beating can help
anything. I am venting my anger. And all rites are of this kind. Such actions
may be called instinct-actions (Wittgenstein & Granger 2012: 123).
There is no instrumental purpose behind the act of burning an effigy or
kissing the photograph of a beloved one. They simply satisfy an urge or instinct. In
that sense, they are non-cognitive. These analogies that Wittgenstein uses are
parallel to the formation of pain behavior as he explains how human beings learn
meaning of the word pain. "Here is one possibility: words are connected with the
primitive, natural expressions of sensation and used in their place. A child has hurt
himself and he cries; then adults talk to him and teach him exclamations and, later,
sentences. They teach the child new pain-behavior" (Shabbir 2010: 444). Crying out
in pain is non-cognitive. If one genuinely is in pain then, the crying is not purpose
directed. In a similar way, we shout 'come here'. The language of pain is said to
develop out of instinctual, non-linguistic behavior. Similarly, the language we use in
religion - the expression of religious beliefs, is an extension of certain primitive
reactions that is to say a natural expression of wonder or fear (Wittgenstein &
Granger 2012: 109). The kissing of a photograph of a loved one is an expression of
love and burning an effigy is an expression of hatred. These acts are not purpose-
driven and do not to have any effect on the person in the case. This is as opposed to
the instrumentalist understanding where burning an effigy for example is to effect
some harm to the persons involved (Wittgenstein & Granger 2012: 22). The
satisfaction derived from the performance of the rituals does not arise from the
belief. The action affects the objects represented in it. Yuval Lurie, while
commenting on Wittgenstein's remarks on ceremonies and rituals in Philosophy of
Psychology, makes the following statement:
Myth, magic, and religion are inspired symbolic expressions of existential
concerns, promoting and enriching shared spiritual attitudes toward life. They
manifest our common human nature, which gives rise to such concerns, as
well as our natural human tendency to channel these concerns into expressive
rituals that transforms them into inspiring spiritual attitudes toward life.
(Graham 2014:179)
Anthony O'Hear asserts that Wittgenstein emphasizes the expressive and
emotive aspects of primitive religion as religious beliefs accompany ritualistic
practices that express and evoke deep needs and emotions (Shabbir 2010: 449).
The expressive and symbolic interpretation of religious rituals leads to an non-
cognitive understanding of religious belief in Wittgenstein. Religious rites are
expressive and celebratory, none of which are performed to bring out anything. The
theological function emphasized by Frazer is sidelined here in Wittgenstein's
explanation. Wittgenstein urges us to see that religious rites need not be
understood as purpose-driven at all. The rituals express something; however, what
is expressed cannot be logically separated from the ritual itself. What is expressed
Ludwig Wittgenstein: Language-Game And Religious Belief Ottuh & Idjakpo (166-181) 179
in the celebration of rituals cannot be described without reference to the form of
the ritual itself (Lerner 1995).
TOWARDS A COMMON SPIRITUAL NATURE OF HUMAN BEINGS
Wittgenstein's criticism of Frazer on the conceptual nature of religion as it
is based on reasoning and theoretical foundation point to another important
aspect: There is a common underlying spiritual nature to human beings in all
cultures. Wittgenstein imagines a religion without doctrines; however, he could not
imagine a culture without some sort of religion. In every culture, there is a common
spiritual nature that inspires humans to perform symbolic and expressive practices
that relate to existential concerns without being founded on any theoretical
principles, adapted in the course of time to support such practice (Allam 2018).
Frazer traces several religious practices along with myths and magic in
several cultures in the ancient world due to historical influences. Wittgenstein, by
criticizing this historical explanation to various rituals in different cultures, describes
that these cultures manifest a common spirit. It is the common spirit or spiritual
inclination that enables human beings to create and practice religious rituals and
give expressive meaning to them. In many different cultures, human beings give
symbolic expression of common existential concerns through religious practices.
"All these different practices show that it is not a question of the derivation of one
from the other, but of a common spirit. And one could invent (devise) all these
ceremonies oneself. And precisely that spirit from which one invented them would
be their common spirit" (Arnswald 2009: 151).
Wittgenstein criticizes Frazer's attempt to trace the similarity of different
rituals due to historical influence and the failure to acknowledge the common spirit.
These practices derive from the common spiritual nature manifesting human
existential concerns (Lerner 1995). Our understanding of the expressive meaning of
religious rituals can be articulated in meaningful and expressive language. 'Man as
a ceremonial animal' (Díaz 2019:129) has a mysterious life which is brought about by
the symbolic and expressive rituals. The common spiritual nature of human beings
has to be understood by the very self that performs the rituals and makes research
about the common spiritual nature. The focus should be on the primitive nature of
the self with its instincts and urges instead of primitive distant societies.
Wittgenstein's method seems to reduce the unfamiliarity between oneself and an
alien culture by prompting us to see that certain practices performed in other
cultures stem from the same primitive urge and instinct out of which certain rituals
are practiced in our own culture. Foreign culture and rituals originated in other
cultures are made more familiar and understandable. Seeing our humanity reflected
in rituals and practices of other people help us to see the familiarities and
strangeness and ultimate inexplicability of our own human nature (Lerner 1995).
Wittgenstein's purpose is to show that people's behavior is manifested through its
religious beliefs which are expressed in the practices ceremonies. The communal
religious practices make manifest the values, ideals and concepts which lie at the
heart of their culture. Rituals are mirrors that reflect human nature (Nagl 2017: 31).
180 INTERFERENCE: Journal of Language, Literature, and Linguistics Vol.1, No.2, August 2020
CONCLUSION
Wittgenstein, in his later philosophy, has developed a new theory of
meaning - meaning as use is sufficiently supported by his idea of the language-
game, family resemblance and form of life. Language is compared to a game which
is played in accordance with certain rules and a patterned order. These rules are
mastered by constant practice, and it is very much embedded in daily life. Language-
games are based on the form of life which provides ample context for any game.
The rules of all language-games are meaningful within their internal boundary. Since
they have their own patterned order and social nature, they go beyond individual
freedom either to create or choose the rules to be applied. Here reconciliation is
attempted between the language-game as a rule-bound activity and the role of
human freedom within the language-game on the basis of form of life.
Wittgenstein’s philosophy is an attack on the essentialist view that essence
precedes existence. In the essentialist view, a rule is conceived as something
abstract, and the application of a rule is something concrete. The application is
controlled and directed by the abstract norms and rules. This Platonic essentialism is
questioned by Wittgenstein in his interpretation of rule-following as one activity.
The Platonic idea of internalized mental structure as determining and justifying our
linguistic action is refuted here (Nagl 2017). Wittgenstein sidelines any concept of
the abstract idea of rule or any mental structure which can determine our linguistic
activity by removing the gap between the rule and application. Wittgenstein’s
understanding of rule-following is an attack on Platonic idealism and essentialism.
REFERENCES
Allam, O. S. (2018). Unmasking “Alekwu” Religious Experience among the Idoma
People-Group of Nigeria. GNOSI: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Human
Theory and Praxis, 1(2), 118-130.
Arnswald, U. (2009). In Search of Meaning: Ludwig Wittgenstein on Ethics,
Mysticism and Religion. In In Search of Meaning: Ludwig Wittgenstein on
Ethics, Mysticism and Religion. https://doi.org/10.26530/oapen_422396
Asuquo, O. O. (2019). Humanism as a Category of Religious Alternative. GNOSI: An
Interdisciplinary Journal of Human Theory and Praxis, 2(1), 30-36.
Díaz, J. A. (2019). Wittgenstein y la religión. In Ensayos de Filosofía II (pp. 6190).
https://doi.org/10.2307/j.ctvb6v6n5.6
Dienstag, J. F. (1998). Wittgenstein among the savages: Language, action and
political theory. In Polity (Vol. 30, Issue 4, pp. 579603).
https://doi.org/10.2307/3235256
Graham, G. (2014). Wittgenstein and Natural Religion. In Wittgenstein and Natural
Religion. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198713975.001.0001
Kidd, I. J. (2012). Oswald Spengler, technology, and human nature. In European
Legacy (Vol. 17, Issue 1, pp. 1931).
https://doi.org/10.1080/10848770.2011.640190
Lerner, B. D. (1995). Winch and Instrumental Pluralism. Philosophy of the Social
Sciences, 25(2), 180191. <Go to ISI>://A1995RA76400002
Ludwig Wittgenstein: Language-Game And Religious Belief Ottuh & Idjakpo (166-181) 181
Morra, L. (2019). Wittgenstein and Piccoli. Wittgenstein-Studien, 11(1), 129.
https://doi.org/10.1515/witt-2020-0002
Mulhall, S. (2011). Wittgenstein on Religious Belief. In The Oxford Handbook of
Wittgenstein. https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199287505.003.0034
Nagl, L. (2017). „James’s book The Varieties of Religious Experience does me a lot of
good.“. Wittgenstein-Studien, 8(1). https://doi.org/10.1515/witt-2017-008
Phillips, D. Z. (2017). Just say the word: Magical and logical conceptions in religion.
In Religion and Wittgenstein’s Legacy (pp. 139159).
https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315244761-8
Rono, J. (2018). Revolutionary Traits in Wittgenstein and St. Paul. Philosophy and
Theology, 30(2), 333359. https://doi.org/10.5840/philtheol201944106
Sasa, M. S. (2018). Vico and Man’s Creation of Institutions: A Backward Journey to
Human Root. GNOSI: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Human Theory and
Praxis, 1(2), 110-117.
Shabbir, A. (2010). Ludwig Wittgenstein: Ethics and Religion (review). Philosophy East
and West, 60(3), 422424. https://doi.org/10.1353/pew.0.0109
Tanney, J. (1994). Wittgenstein’s centenary essays,. History of European Ideas, 18(6),
970973. https://doi.org/10.1016/0191-6599(94)90366-2
Vinokurov, V. (2018). LUDWIG WITTGENSTEIN: LANGUAGE AND STRUCTURES OF
LIFE. 5th SGEM International Multidisciplinary Scientific Conferences on
SOCIAL SCIENCES and ARTS SGEM2018, Ancience Science, 5.
https://doi.org/10.5593/sgemsocial2018h/21/s06.033
Wawrzyniak, J. (2003). Ludwig Wittgenstein a Religia - Wprowadzenie [Ludwig
Wittgenstein and Religion - Introduction]. Forum Philosophicum, 8, 288291.
https://doi.org/10.5840/forphil2003834
Wittgenstein, L. (1965). I: A Lecture on Ethics. The Philosophical Review, 74(1), 3.
https://doi.org/10.2307/2183526
Wittgenstein, L., & Granger, G. (2012). Tractatus logico-philosophicus. Paris:
Gallimard.
... Utilitarianism, Kantianism, virtue ethics, principlism, moral necessity, and religious ethics might not accept yahoo yahoo as a solution of survival. According to Ottuh and Idjakpo (2020), in utilitarianism, the ethically appropriate action or system is determined by the utility that it produces. This is done by comparing the consequences. ...
Article
Full-text available
In Nigeria, there is the scourge of internet fraud known as Yahoo-Yahoo which have swindled many unsuspecting victims their hard-earned resources. This article evaluates this menace from an ethico-religious perspective. In order to achieve the aim of this paper, the research adopts the evaluative and descriptive methods. The findings show that several factors like poverty, unemployment, dwindling societal value and greed are responsible for the menace. The paper concludes that the act is not ethically and religiously justifiable. Furthermore, there is need to increase societal, religious and family values, such as sanctity of human life, dignity of labour, integrity, and contentment as a way forward.
... So far, literature studies that discuss language games tend to focus on patterns of particular interest and rely on three perspectives, namely: (1) constitutional texts and political language have language game rules with normative, factual characters, and play in language logic, even some of them contain pretense, so that they have a great influence, especially in the democratic system (Hartini, 2019;Salazar, 2021;Wilujeng, 2013); (2) the comedians use language games to be funny and attract the audience. This language game found deviations from pragmatic principles, namely the principle of politeness and irony language style (Lilaifi, 2019); (3) language games are used as an effective translation methodology in children's short stories (Sulistyowati, 2015); and (4) language games in da'wah texts and religious interests have broad implications, including attracting listeners' interest (Amanullah, 2021;Firdausiyah & Fikri, 2021;Ottuh & Idjakpo, 2020). ...
Article
Full-text available
Each language has its own rules and pattern and a certain tendency. Language games are the rules of language for a particular purpose. Nawal Sa'dawi uses denotative meaning as criticism and disagreement about existing social phenomena. Therefore, this study aims to determine the form of language games in the book "al-Mar'ah wa al-Jins" by Nawal Sa'dawi based on the perspective of Ludwig Wittgenstein. This study uses an interpretation method to express linguistic diction in books and their meanings as human expressions. This study uses Wittgenstein's hermeneutic approach to reveal linguistic facts from the book's narrative. The source of this research data is taken from the book "Al-Mar'ah wa al-Jins" by Nawal Sa'dawi. Data collection techniques in this study used reading techniques and note-taking techniques. The analysis of this research uses the technique of analyzing the philosophy of language from Ludwig's perspective. The results of this study indicate that there are four kinds of language games in the book "al-Mar'ah wa al-Jins" by Nawal Sa'dawi, namely: (1) emphasis; (2) feminist language; (3) sarcasm; and (4) subtle persuasion. This language game aims to reveal facts and as a form of assertiveness from its users upon request or support.
Article
Full-text available
This research is a theological and ethical assessment of suicide among undergraduate students at tertiary institutions in Delta State, Nigeria. The historico-descriptive and analytical approaches were used to achieve the research's goal. The focus was on seven postsecondary institutions in Delta State. The study revealed that variables such as suicidal ideation and prior suicide attempts are contributing factors to the suicide rate among undergraduates at Delta State. In addition, views from the theological and ethical spectrum show that religion lowers the student suicide rate. It posited that to curb student suicide in higher education institutions in Nigeria, it is crucial to employ ethical attitudes and religious practises, hence, there is a need to carry out more research on student suicide in Delta State and across Nigeria.
Article
Full-text available
The discourse of this study focuses on the language game theory by Ludwig Wittgenstein which is applied in the da’wah language. The purpose of the study is to determine the significance of the language game theory applied to the da’wah language. The research method used is library research, with data analytics in the form of descriptive-interpretative, and is assisted by Hans George Gadamer’s effective hermeneutic theory in studying language game theory and Wittgenstein’s idea. The results of this study are sufficient to answer the significance of the language game theory applied to the da’wah language, with two points. First, language game theory can be applied in da’wah language. Second, the use of language game theory can attract the interest of da’wah listeners. These two points have implications for the actions or behavior of the da’wah listeners, which is called compulsive and impulsive behavior. cThus it can be understood that language and da’wah are an inseparable bond
Article
Full-text available
Man is faced with several problems in life and issues which disturb and frighten him. There are some other issues of life which he does not understand, for instance, the source of life, the origin of death, the nature of the hereafter. He also desires peace, comfort and security in life. These and several other reasons have made man to search for answers and solutions to his predicament. This search has given rise to the various known religions. However, despite the existence of these religions, man's problem still persists. This situation has made some people to suggest or advocate the adoption of other secular alternatives to religion, with the hope that they may solve man's problems. This paper examines one of such secular alternatives called Humanism. In this process, it examines its meaning, and the merits and demerits of some humanistic theories. This is meant to help the reader to decide whether to adopt it or not.
Article
In 1929 Ludwig Wittgenstein met Raffaello Piccoli, the Cambridge Professor of Italian, with whom he arranged several meetings in the following terms. For a long time their intellectual friendship was suggested only by the occurrences of Piccoli’s name in Wittgenstein’s Cambridge Pocket Diaries, then a paper about Piccoli including hypothesis on his meetings with Wittgenstein was published (Marjanović 2005), and more recently, the diaries of a student of both Piccoli and Wittgenstein in 1929–1930 were discovered. The new material, on the background of data now available about Piccoli’s life and works, throws new light onto his relationship with Wittgenstein, and hypothesis on the topics of their conversations are also advanced. Piccoli’s perspective on the difference between ethics, religion and philosophy on the one hand and science on the other was in tune with Wittgenstein’s view and similar was also their aversion towards scientism; furthermore, Piccoli read many of the authors for which Wittgenstein showed an interest in 1930 –1931 – Freud, Spengler, Frazer, Augustine, and also James.
Article
Wittgenstein zitiert in seinen Schriften nur wenige Autoren, den amerikanischen Pragmatisten William James bis in sein Spätwerk hinein jedoch mit auffallender Häufigkeit. Das hängt - so die Leitthese des Beitrags - vor allem mit der Rolle zusammen, die James‘ Erkundungen des Religiösen für Wittgensteins Nachdenken über Religion spielen. Der intrikaten Verbindung Wittgenstein-James wird in sieben Reflexionen nachgegangen: 1. Krisis der Lebenspraxis: „The Sick Soul“ (James, Tolstoi, Wittgenstein); 2. Das existentiell dimensionierte „Paradoxon“ als rektifizierte/dekonstruierte Dialektik? Wittgensteins (beredtes?) Schweigen im Tractatus; 3. Kann Reflexion stillgestellt werden? „Therapie“ als „Ende der Philosophie“? 4. Kritische Eindämmung des „Szientismus“: Wittgensteins und James‘ Einsprüche gegen die „survival theory of religion“; 5. Exkurs zum Jamesschen Thematisierungsversuch des „Mystischen“; 6. James und Wittgenstein über das „institutionalisierte“ Religiöse: „Religion - a matter between me and God only“? - „Subjektive“ Religiosität vs. „korporative“ Religion; 7. Coda. Die (innere) Ambivalenz religiöser Motivation: Sami Pihlströms (post‐) Wittgensteinsche Reflexionen.
Chapter
This article is based on three assumptions. The first is that Ludwig Wittgenstein's impact in the philosophy of religion has been more a function of the work of those inspired by him than of his own writings on this topic. The second is that Wittgensteinian philosophers of religion took their primary inspiration from Wittgenstein's later approach to philosophy in general, as manifest in the Philosophical Investigations, rather than from his specific writings on religion. The third assumption is that such Wittgensteinian philosophy of religion has been burdened virtually from its outset by the fateful charge of fideism. This charge originated with Kai Nielsen, who argued that assumptions common to a range of Wittgensteinian authors entailed an unacceptable immunisation of religious belief against rational criticism (just as theological fideists hold that religious belief is grounded on faith rather than reason). This article also explores Cora Diamond's development and application of a third perspective known as 'The Realistic Wittgenstein', in addition to the first two: 'The Fideist Wittgenstein' and 'The Canonical Wittgenstein'.
Article
In his attempt to understand matters of the spirit, most notably in the "Remarks on Frazer's Golden Bough," Wittgenstein elaborated an account of human action that enables us to overcome the commonplace modern dichotomy between political science and political theory. His work creates the possibility for a certain kind of exchange between the "facts" of political behavior and the "values" of theory by developing the category of "mythology," a form of human activity that bridges the theory-practice divide. The central point is to establish an ontological equivalence between words and deeds so that neither is regarded as more fundamental than the other. In addition to enriching our understanding of the elements of human existence that some label "irrational," this account of action can, by extension, offer a description of the role of political theory in relation to politics that defends theory's value while preserving its distinctiveness.
Article
Peter Winch and Ludwig Wittgenstein have opposed the idea that traditional religion and magic are practiced in order to gain practical, instrumental ends. Their argument rests on interpretive charity: other cultures would have to be unbelievably irrational to believe in magic's practical effectiveness. In this paper, I show that Winch's own philosopical doctrine makes room for the possibility of instrumental pluralism, the notion that different societies may possess different criteria of instrumental rationality. Judged in terms of a native criterion, the instrumental use of magic and religion may be rationaL