Content uploaded by Martin Lang
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Martin Lang on Aug 03, 2021
Content may be subject to copyright.
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2021, Oce 415, e Workstation, 15 Paternoster Row, Sheeld, S1 2BX
Journal for the Cognitive Science of Religion 7.1 (2019/2021) 39–53 JCSR ISSN (print) 2049-7555
https://doi.org/10.1558/jcsr.19803 JCSR ISSN (online) 2049-7563
Keywords: cognitive science, religion, mental disorders, cultural frameworks,
predictive processing, imagination
R E A I
P C F S
I C R T S C
V M
Coventry University
ac2492@coventry.ac.uk
M L
Masaryk University, Brno
martinlang@mail.muni.cz
In this commentary of McCauley and Graham’s book on mental
abnormalities and religions, we identify a number of challenges, and
present possible extensions of their proposed research. Specically, we
argue that no specialized religious cognition should be assumed, and
instead suggest that the cases of mental abnormalities discussed in the
book specify particular instances of religious content, and that other
disorders may show a more causal relationship to religiosity. We argue
that the discussed religious content may be best explained in the con-
text of cultural frameworks and their contribution to experiencing the
world through priors and predictive processing. Moreover, cognition
required to understand and engage with religion, but not special to
it, might crucially involve our capacity for imagination, supported by
memory. Disorders in imagination are therefore expected to show like-
wise dysfunctions in religious phenomena.
Introduction
In Hearing Voices and Other Matters of the Mind, McCauley and Graham
discuss a relatively neglected but extremely important topic of similarities
between religious phenomena and mental disorders (McCauley & Graham,
2020). ey are to be congratulated for investigating this topic with care and
the required depth. e examples they picked to illustrate their point, such as
the depression of Mother Teresa, or the scrupulosity of Martin Luther, speak
40 Valerie van Mulukom and Martin Lang
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2021
to the imagination and make the religious experiences real to the readers (even
if some examples, like Martin Luther’s, may border on the overly speculative).
McCauley and Graham also champion a highly interdisciplinary approach,
as is necessary for the topic at hand, reected in their “ecumenical natural-
ism.” In doing so, they advance the meta-theoretical framework of the Cog-
nitive Science of Religion (CSR), which we wholeheartedly embrace. Indeed,
complex phenomena such as religious experiences are best approached by
a synthesis of multiple levels of investigation (Lang & Kundt, 2020). Not-
withstanding the benets of such an approach, a multilevel investigation of
religious phenomena also presents important challenges for researchers, some
of which are manifested in the work of McCauley and Graham. We discuss
these challenges and provide suggestions for future research.
Naturalism and Religious Cognition
McCauley and Graham frame their inquiry into the relationship between
mental disorders and religious phenomena as “ecumenical naturalism.” Ecu-
menical naturalism combines earlier propositions by McCauley and Bechtel
(2001) regarding explanatory pluralism of cognitive sciences with philosoph-
ical naturalism. Such a combination lays a solid meta-theoretical foundation
for their investigation without the need to reduce religious phenomena to
pathological manifestations of the human mind (sensu Freud, 1907). at
is, ecumenical naturalism allows McCauley and Graham to investigate how
“many features of religious experiences rely on maturationally natural cog-
nitive processes that underpin much of ordinary mental life” (McCauley &
Graham, 2020, p. 28). However, while arguing that religious experiences
are facilitated by “ordinary cognition” (p. 5), McCauley and Graham also
maintain a concept they call “religious cognition,” rendering it unclear what
exactly religious cognition is, if not simply ordinary cognitive systems engag-
ing with religious content. While we agree that neurocognitive mechanisms
underlying religious phenomena likely did not evolve for this reason, putting
forward a concept of religious cognition may confuse the reader to thinking
that McCauley and Graham suggest that there is a special type of cognition
dedicated to religion, which by their own admission, McCauley and Gra-
ham claim not to do. is potential confusion is exacerbated by the fact that
the book intentionally focuses on specic religious avors of mental disorder
(labelled “religious disorders” in the book; e.g., scrupulosity), which again
suggests an impairment in specically religious mental mechanisms.
Taking a hard stance on the non-existence of true religious cognition cre-
ates somewhat of a problem for the main goal of the book, which is to explore
the continuity between religious cognition and specic cognitive structures
impaired in patients suering from depression, obsessive-compulsive disor-
Religious Experiences and Cultural Priors 41
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2021
der, or individuals on the autistic spectrum (Figure 1.1, p. 3). According
to McCauley and Graham, this approach should serve to inform both our
understanding of religious experience and of mental disorders. e former
(research on mental disorders informing the CSR) can indeed be reached if
we assume that religious cognition is just ordinary cognition. Examining the
neurocognitive mechanisms that underlie mental disorders expressing hyper-
or hypo-religiosity should help us better understand mechanisms facilitating
religious experiences.
However, the latter goal (religious experience informing the research on
mental disorders) is more equivocal until we assume the existence of actual
religious cognition. While we agree that there are interesting similarities in
certain features of religious experiences and mental disorders and highlight-
ing them bears merit, sometimes, the similarities appear tenuous and depend
on religious content rather than religious cognition that could enrich our
understanding of the underlying neurocognitive mechanisms. For example,
it is dicult to see what researchers on depression can learn from the partic-
ular case of Mother Teresa when not assuming specic neurocognitive mech-
anisms related to her religious conviction.
e main underlying cognitive mechanism that is considered shared
between “religious” and “ordinary” depression is a strong sense of abandon-
ment, whereby a previously felt connection or attachment is lost, which
results in desolation, feelings of unworthiness, and ultimately, depression.
While this clearly can underlie both cases of “ordinary” and “religious”
depression, it is not clear that a lost connection to the Christian God is cog-
nitively dierent from a connection to a close loved one. A relationship with
the Christian God has been likened to, and explained by, the attachment
theory (Granqvist, 2020; Granqvist, Mikulincer, & Shaver, 2010). According
to attachment theory, God takes a place much like a parent would, who,
when disappointed or disapproving of the individual’s actions, may retreat
their aections and attention. If God and God’s love features in someone’s
life as a human person and their love, then the loss of such presence and love
would be (at least) equally devastating. us, while there may be a common
underlying cognitive mechanism – processes of attachment for example –
McCauley and Graham have focused on the content instead: loss of a con-
nection to God instead of a human loved one. Again, this helps elucidate the
mechanisms facilitating relationships to supernatural deities but likely not
the mechanisms of depression.
Chapter 2, on hearing voices, is another example of how the discussed
cases of mental disorders may be explained by religious content rather than
religious cognition. At the core of this chapter lies the argument that hearing
voices and other forms of hallucinations may not be considered a disorder
42 Valerie van Mulukom and Martin Lang
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2021
or pathology if it is not accompanied by other symptoms of mental disor-
ders such as schizophrenia, if frequency and duration are low (a recurring
argument in the book that we agree with) and if there is narrative or social
support. Cultural expectations inuence how people represent their experi-
ences as voices or inner speech or thought (Luhrmann, 2012), for example
through narratives (van Mulukom, 2017). Religion clearly provides a cultural
framework by which the phenomena can be understood, but also shaped:
thoughts formulated in words make available the objects of narratives (“lan-
guage processing”; McCauley & Graham, 2020, p. 63). ey become both
available and accessible: “People’s specic interpretations of their experiences
are made more probably by (among other things) how culturally imaginable
or readily available the interpretations or descriptors are” (p. 60). is means
that religion is not associated with a special type of cognition to interpret the
world with, but rather a cultural framework. By way of simile, the voices one
hears may be in German or French, or in secular or religious “language.”
Mental Disorders and Religiosity
Establishing that McCauley and Graham refer mostly to religious content,
we suggest that there are other disorders, which may be particularly enlight-
ening to hone in on mechanisms required for religion, rather than mecha-
nisms merely involved (cf. brain lesion studies, like Cristofori et al., 2016).1
For example schizophrenia, which is discussed in Chapter 2 in the context of
auditory verbal hallucinations, is associated with religiosity in a more general
way (Gearing et al., 2011). A crucial aspect of schizophrenia is abnormal
dopamine signaling, which may lead to (psychotic) experiences with aberrant
salience (Kapur, 2003). Dopamine release is implicated in the “stamping-in”
of memories that attaches motivational importance or salience to otherwise
neutral environmental stimuli (Wise, 2004). If dopamine contributes to a
feeling so unusual but also signicant that it is often interpreted as “sacred,”
then it may be a crucial factor in religious experiences (Deeley, 2004; Geertz,
2010).2 If this hypothesis holds true, then one would also expect that, con-
versely, abnormally low levels of dopamine are associated with hyporeligiosity
– and this is indeed the case. Patients with Parkinson’s disease – a disease
marked by low levels of dopamine – frequently experience reductions in reli-
1. Aside from a potential underlying shared mechanism between schizophrenia and
religiosity, there is also important research suggesting that, depending on the
culture, religious/spiritual coping may be benecial for adherence to treatment in
schizophrenia (Gearing et al., 2011).
2. It has been suggested that imagistic religious rituals induce dopamine release
with referentially open stimuli (Deeley, 2004) the interpretation of which needs
a referential framework.
Religious Experiences and Cultural Priors 43
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2021
giosity (Butler, McNamara, Ghofrani, & Durso, 2011; McNamara, Durso,
& Brown, 2006). is suggests that cognitive abnormalities can inform us
about aspects of religiosity without the need to claim that dopamine is a
religious chemical or the only mechanism facilitating religious experience,
for that matter.
Furthermore, there are other cognitive abnormalities directly related to
changes in religiosity that may be of interest, namely, epilepsy. While the
research on the connection between epilepsy and religious experiences ini-
tially allured many researchers to speculate about the presence of this disorder
in important religious gures (Dewhurst & Beard, 1970) or make simplistic
claims about the god part of the brain, we believe that a careful and informed
interdisciplinary research on epilepsy can be extremely fruitful. Indeed, epilepsy
may be associated with sudden personality changes, which can include changes
in religiosity (Hansen & Brodtkorb, 2003), thus creating an opportunity to
investigate whether the cognitive mechanisms that are aected by epilepsy are
causally involved in religiosity (or in cultural frameworks more generally).
However, even if a disordered brain-mechanism related to epilepsy may be
crucial for facilitating religious experience, a cultural framework enveloping
these experiences is still crucial. e ictal experience (i.e., during a seizure)
can involve a variety of ecstatic sensations, including sensory hallucinations
and erotic sensations (Hansen & Brodtkorb, 2003). On closer inspection,
some reported experiences include common religious components, such as
feeling a presence, hearing voices, and receiving messages (Hansen & Brod-
tkorb, 2003). erefore, it may be the case that people experiencing these
phenomena have heard about these phenomena before, but only in a reli-
gious framework (regardless of whether they themselves are religious), and
therefore are prone to interpret the experience as such.
Cross-cultural variation in religious cognition and content
Our argument that McCauley and Graham focus mostly on the religious con-
tent of mental disorders that is crucially dependent on specic religious con-
texts suggests that this issue would best be investigated cross-culturally. For
instance, it would be interesting to examine whether some psychopathology
is more likely to be cross-culturally associated with religious contexts, but this
goes beyond the goals of the McCauley and Graham book. Indeed, despite
acknowledging that religion can “colour” experiences through the cultural
framework it provides, the focus of the book is heavily biased toward mono-
theistic – and, in particular, Abrahamic – religions, which is sometimes called
out (p. 78) but not always (p. 91). In the light of the discussions of narrow
sampling in psychology and related elds (Henrich, Heine, & Norenzayan,
2010; Sears, 1986), we believe that the conclusions oered by McCauley and
44 Valerie van Mulukom and Martin Lang
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2021
Graham are limited by the overt focus on the U.S./Christian populations.
While we do not want to discuss at length the need for understanding
religion outside of the so-called WEIRD (Western, Educated, Industrial-
ized, Rich and Democratic) populations (Newson, Buhrmester, Xygalatas,
& Whitehouse, 2020), we would like to highlight the possible drawbacks
of implicitly assuming that one type of religion is “prototypical” (McCau-
ley & Graham, 2020, p. 79). In the eld of linguistics, a paradigmatic shift
took place when Chomsky proposed the concept of generative grammar
(Chomsky, 1957), introducing a theoretical framework through which all
languages could be analyzed and their universals unveiled. is proposition
revolutionized linguistics, similar to how the study of religion was revolu-
tionized by the inception of the CSR. However, Chomsky took English to
be the default or prototypical language, from which the grammars of other
languages diverged. Regardless of the historical inaccuracy of English even
being close to a proto-language, this means that all kinds of cognitive oper-
ations had to be postulated to t non-English languages (essentially, coming
from non-WEIRD populations) in the same underlying cognitive grammar.
For example, he postulated that in languages where “wh-” question words
(“what,” “where,” etc.) do not appear at the beginning of a sentence, would
move “covertly” (i.e., in one’s head outside of conscious awareness, not in
spoken or written language) to the beginning of the sentence for syntacti-
cal operations to be presumed equal across all languages (Chomsky, 1995),
despite there not being an a priori reason or a reason based on cognitive prin-
ciples for the wh-words to appear at the front of the sentence. e CSR has
done well to embrace the diversity of religions but it is important to continue
relying on ample cross-cultural and comparative work when studying uni-
versals to avoid potential biases related to using one religion as prototypical.
Moreover, understanding the cultural evolutionary history of particular
religions (i.e., the historical processes that formed religions under various
socio-ecological conditions [Lang & Kundt, 2020; Sosis, 2020]) could help
us elucidate why religious content may be more typical for some disorders
than others in particular social systems. For example, some religious tradi-
tions may include harsh, punitive, and omniscient deities that help to stabi-
lize cooperation among anonymous co-religionists (Lang et al., 2019; Noren-
zayan et al., 2016; Purzycki et al., 2016).3 While such beliefs play important
societal functions and are favored by cultural evolution, they also non-trivially
interact with “maturationally natural capacities” and may cause distress and
3. In this respect, we found the argument that some traditions (e.g., Protestantism)
may push their members further on the psychopathology continuum (e.g., in
scrupulosity) intriguing and see this as a fruitful intersection of the CSR research
with cultural evolutionary theories.
Religious Experiences and Cultural Priors 45
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2021
anxiety from fearsome gods (Flannelly, 2017). On the other hand, the cul-
tural evolution of omnipotent deities may also have important by-products,
for instance, the belief that such omnipotent deities can help people in dif-
cult situations. One study of participants in the extreme ritual of the ai-
pussam festival in Mauritius showed that painful acts of devotion celebrating
Murugan (a Hindu god of war) was associated with later improvements in
participants’ self-reported well-being (Xygalatas et al., 2019; see also Tewari
et al., 2012). ese examples suggest that mental health may be aected by
specic religious settings in complex, non-linear ways (Lang, 2020).
Predictive Processing and Priors
Cultural frameworks such as religions further inuence phenomenologi-
cal experiences as do individual dierences in cognition (e.g., the capacity
for absorption). For example, whether the boundary between self/other or
inside/outside the mind, is “porous” rather than “bounded” varies between
individuals and cultures (Luhrmann et al., 2021; see also McCauley & Gra-
ham, 2020, p. 52). Whether the boundaries are porous or bounded deter-
mines whether a person is thought to be able to receive thoughts, emotions,
or knowledge directly from outside sources (such as through telepathy or
divine inspiration). is means that beliefs may dier interculturally prior to
even having an anomalous experience such as hearing voices. In other words,
dierent religious traditions would provide dierent priors for their adher-
ents to interpret their unusual experiences (in a predictive coding or process-
ing framework; Clark, 2013), which would aect the specic manifestations
of particular disorders. e extent to which religious concepts are woven to
the everyday fabric of life in various cultures would create dierently strong
priors for the top-down generative models in the minds of particular reli-
gionists (Taves & Asprem, cf. Lang & Kundt, 2017) and impairments in
the self-monitoring capacity may be more readily populated with religious
concepts in some cultures over others (Fletcher & Frith, 2009). at is, pri-
ors such as a religious framework or other socially supported interpretation
can help frame the event into a religious experience. Crucially, these priors
would aect whether individual cultures encourage or stigmatize psycholog-
ical abnormalities.
While McCauley and Graham discuss this process of “background beliefs
and expectations” inuencing interpretations in the source monitoring sec-
tion of Chapter 2, they do not refer to predictive processing explicitly. We
suggest that the predictive processing framework can provide a more parsi-
monious explanation for the discussed phenomena (van Elk & Wagenmak-
ers, 2017) than source monitoring, which we argue is more closely involved
with assessing the status of the thought (i.e., derived from external or internal
46 Valerie van Mulukom and Martin Lang
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2021
sources; Johnson & Raye, 1981), and to which we return below. Indeed, the
eect of degraded inputs or bottom-up signals, whether due to external cir-
cumstances (e.g., unreliable sensory signals due to low levels of lighting, etc.)
or internal circumstances (e.g., trauma) has been suggested to be an opportu-
nity for religious interpretations, or top-down priors, to sweep in (Schjoedt
et al., 2013a, 2013b). Besides a reduced reliability of bottom-up signals, an
increased reliability of top-down priors, such as the presence of material reli-
gious artefacts, can further steer the experience (Clark, 2013).
Imaginative Capacity Underlies Religious Representation
Despite the caveats highlighted in the previous sections, we believe that
McCauley and Graham would agree there are neurocognitive mechanisms
not dedicated to religion but required for religion. In the current section,
we will argue that imagination may lie at the center of religious beliefs and
behaviors, and may be at the foundation of such cognition (van Mulukom,
2019), and suggest some possible extensions for the work that McCauley and
Graham have put forward.
e ability to imagine a god is a recurring underlying theme in Chapter 2,
3, and 5: e ability to hear the voice of God is supported by practicing one’s
imagination; a reduced ability to “imagine” the presence of God is associated
with depression; and the inability to imagine other minds is associated with
reduced religiosity in individuals on the autism spectrum. Imagination dened
as the cognitive capacity to simulate mental representations in the absence of
external input shares with religion its involvement with content that “tran-
scends the here and now” (van Mulukom, 2019). Given the transcendental
nature of religion, we argue that the capacity for imagination is a prerequisite
for religious experience (regardless of the ontological status of supernatural
beings, places, and so on). In other words, imagination is at the core of the
ability to engage fully with religion. We now investigate whether mental dis-
orders with religious content have similar abnormalities in imaginative ability.
Pentecostalists engage in certain prayer techniques such as imagining oneself
talking to God and imagining observing the church from God’s point of view
to increase their feelings of connectedness to God (Luhrmann, 2012). Such
practice increases the ease of imagining over time, which in turn contributes
to plausibility or felt realness of the experience (Tversky & Kahneman, 1973,
1993; see also, van Mulukom et al., 2016). e process by which thoughts
are assessed has also been called source monitoring or reality monitoring
(Johnson & Raye, 1981). Importantly, reduced source monitoring, such as
in individuals with high levels of fantasy proneness or absorption, may cause
imaginings to appear more real (van Mulukom, 2020). Higher levels of per-
ceived realness can in turn inuence beliefs following from religious experi-
Religious Experiences and Cultural Priors 47
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2021
ences. Scrupulosity might be an instance of this – the thought-action fusion
entails that thoughts are thought real to the extent that they can be perceived
as actions in of themselves. is can prove debilitating, especially when com-
bined with rumination, or an excessive simulation of (imaginary) threat.
Besides individual dierences, excessive belief in the imaginary (“delu-
sions”) is crucially manifested in mental disorders such as schizophrenia.
When the imaginary, that is content that transcends beyond the here and
now, is no longer perceived as such and is considered as real, we might call
this “hyper-imagination.” Conversely, “hypo-imagination” refers to impaired
ability to imagine (for a similar framework, linking mental disorders to cre-
ativity, see Flaherty, 2005). McCauley and Graham suggest that in the case
of hypo-imagination, it becomes impossible for the individual to feel God’s
presence. Indeed, since the Christian God is faceless and invisible, imagina-
tion is required to invite His presence during prayer. However, depression
compromises imagination (Williams et al., 1996) and reduced or blocked
imagination during prayer means that no connection to God can be made,
plunging the praying individual into feeling abandoned by God, which in
turn further reduces the ability to imagine in a vicious cycle.
eory of Mind, like future event imagination, relies on autobiographi-
cal information and involves imagining an alternative perspective to one’s
own perspective in the here and now (Buckner & Carroll, 2007). Autism, in
this sense, may be considered a decit in imagination as well (see also Roth,
2007; though cf., Visuri, 2019). McCauley and Graham point out that autis-
tic individuals may develop an “ersatz” eory of Mind by systemizing their
social experience, in particular in terms of social conventions rather than
psychological insights about other people’s minds. is ersatz theory is a fac-
tual representation of what might have happened without the requirement of
an imagining of another person’s mind. A similar distinction might be made
between semantic and episodic memory: whereas the former is the storage
of factual information, the latter involves storage of remembered personal
experiences including an experiential aspect through which the imaginer can
relive the experience (Tulving, 1985b). Indeed, autistic individuals display a
similar decit in episodic memory as compared to semantic memory (Crane
& Goddard, 2008), as do individuals with depression (Williams et al., 1996),
suggesting an important role for (the feeling of) experience (or “autonoetic
consciousness;” Tulving, 1985a).
Given that religion requires a capacity for imagination to represent gods’
minds (Purzycki & McNamara, 2016), it would stand to reason that religios-
ity is impaired in autistic individuals. However, it has also been argued that
in religions with bodiless supernatural agents, religion might be easier for
autistic individuals, as they do not have to engage with full persons (Visuri,
48 Valerie van Mulukom and Martin Lang
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2021
2018), and can, as it were, create them in their image. However, due to this
increased idiosyncrasy, such religiosity does not always get picked up by stud-
ies of religion (Visuri, 2020).
Furthermore, weaved throughout the book is an underlying tenet that a
coherent, stable sense of self contributes to mental wellbeing, whereby an inter-
ruption of this sense of self is connected to mental disorders (Waters, 2014).
A healthy sense of self or identity is crucially supported by narrative, which
weaves one’s past, present and future together into a coherent whole (McAd-
ams, 2001), stored in and accessed from autobiographical memory. rough
their support of identity, narratives are crucial for psychological wellbeing
(Baerger & McAdams, 1999), and deciencies in narrative or identity are
associated with psychopathology (Neimeyer, 2000). However, contrary to
McCauley and Graham (p. 99), we argue that narrative thought comes natu-
rally and automatically (Bruner, 1986) and is required for the establishment
of an identity (McAdams, 1993, 2001). ese narratives are ways of telling
ourselves and others who we are (i.e., our identities), and religiosity can be
an important part of that. Religious rituals, especially high-arousal ones, can
contribute signicantly to such narratives (van Mulukom, 2017).
To conclude, in so far that one of the main functions of autobiographical
memory may be to provide the building blocks for imagination (Schacter &
Addis, 2007), and that narrative and other social constructions may rely on
imagination (van Mulukom, 2020), we do not have to postulate additional
cognitive systems to account for religious experiences. In Chapter 2, McCau-
ley and Graham explicitly propose ve cognitive systems that may underlie
hearing voices: source monitoring, language processing, agency detection,
eory of Mind, and “penchant for narrative.” Of these, we have covered all
except for agency detection and showed that the capacity for imagination,
supported by memory, plays a crucial role in all of them. In the interest of
space, we will not contribute further to the agency detection debate (in the
CSR), and will simply agree here that it is likely that humans are “naturally
poised to detect intentional, purpose-driven agents” (McCauley & Graham,
2020, p. 63), and suggest that this may be another (predictive) prior inuenc-
ing human perception (cf. Andersen et al., 2019).
Conclusions
How cognition supports religion and religious thoughts and behaviors has
been the target of decades long research. In their book, McCauley and Gra-
ham examine an under-investigated corner of that research: the overlap
between cognition in mental disorders and cognition involved in religion. In
this article, we have pointed out some caveats of their approach as well as pos-
sible extensions of their research proposal, in particular referring to cultural
Religious Experiences and Cultural Priors 49
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2021
frameworks, predictive processing, and imaginative capacity. e interaction
between mental disorders and religiosity is a rich and fascinating aspect of
cognitive science, and we applaud McCauley and Graham for bringing so
many interesting aspects together into a coherent book.
References
Andersen, M., Nielbo, K. L., Schjoedt, U., Pfeier, T., Roepstor, A., & Sørensen,
J. (2019). Predictive minds in Ouija board sessions. Phenomenology
and the Cognitive Sciences, 18(3), 577–588. https://doi.org/10.1007/
s11097-018-9585-8
Baerger, D. R., & McAdams, D. P. (1999). Life story coherence and its relation
to psychological well-being. Narrative Inquiry, 9(1), 69–96. https://doi.
org/10.1075/ni.9.1.05bae
Bruner, J. S. (1986). Actual minds, possible worlds. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press. https://doi.org/10.4159/9780674029019
Buckner, R. L., & Carroll, D. C. (2007). Self-projection and the brain. Trends in
Cognitive Sciences, 11(2), 49–57. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2006.11.004
Butler, P. M., McNamara, P., Ghofrani, J., & Durso, R. (2011). Disease-associated
dierences in religious cognition in patients with Parkinson’s disease. Journal
of Clinical and Experimental Neuropsychology, 33(8), 917–928. https://doi.or
g/10.1080/13803395.2011.575768
Chomsky, N. (1957). Syntactic Structures. Berlin: de Gruyter.
———. (1995). e Minimalist Program. Cambridge, MA: Massachussetts Institute
of Technology Press. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783112316009
Clark, A. (2013). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of
cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36(3), 181–204. https://doi.
org/10.1017/S0140525X12000477
Crane, L., & Goddard, L. (2008). Episodic and semantic autobiographical memory
in adults with autism spectrum disorders. Journal of Autism and Developmental
Disorders, 38(3), 498–506. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10803-007-0420-2
Cristofori, I., Bulbulia, J., Shaver, J. H., Wilson, M., Krueger, F., & Grafman, J.
(2016). Neural correlates of mystical experience. Neuropsychologia, 80, 212–
220. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2015.11.021
Deeley, P. Q. (2004). e religious brain: Turning ideas into convictions. Anthropology &
Medicine, 11(3), 245–267. https://doi.org/10.1080/1364847042000296554
Dewhurst, K., & Beard, A. (1970). Sudden religious conversions in temporal lobe
epilepsy. e British Journal of Psychiatry, 117(540), 497–507. https://doi.
org/10.1192/bjp.117.540.497
Flaherty, A. W. (2005). Frontotemporal and dopaminergic control of idea generation
and creative drive. Journal of Comparative Neurology, 493(1), 147–153.
https://doi.org/10.1002/cne.20768
50 Valerie van Mulukom and Martin Lang
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2021
Flannelly, K. J. (2017). Religious beliefs, evolutionary psychiatry, and mental health in
America. New York: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-52488-7
Fletcher, P. C., & Frith, C. D. (2009). Perceiving is believing: A Bayesian approach
to explaining the positive symptoms of schizophrenia. Nature Reviews
Neuroscience, 10(1), 48–58. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrn2536
Freud, S. (1907/1961). Obsessive actions and religious practices. In J. Strachey (Ed.
and Trans.), e standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund
Freud (Vol. 9) (pp. 116–127). London: Hogarth.
Gearing, R. E., Alonzo, D., Smolak, A., McHugh, K., Harmon, S., & Baldwin,
S. (2011). Association of religion with delusions and hallucinations in the
context of schizophrenia: Implications for engagement and adherence.
Schizophrenia Research, 126(1–3), 150–163. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.
schres.2010.11.005
Geertz, A. W. (2010). Too much mind and not enough brain, body and culture:
On what needs to be done in the cognitive science of religion. Historia
Religionum. An International Journal, 2, 21–37.
Granqvist, P. (2020). Attachment in religion and spirituality: A wider view. New York:
Guilford.
Granqvist, P., Mikulincer, M., & Shaver, P. R. (2010). Religion as attachment:
Normative processes and individual dierences. Personality and Social Psychology
Review, 14(1), 49–59. https://doi.org/10.1177/1088868309348618
Hansen, B. Å., & Brodtkorb, E. (2003). Partial epilepsy with “ecstatic” seizures. Epilepsy
& Behavior, 4(6), 667–673. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.yebeh.2003.09.009
Henrich, J., Heine, S. J., & Norenzayan, A. (2010). e weirdest people in the world?
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33(2-3), 61–83. https://doi.org/10.1017/
S0140525X0999152X
Johnson, M. K., & Raye, C. L. (1981). Reality monitoring. Psychological Review,
88(1), 67–85. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-295X.88.1.67
Kapur, S. (2003). Psychosis as a state of aberrant salience: A framework linking biology,
phenomenology, and pharmacology in schizophrenia. American Journal of
Psychiatry, 160(1), 13–23. https://doi.org/10.1176/appi.ajp.160.1.13
Lang, M. (2020). Multifunctional religious systems and perturbed dynamics of
psychological wellbeing. Religion, Brain & Behavior, 10(2), 179–184. https://
doi.org/10.1080/2153599X.2018.1532454
Lang, M., & Kundt, R. (2017). Can predictive coding explain past experiences?
Religion, Brain & Behavior, 7(1), 71–73. https://doi.org/10.1080/215359
9X.2016.1150332
———. (2020). Evolutionary, cognitive, and contextual approaches to the study of
religious systems: A proposition of synthesis. Method & eory in the Study of
Religion, 32(1), 1–46. https://doi.org/10.1163/15700682-12341466
Lang, M., Purzycki, B. G., Apicella, C. L., Atkinson, Q. D., Bolyanatz, A., Cohen, E.,
Handley, C., Kundtová Klocová, E., Lesorogol, C., Mathew, S., McNamara,
Religious Experiences and Cultural Priors 51
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2021
R. A., Moya, C., Placek C. D., Soler, M., Vardy, T., Weigel, J. L, Willard,
A. K., Xygalatas, D., Norenzayan, A., & Henrich, J. (2019). Moralizing
gods, impartiality and religious parochialism across 15 societies. Proceedings
of the Royal Society B, 286(1898), 20190202. https://doi.org/10.1098/
rspb.2019.0202
Luhrmann, T. M. (2012). When God talks back: Understanding the American
evangelical relationship with God. New York: Random House. https://doi.
org/10.24260/alalbab.v1i1.16
Luhrmann, T. M., Weisman, K., Aulino, F., Brahinsky, J. D., Dulin, J. C., Dzokoto,
V. A., Legare, C. H., Lifshitz, M., Ng, E., Ross-Zehnder, N., & Smith,
R.E. (2021). Sensing the presence of gods and spirits across cultures and
faiths. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 118(5). https://doi.
org/10.1073/pnas.2016649118
McAdams, D. P. (1993). e stories we live by: Personal myths and the making of the
self. New York: Guilford.
McAdams, D. P. (2001). e psychology of life stories. Review of General Psychology,
5(2), 100–122. https://doi.org/10.1037/1089-2680.5.2.100
McCauley, R. N., & Bechtel, W. (2001). Explanatory pluralism and heuristic
identity theory. eory & Psychology, 11(6), 736–760. https://doi.
org/10.1177/0959354301116002
McCauley, R. N., & Graham, G. (2020). Hearing voices and other matters of the
mind: What mental abnormalities can teach us about religions. Oxford: Oxford
University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190091149.001.0001
McNamara, P., Durso, R., & Brown, A. (2006). Religiosity in patients with
Parkinson’s disease. Neuropsychiatric Disease and Treatment, 2(3), 341–348.
https://doi.org/10.2147/nedt.2006.2.3.341
Neimeyer, R. A. (2000). Narrative disruptions in the construction of self. In R. A.
Neimeyer & J. D. Raskin (Eds.), Constructions of disorder: Meaning-making
frameworks for psychotherapy (pp. 207–241). Washington, DC: American
Psychological Association. https://doi.org/10.1037/10368-000
Newson, M., Buhrmester, M., Xygalatas, D., & Whitehouse, H. (2020). Go WILD,
Not WEIRD. Journal for the Cognitive Science of Religion, 6(1–2), 80–106.
https://doi.org/10.1558/jcsr.38413
Norenzayan, A., Shari, A. F., Gervais, W. M., Willard, A. K., McNamara, R. A.,
Slingerland, E., & Henrich, J. (2016). e cultural evolution of prosocial
religions. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 39, 1–65. https://doi.org/10.1017/
S0140525X14001356
Purzycki, B. G., Apicella, C., Atkinson, Q. D., Cohen, E., McNamara, R. A., Willard,
A. K., Xygalatas, D., Norenzayan, A. & Henrich, J. (2016). Moralistic gods,
supernatural punishment and the expansion of human sociality. Nature,
530(7590), 327–330. https://doi.org/10.1038/nature16980
52 Valerie van Mulukom and Martin Lang
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2021
Purzycki, B. G., & McNamara, R. A. (2016). An ecological theory of gods’ minds.
In H. De Cruz, & R. Nichols (Eds.), Cognitive science of religion and its
philosophical implications (pp. 143–167). New York: Continuum.
Roth, I. (2007). Autism and the imaginative mind. In I. Roth (Ed.), Imaginative minds
(pp. 277–306). Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.5871/
bacad/9780197264195.001.0001
Schacter, D. L., & Addis, D. R. (2007). e cognitive neuroscience of constructive
memory: Remembering the past and imagining the future. Philosophical
Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 362(1481), 773–786.
https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2007.2087
Schjoedt, U., Sørensen, J., Nielbo, K. L., Xygalatas, D., Mitkidis, P., & Bulbulia, J.
(2013a). Cognitive resource depletion in religious interactions. Religion, Brain
& Behavior, 3(1), 39–55. https://doi.org/10.1080/2153599X.2012.736714
———. (2013b). e resource model and the principle of predictive coding:
A framework for analyzing proximate eects of ritual. Religion, Brain &
Behavior, 3(1), 79–86. https://doi.org/10.1080/2153599X.2012.745447
Sears, D. O. (1986). College sophomores in the laboratory: Inuences of a
narrow data base on social psychology’s view of human nature. Journal
of Personality and Social Psychology, 51(3), 515–530. https://doi.
org/10.1037/0022-3514.51.3.515
Sosis, R. (2020). e last Talmudic demon? e role of ritual in cultural transmission.
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 375(1805), 20190425.
https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2019.0425
Taves, A., & Asprem, E. (2017). Experience as event: Event cognition and the study
of (religious) experiences. Religion, Brain & Behavior, 7(1), 43–62. https://
doi.org/10.1080/2153599X.2016.1150327
Tewari, S., Khan, S., Hopkins, N., Srinivasan, N., & Reicher, S. (2012). Participation
in mass gatherings can benet well-being: Longitudinal and control data
from a North Indian Hindu pilgrimage event. PLoS ONE, 7(10), e47291.
https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0047291
Tulving, E. (1985a). How many memory systems are there? American Psychologist,
40(4), 385–398. https://doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.40.4.385
———. (1985b). Memory and consciousness. Canadian Psychology/Psychologie
Canadienne, 26(1), 1–12. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0080017
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1973). Availability: A heuristic for judging
frequency and probability. Cognitive Psychology, 5(2), 207–232. https://doi.
org/10.1016/0010-0285(73)90033-9
———. (1993). Probabilistic reasoning. In E. Goldman (Ed.), Readings in philosophy
and cognitive science (pp. 43–68). Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Institute of
Technology Press.
van Elk, M., & Wagenmakers, E.-J. (2017). Can the experimental study of religion be
advanced using a Bayesian predictive framework? Religion, Brain & Behavior,
7(4), 331–334. https://doi.org/10.1080/2153599X.2016.1249915
Religious Experiences and Cultural Priors 53
© Equinox Publishing Ltd. 2021
van Mulukom, V. (2017). Remembering religious rituals: autobiographical memories
of high-arousal religious rituals considered from a narrative processing
perspective. Religion, Brain & Behavior, 7(3), 191–205. https://doi.org/10.10
80/2153599X.2016.1232304
———. (2019). e cognitive science of imagination and religion. Journal for the
Cognitive Science of Religion, 5(1), 5–20. https://doi.org/10.1558/jcsr.39503
———. (2020). e evolution of imagination and ction through generativity
and narrative. In J. Carroll, M. Clasen & E. Jonsson (Eds.). Evolutionary
Perspectives on Imaginative Culture (pp. 53–70). Cham: Springer. https://doi.
org/10.1007/978-3-030-46190-4_3
van Mulukom, V., Schacter, D. L., Corballis, M. C., & Addis, D. R. (2016).
e degree of disparateness of event details modulates future simulation
construction, plausibility, and recall. e Quarterly Journal of Experimental
Psychology, 69(2), 234–242. https://doi.org/10.1080/17470218.2015.1051
559
Visuri, I. (2018). Rethinking autism, theism, and atheism: Bodiless agents and
imaginary realities. Archive for the Psychology of Religion, 40(1), 1–31. https://
doi.org/10.1163/15736121-12341348
———. (2019). A room of one’s own: Autistic imagination as a stage for parasocial
interaction and social learning. Journal for the Cognitive Science of Religion,
5(1), 100–124. https://doi.org/10.1558/jcsr.37518
———. (2020). Sensory supernatural experiences in autism. Religion,
Brain & Behavior, 10(2), 151–165. https://doi.org/10.1080/215359
9X.2018.1548374
Waters, T. E. (2014). Relations between the functions of autobiographical memory
and psychological wellbeing. Memory, 22(3), 265–275. https://doi.org/10.10
80/09658211.2013.778293
Williams, J. M. G., Ellis, N. C., Tyers, C., Healy, H., Rose, G., & Macleod, A.
K. (1996). e specicity of autobiographical memory and imageability of
the future. Memory & Cognition, 24(1), 116–125. https://doi.org/10.3758/
BF03197278
Wise, R. A. (2004). Dopamine, learning and motivation. Nature Reviews Neuroscience,
5(6), 483–494. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrn1406
Xygalatas, D., Khan, S., Lang, M., Kundt, R., Kundtová-Klocová, E., Krátký, J., &
Shaver, J. (2019). Eects of extreme ritual practices on psychophysiological
well-being. Current Anthropology, 60(5), 699–707. https://doi.
org/10.1086/705665