Content uploaded by Cathy Devine
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Cathy Devine on Jun 25, 2021
Content may be subject to copyright.
1
Extensive sociological literature analyses the Olympic Games as a mega-event at the pinnacle
of globalised neoliberal sport culture, with associated socio-political-economic and
ideological struggles for democracy justice and human rights (Horne, 2015; Jennings, 2011).
Critiques explore the gap between mission rhetoric proclaiming ‘the harmonious
development of humankind’ (IOC, 2020a: 11), and the reality of an unaccountable
transnational megalith. In this tradition, critiquing the historically patriarchal IOC celebrating
hegemonic masculinity is important. Female athlete inclusion in the difficult deliberations
regarding the fairest way to include transgender athletes is of contemporary relevance in this
regard.
The Olympic Charter asserts sport is a human right (IOC, 2020a: 11) ‘without discrimination
of any kind, such as … sex …’ (12). The IOC’s role is to ‘ensure the spirit of fair play
prevails’ (16), ‘support the promotion of women in sport at all levels and … the principle of
equality of men and women’ (17) and ‘promote safe sport and the protection of athletes from
all forms of harassment and abuse’ (17). Further, the IOC (2015: 2/3) outlines ‘it is necessary
to ensure insofar as possible that trans athletes are not excluded from the opportunity to
participate’ but reiterates ‘the overriding sporting objective is and remains the guarantee of
fair competition’. It explains ‘restrictions on participation are appropriate to the extent that
they are necessary and proportionate’ and outlines transgender guidelines to be ‘taken into
account’ by governing bodies of sport (GBS) when determining eligibility criteria. Thus, at
least rhetorically, the IOC is committed to fairness, equality between the sexes, and
transgender inclusion if this does not compromise fairness or safety. In essence, although
international human rights instruments do not recognise sport as a human right (Devine,
2013), IOC aspirations mean inclusion claims of both female and transgender athletes must
be fairly and safely balanced.
2
The fair and safe inclusion of females is secured via single sex categories for most sports
given well-established biological and performance-related differentials between the sexes
(Bermon et al, 2019; Handelsman et al, 2018; Harper et al, 2021; Hilton and Lundberg, 2021;
Knox et al, 2018). The socio-historically contextualised sex-related performance gap stopped
narrowing in the 1980’s revealing underlying biological differentials (Thibault et al, 2010).
Hilton and Lundberg explain testosterone-driven male puberty ‘underpins sporting
advantages that are so large no female could reasonably hope to succeed without sex
segregation in most sporting competitions’. Thus, in 2019 the fastest woman in the world,
Shelly-Anne Fraser-Pryce, ran 100 metres in 10.71s, 2160 adult males and 107 boys (under
18’s) are listed as running faster (IAAF, n.d.) and 10 000 males have faster personal bests
(Hilton and Lundberg, 2021). These sex-differentials hold true across all athletic events
including the marathon where Brigid Kosgei’s all-time women’s record of 2:14:04 was
exceeded in 2019 alone by 586 listed males (IAAF, n.d.). Without single sex categories, the
fastest highest and strongest females would disappear from most elite sport. Inclusion of
transwomen via female categories is therefore controversial and may be difficult to reconcile
with fairness for females.
IOC plans to revise transgender guidelines prior to Tokyo 2020 were delayed since
agreement was ‘far more difficult than expected because this is such a tricky political and
emotive issue’ (Ingle, 2019a). In their absence, World Athletics and four additional
international GBS reduced the upper limit for serum testosterone for transwomen in the
female category to 5 nmol/l (World Athletics, 2019), half that suggested by the IOC. Further,
World Rugby (2020a), following an extensive scientific review and elite player survey
(World Rugby, 2020b), decided ‘transgender women may not currently play women’s rugby’
and revised rules require competition in sex not gender categories.
Aims
3
This research is contextualised by the feminist socio-cultural-political and citizenship theory
of Pateman, Fraser and Lister who argue for recognition and ‘voice’ of all affected by the
reach of any socio-cultural-political policy. The IOC Transgender guidelines frame inclusion
of transwomen as via female categories and consequently female Olympians are stakeholders.
The aims are firstly, to investigate whether female Olympians have been consulted by the
IOC and GBS and secondly, to solicit their ‘voices’. Females who have competed in any
Olympic Games were eligible to participate.
Background
Initial IOC Transgender guidelines for eligibility in female categories (2003) recommended
completed surgery, legal recognition of reassigned sex, and hormone therapy. Revised
Guidelines (IOC, 2015) reiterated the overriding commitment to fairness and that necessary
and proportionate restrictions to transgender participation may be appropriate. The
requirement for surgery and legal recognition were removed and serum testosterone adopted
as a proxy for male-advantage. These Guidelines suggest self-declaration of female gender
identity and serum testosterone below 10nmol/L for at least 12 months. However, reference
female serum testosterone is 0-1.7 nmols/L and for males significantly higher at 7.7-29.4
nmols/L (Handelsman et al, 2018), explaining the lower World Athletics limit and anticipated
IOC revisions. Further, recent scientific reviews of male-advantage mitigation conclude
‘strength may be well preserved in transwomen during the first 3 years of hormone therapy’
(Harper et al 2021) notwithstanding ‘most therapeutic interventions result in almost complete
suppression of testosterone levels, certainly well below 5 nmol/L’ (Hilton and Lundberg,
2021 211).
World Rugby’s elite female survey (2020b) finds only a minority of Women’s Sevens World
Series (17 of 86, 20%), Women’s Six Nations (7 of 65, 11%) and other elite players (10 of
4
29, 34%) support introducing the IOC Guidelines in rugby, or transwomen playing in elite
female competition (Women’s Sevens World Series: 16 of 86, 19%; Women’s Six Nations: 6
of 65, 9%; other elite players: 10 of 29, 34%).
Importantly, populations with disorders/differences/variations of sexual development
(DSDs/VSDs) have minimal overlap with transgender populations (García-Acero et al;
ISNA, n.d.). Consequently, GBS have distinct eligibility guidelines for these athletes (IOC,
2015, IAAF, 2019a; 2019b).
Theoretical Framework
‘meta-political misrepresentation arises when states and transnational elites
monopolise the activity of frame-setting, denying voice to those who may be harmed
in the process’ (Fraser, 2008 p26)
Feminist socio-cultural-political and citizenship work documents that historically ‘persons’
‘citizens’ ‘moral agents’ and ‘human rights’ have recognised only or primarily males, with
females excluded from full status and the social contract between persons and civil society.
Pateman’s work explains that women historically did not possess ‘property in the person’,
were not party to the contract but rather the subject of it. Consequently, women were the
property of men and ‘the contract establishes men's political right over women …
establishing orderly access by men to women's bodies' (1988: 2). The Convention on the
Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women (UN, 1979) is the international
human rights instrument designed to address hegemonic masculinity of patriarchal citizenship
and recognises discrimination against women on the basis of sex.
Nevertheless, female exclusion from personhood and decision-making about themselves and
their bodies is evident in contemporary global policy arenas including sport (Burt, 2020;
Devine 2016). Lister (2003) terms this ‘androcentric citizenship’ which presents as universal
5
and sex-neutral but includes female citizens primarily as recipients or subjects of decisions
made about them and their bodies rather than decision-making agents. She notes ‘behind the
cloak of gender-neutrality … there lurks … a definitely male citizen, and it is his interests
and concerns that have traditionally dictated the agenda’ (4). Further, ‘to the extent that (a)
universalist principle in fact embodies masculine particularist interests, women will remain
excluded or will be included only on male terms' (199). Androcentric citizenship and human
rights frameworks foreground male interests whilst females remain de facto second-class.
Lister proposes an inclusive universal differentiated, rather than androcentric (sex-blind)
citizenship requiring ‘status’ recognition of females as members of communities and
‘practice’ recognition as socio-cultural-political participation or ‘voice’ in public life so
women’s voices carry equal democratic weight.
Fraser’s work on justice involves mapping the socio-cultural-political terrain in any human
endeavour, identifying ‘subjects of justice’ and fairly balancing countervailing inclusion
claims. Interrogating naturalised hegemonic frames is central since if drawn too narrowly,
legitimate subjects of justice are excluded from contested cultural arenas. Contestation may
comprise conflicting ontologies and incommensurability between inclusion claims.
Accordingly, Fraser adopts a critical democratic theory of framing, drawing socio-cultural-
political maps more broadly at meta-political levels, foregrounding transborder injustices and
avoiding mis-recognition mis-framing and gerrymandering of socio-cultural-political space.
To this end, mapping and balancing involve three inextricably linked components: cultural
recognition, political participation and economic redistribution (Fraser, 2008).
Application
‘this feminine semi-Olympiad is impractical, uninteresting, ungainly, and…improper.
It is not in keeping with my concept of the Olympic Games … the solemn and periodic
6
exaltation of male athleticism…with the applause of women as a reward’ (De
Coubertin, 1912: 713)
All frames, including IOC committees and competition categories create, by definition,
boundaries and exclusions but the test of fairness is that these are just. Crucially, when
framing any socio-cultural-political space ‘all those affected by a given social structure or
institution have moral standing as subjects of justice’ (Fraser, 2008: 24).
De Coubertin’s androcentrism is unsurprising given most modern sports celebrate hegemonic
masculinity. Nevertheless, although female elite competitor status is increasingly recognised,
this is incomplete and possibly fragile. Females comprised 2.2% of athletes at the 1900
Olympics and by Rio 2016 just 45% of athletes and 11% of coaches were women. Decision-
making is far from egalitarian and leading into Rio, 62 National Olympic Committees (NOC)
were less than 20% female and ten included no women (IOC, 2020b). Further, the sexist
remarks of the Head of the Tokyo NOC resulted in resignation six months before the
rescheduled 2021 Games, and as a concession, Japan’s ruling Party invited five women to
observe but not speak, at its all-male Board Meetings (BBC, 2021a). The IOC Board is 30%
female and five of 20 IOC 2015 Transgender Panel members were female. Whether this
Panel sought elite female or transgender athlete representation is unknown, but it included
one transwoman. Estimated transgender population prevalence is up to 1%, two thirds of
whom are biological males (Collin et al, 2016; Stonewall n.d.).
Inclusion and Fairness
“discussions so far have confirmed considerable tension between the notions of
fairness and inclusion, and the desire and need to protect the women’s category,”
(IOC, cited by Pavitt, 2020)
7
Notwithstanding the IOC’s overarching fairness principle, the dominant discourse assumes
that instead of inclusion being dependent on fair eligibility criteria, inclusion and fairness are
in tension. Further, transgender inclusion via ‘tolerable unfairness’ appears privileged over
female inclusion via fairness (Devine, 2019; Gooren and Bunck, 2004; Knox et al, 2019).
Thus, three IOC Panel members published ‘Beyond Fairness: The Biology of Inclusion for
Transgender and Intersex Athletes’ (Pitsiladis et al, 2016), and some IOC scientists are
attempting ‘a reasonable compromise between inclusion and fairness’ (Ingle, 2019a).
A fairness/inclusion opposition rather than alignment discourse assumes transwomen’s
biological advantages are less important than social disadvantages, even in elite sport,
justifying inclusion in female categories. This is problematic, given females are widely
recognised as socio-culturally, politically and economically disadvantaged (Burt, 2020), and
biologically disadvantaged in most sports. Equality is not yet achieved within Olympic
categories, elite sport, sports participation or decision-making structures in sport and wider
society. Further, female inclusion necessitates fair competition categories recognising female
sexed bodies and performance-related consequences. If the overarching fairness principle is
displaced by inclusion, athletes asked to ‘tolerate’ unfairness are certainly subjects of justice
and should be centrally involved in policy development.
Importantly, transwomen as distinct from transgender advocacy organisations and many
trans-allies and academics, espouse heterogenous positions. Joanna Harper, IOC Panel
transgender member, adopts a fairness/inclusion opposition discourse and whilst
acknowledging, ‘Transgender women after hormone therapy are taller, bigger and stronger on
average than cisgender (sic) women.’ believes,
‘But that does not necessarily make it unfair. In high levels of sport transgender
women are substantially under-represented. That indicates that, whatever physical
8
advantages transgender women have – and they certainly exist – they are not nearly as
large as the sociological disadvantages’ (Ingle, 2019b).
Conversely, Caitlyn Jenner, 1976 Olympic gold medal winner prior to transition, advocates a
fairness/inclusion alignment commenting, ‘This is a question of fairness…That's why I
oppose biological boys who are trans competing in girls' sports in school. It just isn't fair.’
(BBC, 2 May 2021b). Similarly, Renee Richards, a medical doctor who played on the
professional women’s tennis circuit in her 40’s elucidates ‘I think transsexuals have every
right to play, but maybe not at the professional level, because it’s not a level playing field’
explaining ‘I know if I’d had surgery at the age of 22, and then at 24 went on the tour, no
genetic woman in the world would have been able to come close to me. And so I’ve
reconsidered my opinion’ (Bazelon, 2012).
A dichotomy exists between scientific/quantitative and humanities/qualitative disciplines
with the former foregrounding ‘fairness’ or ‘tolerable unfairness’ by exploring mitigation of
the widely accepted puberty-related male-advantage (Bermon et al, 2019; Gooren and Bunck,
2004; Handelsman et al, 2018; Hilton and Lundberg, 2021; Knox et al, 2018; Thibault et al,
2010). In contrast, the humanities/qualitative literature often asymmetrically prioritises
gender identity recognition and transgender inclusion, while discounting female exclusion via
unfairness, or minimising misunderstanding or denying the science regarding biological and
performance-related sex differences (Gleaves and Lehrbach, 2016; Anderson and Travers
2017) and that documenting legacy puberty-related male-advantage of transwomen (Gooren
and Bunck, 2004; Harper et al, 2021; Hilton and Lundberg, 2021; Wiik et al, 2020). Thus,
Gleaves and Lehrbach argue ‘inclusion of transgender and intersex athletes must move
beyond the idea of fairness’ (Gleaves and Lehrbach, 2016: 323) and be ‘unaffected by
contingent appeals to science’ (314).
9
These perspectives align with gender identity theory grounded in postmodern/queer theory
(Burt, 2020; Lowrey, 2021; Suissa and Sullivan, 2021) and dominant particularly in North
America. This epistemological orthodoxy draws heavily on Butler (2006) who famously
collapses the conceptual sex/gender binary, and Fausto-Sterling criticised for over-estimating
‘intersex’ prevalence (García-Acero et al, 2020; Sax, 2002), claiming five sexes and
subsequently acknowledging this as tongue-in-cheek (n.d.). The gender identity theory
conceptualisation of gender departs from both the inaccurate gender as a synonym for sex,
and established scientific (Heidari et al, 2016) and historical feminist (Stone, 2007)
understandings of the analytically distinct sex and gender where gender depicts socio-cultural
historically contextualised femininity and masculinity. Historically feminism has conceived
these as contested hierarchical stereotypes essential to the subjugation of women and
maintenance of patriarchy. Instead, gender identity theory deconstructs or reverses sex and
gender, so gender metamorphosises into an innate essence albeit subjective and unverifiable,
whilst sex becomes socially constructed, ideological and ‘assigned at birth’. Gender identity
theorists believe biological sex itself (not sex characteristics) exists on a spectrum, because
the endocrine systems of both sexes include testosterone albeit in non-over-lapping ranges,
and female and male sport performance distributions overlap (Anderson and Travers, 2017).
Consequently, gender identity should overwrite sex, sex categories become gender
categories, and sex segregation in sport is reconstructed as oppressive rather than essential for
female inclusion. Sometimes an understanding of human sexual dimorphism is linked to
whiteness where ‘assumptions of unfair male advantage…lean heavily on a Western image of
white middle- and upper-class female frailty’ (Anderson and Travers, 2017: 3).
Critics argue gender identity theory encompasses (at least) three problematic conceptual
conflations: immutable biological sex with socially constructed gender; transgender people
without DSDs, with people with DSDs who are not transgender (García-Acero et al, 2020;
10
ISNA, n.d); and sex segregation in sport (based on biological reality) with race segregation
(unscientific racist ideology). Also, in sport, conflation of historical/contemporary
exploitation and sex-testing of DSD athletes, with transgender inclusion guidelines permitting
therapeutic use exemptions for prohibited substances (WADA, 2017). Biological realists
maintain anisogamous sex, determined at conception, immutable and unproblematically
classified in 99.98% of humans including transgender athletes, is settled science (Bhargava et
al., 2021; 2019; Hull, 2006; Sax, 2002) but should not determine social roles of females and
males. Also, people with DSDs support rather than negate the sex binary given, by definition,
DSDs are disorders/differences of either female or male sexual development not additional
sexes. Further, conceptualising innate gender identities reinscribes rather than deconstructs
oppressive hierarchical gender stereotypes assigning a feminine ‘cisgender’ identity to
females in direct contradistinction to historical/contemporary struggles to dismantle gendered
social scripts (Burt, 2020; Suissa and Sullivan 2021). Accordingly, gender identity theory
appears definitionally sexist, denying the importance of female sex to the recognition and
human rights of females and redefining them as sexist gender stereotypes.
Further, Crenshaw’s work on discrimination discourse at the intersections of sex race and
class (1989) together with a transnational feminist lens (Ratna, 2018) necessitate avoiding
homogenising black female athletes within dominant epistemologies. Empirical work by and
with black female athletes and athletes of colour, including their voices on sex and gender, is
under-represented/non-existent in sport sociology. However, given black elite female athletes
particularly from the global south including Fraser-Pryce from Jamaica and Kosgei from
Kenya are well represented in athletics and depend on female categories for their success, it
seems unlikely they do not share an understanding of the importance of human sexual
dimorphism for female sport. In sum, disappearing sex/females and consequently sexism, is
seen by critics as supporting institutions and practices reflecting and reinforcing rather than
11
resisting intersectional power configurations between females and males, in this case within
sport. This is perpetuated by knowledge production of privileged white academics from the
global north, often male, speaking on behalf of heterogeneous hegemonically excluded black
female athletes from the global south, rather than soliciting their voices.
Nevertheless, most stop short of prescribing and policing female athlete’s voices and
permitted interventions by way of coerced solidarity and allyship (Anderson and Loland,
2015; Teetzel, 2020) and Teetzel concedes ‘very little is known about athlete’s opposition to
trans-inclusive sport’ (10) acknowledging ‘athletes need to be able to exercise their freedom
of speech and not be stifled’. Consequently, regardless of theoretical allegiance, whether to
biological realism and human sexual dimorphism, or gender identity theory, there is
agreement female athletes’ voices should be heard.
Method
Female Olympic athletes are a hard to reach ‘hidden’ demographic given the worldwide
celebrity and high-profile status of many, some of whom are household names.
Consequently, they take significant measures to protect privacy and manage time by
balancing demands of training, travelling and competing with those of work, family and
sponsors. Olympians prepared to comment on this contentious issue are doubly difficult to
access and trust between participants and researcher is paramount. Therefore, probability
sampling was not feasible (Bryman, 2015: 415) and a non-probability purposive snowball
sampling design adopted. Further, given their related reluctance to participate in focus groups
or interviews, an online instrument was the only way to collect data.
Noy (2006: 331) explains snowball sampling is used to access marginalised communities but
also ‘groups that do not suffer from stigmas and marginalization, but, to the contrary, enjoy
the status of social elites’ and are ‘hidden by choice’. Given there is no research with female
12
Olympians on this issue and they are centrally important stakeholders in IOC and GBS policy
development, access was of primary concern for this exploratory study. Female Olympians
are marginalised both by the hegemonic masculinity of elite sport structures, and their
‘hidden by choice’ high-profile celebrity status. Noy explains snowball sampling is
particularly useful for feminist hermeneutics and generates ‘a unique type of social
knowledge—knowledge which is emergent, political and interactional’.
The mixed methods design involved data collection via Survey Monkey questionnaire
consisting of career and contact data and 39 closed Likert-style questions grouped in seven
themes with additional open questions. The themes were: IOC Guidelines, fairness, scientific
evidence, impact on female categories, consultation and discussion, what should happen next,
and the fairest way to include transwomen. The questionnaire was cascaded via one
Olympian to her networks and the researcher approached by two additional contacts.
The purpose of the study was clearly described in recruitment information, electronic consent
obtained and participants could ask questions and withdraw consent at any time. Athletes
were assured they would not be identifiable via sport, medals or Olympic Games attended.
Due to the sensitive subject Olympians were asked to keep the Survey confidential.
Additional athletes were referred to the original cascading Olympian or the researcher
avoiding the risk of sabotage and ensuring submissions were verified as from Olympians. It
was explained the research related only to transgender guidelines and not guidelines for
athletes with DSDs. Data were collected between May and December 2019.
Since the purpose of the research was to describe and present the views of female Olympians
the non-probability research design did not test hypotheses or make predictions for the wider
female Olympic population. Because of the unique participant group, retaining data richness
and foregrounding individual participants’ voices was essential to ensure depth and meaning
13
were not diluted or homogenised through extensive data processing. Consequently,
descriptive statistical analysis was used for quantitative data and presented as frequency
distributions. Further, all open-ended responses for each theme were anonymised and
included in the results to retain nuance richness and meaning.
Participants
Anecdotal feedback suggested a shorter instrument would have generated more participants.
However, the trade-off was between participant numbers and data richness, and the detailed
questionnaire was retained. Nineteen Olympians responded with a mean age of 41 (n=15),
seven athletes under 35 and four over 50 (Figure 1), not all answered all questions.
Represented sports were hockey athletics rowing swimming and modern pentathlon, most
Olympians were from athletics, and represented countries were Britain Australia and Canada.
Many of these athletes are/were the best in the world and between them, attended all Olympic
Games from 1976 to 2016. Three attended Rio 2016 and five London 2012 (figure 2), they
have six gold, two silver and one bronze Olympic medal and additional top six placings
(figure 3), plus many additional world championship titles medals and records.
Detailed intersectional data were not collected, however, some athletes are black, some with
global south heritage, one a Paralympian and several from under-privileged backgrounds. No
data on sexuality were collected as this was considered overly intrusive.
14
Table 1: Age of Olympians
Table 2: Olympic games attended
Olympic Games
Number of Olympians
1976 Montreal
2
1980 Moscow
2
1984 Los Angeles
2
1988 Seoul
3
1992 Barcelona
6
1996 Atlanta
7
2000 Sydney
5
2004 Athens
5
2008 Beijing
4
2012 London
5
2016 Rio de Janeiro
3
Table 3: Olympic medals and placings
Medals/Placings
Number
Gold
6
Silver
2
Bronze
1
Fourth
4
Fifth
2
Sixth
4
Results and Descriptive Analysis
The descriptive statistics are presented in figures 4-10 and all comments numbered and
anonymised.
Theme 1: The IOC recommendations.
Age (years)
Number of Athletes
25-29
3
30-34
4
35-39
0
40-44
1
45-49
3
50-54
2
55-59
2
15
Figure 1a
Figure 1b
0% 0%
11% 11%
17%
0%
17%
11%
6%
28%
0% 0%
39%
33% 33%
39%39% 39% 39% 39%
0
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
I was aware of the IOC
2003
recommendations
involving genital
surgery and hormone
therapy
There was
consultation with
female athletes before
introduction of 2003
recommendations
I was aware of the
2015 IOC
recommendation
change so surgery is
now not necessary
I was aware the level
of T allowed for TG
athletes in female
categories is >5x
higher than normal
female range
Figure 1a: IOC Transgender guidelines
Strongly agree Agree No opinion Disagree Strongly disagree
16
Figures 1a and 1b show the majority of athletes were unaware of the 2003 recommendations,
2015 revisions and any consultation with athletes prior to agreement of either set of
guidelines. Athlete 17 commented,
‘I'm not sure how to answer the "I was aware..." questions. I was aware of the
changes in 2015 but NOT in 2003. As well, I’m simply saying I was aware of the
changes, but not that I agreed with those recommendations.’
Athlete 14 contributed,
‘I feel that the opinions of female athletes on such a controversial matter need to be
explained and presented so the facts are clear. Only then can their voices be heard
…Most female athletes have no clue about the decisions that take place behind their
backs that have a direct impact on the sport in which they participate. This is not
right.’
0%
78%
0%
61%
0%
17%
0%
28%
22%
0%
6%
0%
22%
0%
22%
11%
56%
6%
72%
0%
0
2
4
6
8
10
12
14
16
There was proper
consultation with female
athletes before 2015
guidelines introduced
IOC 2015 recommendations
will impact on female
athletes
IOC 2015 recommendations
for TG athletes in female
categories are fit for
purpose
IOC 2015 recommendations
should be put on hold
pending further scientific
research and consultation
with female athletes
Figure 1b: IOC Transgender guidelines
Strongly agree Agree No opinion Disagree Strongly disagree
17
Further, the majority were unaware permitted serum testosterone levels are more than five
times the reference female range and some felt very strongly this was unfair. Athlete 19
commented,
‘Men and women are biologically different, hence the need for single sex
competitions in most sports. Any sport where speed, strength and power (most sports)
require separate competitions for males and females to ensure a fair environment for
competition. I agree in principle that transgender athletes need support and protection
to compete without discrimination, but this cannot be at the expense of female
athletes, when it comes to fair competition. The notion that a male can self-declare
that they are transgender and possibly compete with testosterone levels vastly higher
than the normal range for women is open to exploitation, or at the very minimum an
unfair advantage. More research is needed in this area and the 2015 IOC
recommendations need to be put on hold as soon as possible’.
Athlete 9 stated succinctly ‘The testosterone limit should be lower than 10’ and athlete 5
explained,
‘Being a former Olympian I understand how much dedication and hard work athletes
put in to get towards their dream. Competing against “females” with extremely high
testosterone levels creates a totally unfair field, especially when females of the
sporting world are not properly informed, which ruins any sport and the reason why
Olympic Games was brought about.’
Athlete responses centre fairness. They almost unanimously regarded the 2015
recommendations not fit for purpose with 16 agreeing they should be paused pending further
research and consultation with female athletes. Athlete 16 elaborated,
‘It's really hard to know whether they are fit for purpose or not, the scientific evidence
through the media feels patchy, but the media never provide balanced information and
18
statistics. As ever, most scientific evidence relating to females is pretty patchy, so
definitely more research is essential, but we start from a poor base as sports science is
mostly based on male statistics and research. I think there needs to be an international
expert group to work in a well-funded way on this subject, I don't know what exists at
the moment.’
Others were less equivocal, athlete18 noting ‘We seem to be creating a un-fair playing field
for female athletes--- we need to be stronger, have better facts, and communicate better. We
are being pushed around by new social expectations’ and athlete 2 ‘Neither guidelines are fit
for purpose and extensive research should be done before any transgender athletes are
allowed to compete.’
Finally, athlete 15 commented,
‘Years of knowledge & experience in sport shows me there is a huge physical
difference between male & female performance. New guidelines do not level the
playing field or protect equal opportunities for female athletes to achieve successes
based on their biology. Our human rights to equal opportunities (are) not being
protected. There was not enough science-based research on elite athletes to make
rules. It’s a live experiment where female athletes will lose out until the obvious is
proved. Then it will be changed. That’s not fair’.
Theme 2: Fairness
Figure 2a
19
Figure 2b
28%
50%
24%
0%
44%
33%
47%
6%
11%
0%
6%
11%
17% 17%
24% 22%
0% 0% 0%
61%
0
2
4
6
8
10
12
Elite sport should be fair for
female and transgender
athletes
Nobody should be treated
unfairly because of their
biological sex
Nobody should be treated
unfairly because of their
transgender status
Current rules for inclusion
of TG athletes (born male)
in female sport categories
are fair
Figure 2a: Fairness
Strongly agree Agree No opinion Disagree Strongly disagree
20
The IOC fairness principle was explored further in theme 2 (figures 2a and 2b). The majority
agreed elite sport should be fair for both female and transgender athletes and nobody should
be treated unfairly because of biological sex or transgender status. However, most did not
regard current guidelines as fair.
The majority thought male-advantage should be completely eliminated and athletes who have
experienced male puberty can never compete fairly in female categories. Athlete 18 stated ‘I
don't believe athletes born male, developed as male, should be competing in high
performance sport’. Similarly, athlete 19 explained,
‘I do not fully understand the medical aspects of transgender males who transition to
female, but I find it hard to believe that a male who has gone through puberty and
developed male physical characteristics and then undergone treatment to reduce
testosterone levels does not have some physical advantage over female athletes -
56%
17%
56%
6%
22% 22%
17%
22%
11% 11%
6%
17%
6%
28%
22%
28%
6%
22%
0%
28%
0
2
4
6
8
10
12
Rules for inclusion of TG
athletes (born male) in
female categories should
completely eliminate male
advantage
The rules for inclusion of TG
athletes (born male) in
female categories should
minimise male advantage
Can never be fair for TG
athletes (born male) to
compete in female
categories if gone through
male puberty
Is fair for TG athletes (born
male) to compete in female
categories if been through
male puberty but lower T to
within female range
Figure 2b: Fairness
Strongly agree Agree No opinion Disagree Strongly disagree
21
especially if the current nominated level is over 5 times the normal testosterone range
for females. It is not right that females are disadvantaged by an altruistic desire to
include transgender athletes under an unfair policy.’
Athlete 2 commented ‘My understanding is that the physical advantages gained by going
through male puberty (bones, muscles, organs) will not be ‘undone’ by lowering testosterone
levels post-puberty. So anything post-puberty will still leave trans-gender athletes with a
huge and unfair advantage’.
In contrast, just over half agreed it would be fair to include transwomen in female categories
if testosterone was brought within reference female range despite some also agreeing athletes
who have experienced male puberty can never compete fairly in female categories. This
apparent contradiction possibly represents a staged approach to fairness given the current
upper testosterone limit is significantly above the reference female range, lowering this might
represent an improvement, but actual fairness involves excluding athletes who have
experienced male puberty from female categories. Similarly, a minority thought rules should
minimise male-advantage although some also agreed male-advantage should be completely
eliminated. Nevertheless athlete 16 reflected,
‘These are incredibly hard (questions) to answer, what is 'fair'? Is it fair that an athlete
in a country with good support can reach their potential and another isn't funded in the
same country, or elsewhere in the world? Where is the line between natural and
'unnatural' advantage.... How do we define fair, that's one of the challenges, so I think
it's about minimising/levelling playing field, but there is probably never an absolute
that can be achieved’.
Athlete 10 thought,
22
‘It would only seem "fair" if a transgender's serum testosterone level was required to
be "normal" level of a female. I am unsure how they've come to the conclusion that
having 5 times more would not be considered as having an unfair advantage’.
Athlete14 was interesting regarding medication stating,
‘More research and studies need to make clear if there are still advantages for
transgender athletes (born male) in a variety of different sport when they have
lowered their testosterone. I fundamentally don't agree with giving athletes chemically
enhanced drugs to participate in sport’
and athlete 15 acknowledged ‘Don’t know the science enough to answer last question’.
Athlete 8 thought ‘These answers depend on which sport you are referring too. Some sports
are already mixed, some sports do not depend on testosterone to create an advantage’.
Theme 3: The scientific evidence
Figure 3
23
All Olympians thought there was not enough scientific evidence to show no competitive
advantage for transwomen in female categories and most thought the scientific evidence for
transgender inclusion was unclear (Figure 3). Athlete 19 asserted,
‘As a female athlete I have the right to compete in a fair and safe sporting
environment. It is essential, and indeed a responsibility of peak sporting organisations,
that extensive research is undertaken to fully understand the implications of allowing
transgender athletes (male to female who have gone through puberty) to compete
against females’.
Athlete 2 elaborated ‘I believe trans-gender athletes have a significant advantage over
females and scientific research will show this. There are many cases that are blindingly
obvious but for the sake of clarity the research should be done’.
Theme 4: The impact of the 2015 guideline changes
0% 0%
68%
5%
0% 0%
26%
5%
16%
0%
5%
0%
47% 47%
0%
21%
37%
53%
0%
68%
0
2
4
6
8
10
12
14
The scientific evidence for
inclusion is available and
clear
There is enough scientific
evidence to show no
competitive advantage
More scientific research is
needed
No more scientific research
is needed
Figure 3: Scientific evidence
Strongly agree Agree No opinion Disagree Strongly disagree
24
Figure 4
Figure 4 shows the majority thought 2015 guideline changes likely to increase numbers of
transwomen competing, winning medals, and setting world records in female sport. They
almost unanimously thought the guidelines open to exploitation by countries with athlete 19
explaining,
‘We already know that individuals and countries are prepared to cheat to win - this is
why there is such extensive efforts made to stop doping in sport. There is no doubt in
my mind that these rule changes will be exploited by some’
and athlete 2,
‘Sadly history has shown the extent to which some nations and some individuals will
go for the rewards & glory that sporting success can bring. Athletes/governing bodies
37%
47%
53%
63%
53%
32%
26%
32%
11%
21% 21%
5%
0% 0% 0% 0%0% 0% 0% 0%
0
2
4
6
8
10
12
14
The changes are likely to
increaseTG athletes (born
male) participating in
female sport
TG athletes (born male)
winning medals in female
sport is likely to increase
TG athletes (born male)
setting female world
records is likely to increase
These rule changes are
open to exploitation by
some countries
Figure 4: Impact of IOC Guideline changes
Strongly agree Agree No opinion Disagree Strongly disagree
25
risking illness, injury and permanent body changes have happened before and will
happen again’.
Athlete 16 responded,
‘Again, I find it hard to gauge the impact, I think we are talking about a relatively
small number of athletes. There will always be exploitation by some countries/some
athletes, as there are in doping and other areas where we also don't have a perfect
solution by any means or 100% way of creating a level playing field.’
Athlete 10 reiterated the doping analogy and said ‘In my honest opinion, some current world
records were set by women using performance enhancing drugs’.
Theme 5: Consultation and discussion
Figure 5a
5%
0%
11% 11%
5%
0%
33%
39%
16%
5%
50%
6%
63% 63%
5%
44%
11%
32%
0% 0%
0
2
4
6
8
10
12
14
There is respectful and
evidence based discussion
about TG (born male)
inclusion in female
categories
I can ask questions & speak
freely without accusations
of transphobia
I am concerned about
sponsors if I ask questions
or speak freely about TG
inclusion
I am concerned about other
athletes if I ask questions or
speak freely about TG
inclusion
Figure 5a: Consultation and discussion
Strongly agree Agree No opinion Disagree Strongly disagree
26
Figure 5b
The majority of athletes felt unable to ask questions, speak freely or discuss transgender
inclusion in female categories without accusations of transphobia (Figure 5a). Further, most
indicated their GBS has not consulted female athletes or facilitated respectful and evidence-
based discussion (figure 5b). Athlete 16 elaborated,
‘This is a really sensitive discussion and very difficult to discuss publicly. It therefore
requires federations and the professional bodies to be engaging professionally with
this within their work in order to take up the lead, rather than leave it to others.
Professional bodies should be helping athletes to manage the issue, not the other way
as the questions above suggest’.
Of significant concern is athlete 2’s experience,
5% 5%
11%
0%
5%
28%
21%
26%
44%42%
37%
17%
32%
26%
0%
0
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
My GBS has consulted female athletes
re TG athlete (born male) inclusion in
female sport
My GBS has facilitated respectful and
evidence based discussion re TG
inclusion in female sport
I am concerned for my career if I ask
questions or speak freely re TG
athlete (born male) inclusion in
female categories
Figure 5b: Consultation and discussion
Strongly agree Agree No opinion Disagree Strongly disagree
27
‘In my role with a sporting organisation I have been advised to be careful about what I
say on the matter until their guidelines on this subject have been finalised. Athletes
are wary. I have been abused on social media for commenting on this issue. The abuse
is generally vitriolic and aggressive’.
There was mixed feedback regarding sponsor reactions to discussion of the topic with a
significant minority indicating concern. These may be athletes still competing, or working in
some capacity in sport. Regarding other athletes’ reactions, some were concerned and others
not. Possibly athletes’ views are well known in closed settings even if not expressed publicly,
or retired athletes are less concerned about others’ views and more able to speak freely.
The response to career impact if athletes asked questions or spoke freely was again mixed
with some indicating concern, athlete 12 stating ‘Agree but will do it anyway’ and a small
minority who were unconcerned. These may include older Olympians and athlete 19
explained,
‘I think reactions will vary. Some people would be open to respectful discussions and
others not - possibly due to a lack of understanding of the issues that need to be
further researched and understood. As I am long retired from sport, and semi-retired
from work, I am not concerned that my career will be affected by asking questions or
engaging in discussions, but would have concerns about some personal backlash if my
views were public’.
Athlete 18 elaborated ‘I am not worried about my career, sponsors, what others think. I am
concerned that social expectations are driving matters such as this, without elite sport
realising the consequences’.
Theme 6: What should happen next?
28
Figure 6
Almost unanimously these Olympians think eligibility into female categories should be for
female athletes only, with a majority feeling strongly about this (Figure 6). Fairness is
prioritised with athlete 15 elaborating ‘Biology in sport is key, a protected xx class needs
implementing & maintaining for equal opportunities.’ Athlete 19 thinks ‘More research and
understanding is required to ensure female athletes are not disadvantaged by any policy to
allow for inclusion of transgender athletes in female competitions.’
Similarly, the majority agree/strongly agree current IOC Guidelines are unfair and should be
paused. Athlete 16 elaborated,
‘Again I struggle with what 'fair' really means.... we do not live in a fair world on so
many levels beyond this issue.... we need to define what 'reasonable fairness' or
5%
58% 58%
53%
0%
32% 32%
42%
5% 5% 5% 5%
32%
5% 5%
0%
58%
0% 0% 0%
0
2
4
6
8
10
12
The rules for inclusion of TG
athletes (born male) in
female categories are fair
and should stay as they are
The rules for inclusion of TG
athletes (born male) in
female categories are unfair
and should be put on hold
Female athletes should be
consulted about inclusion of
TG athletes (born male) in
female categories
Eligibility into female sport
categories should be for
female athletes only
Figure 6: What should happen next?
Strongly agree Agree No opinion Disagree Strongly disagree
29
'reasonable minimised advantage' actually means. Sports stars are naturally at the
edge of what's possible which allows them to excel’.
Male puberty is revisited by athlete two who explains,
‘As per my previous statement, the changes to a male body through puberty are
significantly different to that of a woman and are the reason why in almost all sports
the competition is divided by gender. It clearly would not be fair otherwise and is
blindingly obvious if you just look around, look at sporting results, look at men and
women in general. To try and say otherwise is completely ridiculous. To say it’s not
fair for trans-genders to not be able to compete is completely negating the fact that it
disadvantages women. Why don’t women matter? I am in support of people living
however they choose but to try and say this wouldn’t disadvantage women in sport is
a lie’.
Further, the majority agree female athletes should be consulted about transgender inclusion in
female categories, however interestingly, athlete 18 commented,
‘I don't believe female athletes should be overly consulted, nor put under pressure to form
a view. I believe it is everyone's role to consider the implication of transgender athletes
competing in female sport, and its everyone's role to ensure we keep a level playing
field’.
Crucially, athlete 17 explained ‘consultation anonymously will be only way to get current
(active sport career) females to speak up.’
Theme 7: What is the fairest way to include transwomen in elite sport?
Figure 7
30
These Olympians unanimously disagreed with transgender inclusion in female categories
without male-advantage mitigation (Figure 7). However, although the majority did not agree
with inclusion in female categories even with hormone/surgery-related restrictions, a
minority supported this. Athlete 18 explained ‘I believe transgender athletes should be able to
compete at all competitions minus the top events (eg world cups and Olympic Games) or
where they are supporting countries to qualify for such events’. Four athletes had no opinion
on third category/open category options with athlete 19 acknowledging ‘I do not pretend to
fully understand the implications of the above options. We need research and facts to base
respectful discussions on before any decisions are made’. The most popular option by a small
margin was for additional categories, however, athlete 4 pointed out ‘It would not be fair to
expect athletes who have had surgery or hormone therapy (to) compete against those who
have not’. Half supported open/protected female categories with athlete 15 explaining ‘Open
0% 6%
37%
26%
0%
28% 21% 21%
0% 6%
21% 21%
16%
33%
16%
26%
84%
28%
5% 5%
0
2
4
6
8
10
12
14
16
18
Include TG athletes (born
male) in female categories
without restrictions
Include TG athletes (born
male) in female categories
with restrictions relating to
hormones and/or surgery
Include a third category for
TG athletes inclusive of all
TG people including those
who do not wish to have
homonal or surgical
intervention
The male category could be
open and the female
category for the female
biological sex only
Figure 7: What is the fairest way to include transwomen?
Strongly agree Agree No opinion Disagree Strongly disagree
31
means no one is excluded’ and athlete 2 ‘I think this is the fairest way to support trans-gender
athletes right to live & compete as a women but to stop female sport being destroyed by
unfair competition’, but a significant minority disagreed. This may be due to lack of
symmetry between open/female, as compared to male/female categories, meaning the female
category is considered secondary.
Discussion
Fairness, scientific evidence and IOC guidelines.
These female Olympians centred fairness, scientific evidence, and the importance of both for
female inclusion in sport. The majority agreed elite sport should be fair for female and
transgender athletes, but not that transgender inclusion should take precedence over fairness
for females. Their principles therefore aligned with the IOC for which transgender inclusion
should be ensured insofar as possible, but the overriding objective remains fairness.
However, the athletes diverged regarding evidence for the IOC guidelines, for two
empirically-related reasons. Firstly, they considered permitted serum testosterone too high to
mitigate male-advantage and secondly, together with former elite transwomen athletes Jenner
and Richards, they were unconvinced the evidence supports mitigation of puberty-related
male-advantage based on testosterone suppression alone.
It is therefore necessary to (re)visit the research. There is a growing consensus that,
notwithstanding the IOC’s fairness principle, achieving ‘tolerable unfairness’ using serum
testosterone as a proxy for male-advantage necessitates lowering the upper limit to 5nmols/l.
This is well above the reference female range, at the top end of female outliers with
polycystic ovary syndrome, and below the male range (Handelsman et al, 2018; World
Athletics, 2019). However, Harper et al (2021), and Hilton and Lundberg (2021) both report
32
therapeutic intervention for non-athletic transwomen achieves testosterone suppression to
well below 5 nmol/l.
This leads to the second question regarding puberty-related male-advantage mitigation via
testosterone suppression alone. Both review articles find that despite extremely low
testosterone levels in transwomen, significant male-advantage is retained. Hilton and
Lundberg (2021, 199) conclude ‘the effects of testosterone suppression on muscle mass and
strength in transgender women consistently show very modest changes, where the loss of lean
body mass, muscle area and strength typically amounts to approximately 5% after 12 months
of treatment’ and Harper et al (2021) that ‘values for strength, LBM (lean body mass) and
muscle area in transwomen remain above those of cisgender (sic) women, even after 36
months of hormone therapy.’ In contrast, male-advantage ranges from 8-12% in running
events (Handelsman et al, 2018) to 50% in some strength and power sports (Hilton and
Lundberg, 2021) and females have ‘31% lower LBM, 36% lower hand-grip strength and 35%
lower knee extension strength’ than males (Harper et al, 2021). The scientific evidence is
unequivocable, testosterone suppression to well below both 5 and 10nmol/l for one year, only
minimally affects male-advantage.
The two specific concerns of these Olympians regarding lack of evidence to support the IOC
guidelines as fair or even ‘tolerably unfair’ are therefore upheld by the scientific literature.
Conversely, significant male-advantage remains following the suggested protocol.
Accordingly, Hilton and Lundberg (p. 211) conclude, ‘These data significantly undermine the
delivery of fairness and safety presumed by the criteria set out in transgender inclusion
policies.’ It appears 2015 IOC guidelines do not align with current scientific evidence and,
notwithstanding the over-arching fairness principle, prioritise transgender inclusion via
intolerable unfairness, over fairness or even tolerable unfairness for females.
33
Consultation and discussion
Given the IOC pre-frames the socio-cultural-political space within which inclusion claims for
transwomen in elite sport are weighed as female categories, female elite athletes are self-
evidently stakeholders and the athletes required to tolerate any unfairness. However, the
majority were unaware of either set of IOC Transgender guidelines and did not think there
has been adequate information or consultation with female athletes. Of real concern was that
the majority of athletes felt unable to ask questions, speak freely or participate in evidence-
based discussion, without being accused of transphobia.
This is corroborated by Teetzel (2020) who documents female Olympians are often labelled
anti-inclusive, transphobic, anti-trans, bigoted or intolerant for questioning the fairness of
existing guidelines and the scientific evidence. Accusations of transphobia (irrational fear of
transgender people) are widespread beyond sport in relation to feminist academics who
support female socio-cultural-political justice on the basis of sex (Burt, 2020; Blackburn,
Murray and Mackenzie, 2021; Lowrey, 2021; Suissa and Sullivan, 2021). These allegations
reprise androcentric discourses, framing women’s socio-cultural-political interventions as
emotional (irrational fears and phobias) rather than rational (logical and evidence-based).
Teetzel, for example, adopts sexist gender stereotypes by assuming female Olympians are
‘acting from jealousy fear or ignorance’ or ‘perpetuating injustices’ (10). This negates their
moral agency, scientific understanding, embodied lived experience, and equal socio-cultural-
political value within policy deliberations regarding their own categories. Given these
Olympians’ views aligned with the IOC principles, the scientific evidence and the views of
some ex-elite transwomen athletes, their views cannot be considered transphobic bigoted or
intolerant. That is, unless the overarching fairness principle, scientific literature and ex-elite
transwomen are also considered to be so.
34
To the contrary, these athletes demonstrated reasonable considered and respectful
engagement and concern for fair inclusion of transgender people. Consequently, athlete 14
fundamentally disagreed with eligibility criteria requiring medication, athlete 4 outlined the
unfairness of athletes with hormonal/surgical intervention competing in third categories
against those without, and athlete 18 that ‘transgender athletes should be able to compete at
all competitions minus the top events.’
What should happen next?
The athletes overwhelming agreed with Harper et al (2021) and Hilton and Lundsberg (2021)
that research is necessary with elite transgender athletes including investigation of scientific
protocols which might eliminate/mitigate male-advantage. To explore the extent to which
these might be considered fair/tolerably unfair, female athletes and heterogenous transwomen
should be meaningfully consulted. Further, as Athlete 16 identified, given scientific research
is androcentric, research with female athletes who are the comparators needs attention
beyond circulating testosterone levels. This accords with Brown et al (2020) who report the
‘dearth of female-specific research in sport, and in sports medicine’. The specific
morphology, biomechanics, physiology and endocrinology of females is under-researched
which Heidari et al (2016) explain ‘limits the generalizability of research findings and their
applicability… in particular for women’.
In the meantime, these athletes favoured pausing IOC Guidelines and exploring alternative
solutions, including additional transgender categories, or protected female categories together
with open categories. The latter might actually maximise transgender inclusion, since a
minority of transgender people undergo any hormonal/surgical transition (Collin et al, 2016),
and social-only transition would exclude transwomen and male non-binary athletes from
35
female categories requiring male-advantage mitigation, but enable inclusive competition in
open categories.
Conclusions
This exploratory research investigated the intersectional hegemonically excluded ‘hidden by
choice’ voices of 19 female Olympians regarding IOC Transgender guidelines, but may not
be representative, preventing generalisability. The emergent knowledge should therefore be
developed by the IOC and GBS including, in particular, black elite female athletes and
athletes of colour from the global south.
However the socio-cultural-political space for transgender inclusion is mapped, whether at
first-order meta-political levels or as single sex categories, female elite athletes are ‘subjects
of justice’ and entitled to the full citizenship and human rights of both status and practice
within elite and Olympic sport communities. Yet these female Olympians, have not been
recognised and afforded equal political participation in policy formulation. This social justice
deficit means female athletes are recipients of arguably coercive evaluative decisions
regarding their own categories and sexed bodies. Further, given they felt unable to speak
without being termed transphobic, the wider female athlete population may feel similarly
silenced mis-recognised and mis-represented. This is a significant democratic failing by the
IOC and GBS which should rightly recognise the unique embodied lived experiences of
female elite athletes. Further, the IOC and GBS should ensure ‘protection of athletes from all
forms of harassment and abuse’ (IOC, 2020) including accusations of transphobia, for
contributing to eligibility deliberations about their own categories.
These Olympians agreed with the IOC’s over-arching fairness principle but, in common with
some ex-elite transwomen athletes, did not think evidence regarding male-advantage
mitigation via testosterone suppression supports IOC 2015 Transgender guidelines. The
36
scientific literature corroborates this position. Further, they did not accept fairness for females
should be subordinated to inclusion for transwomen, and consequently regarded IOC
guidelines as unfit for purpose. A minority supported the ‘tolerable unfairness’ of
testosterone suppression but were unaware this only minimally reduces male-advantage.
Within sport sociology, the dominant framing of quantitative methods and the social and
biological sciences as the pejorative scientism (Pringle and Falcous, 2018), is deeply
problematic for socio-cultural-political justice for female athletes. What might be considered
the disciplinary hubris and somatophobia of negating the material reality of human sexual
dimorphism, biologically sexed bodies and performance-related consequences for female
athletes notwithstanding the over-whelming scientific evidence, reinstates/maintains a
patriarchal mis-recognition of female persons as at most, smaller/lighter/inferior males. This
reinscribes normalised sex-blind hegemonic masculinity and androcentric citizenship. The
emancipatory origins of social constructionism, postmodernism and qualitative methods, may
have engendered a widespread over-reach of these privileged epistemologies necessitating a
rebalancing to include more empirical quantitative and cross-disciplinary research (Elling,
2015) with heterogenous female and transgender populations in the pursuit of socio-cultural-
political justice.
Both female and transgender athletes are socially disadvantaged, however fairness in sport
necessitates that females are not also physically disadvantaged. Justice entails the recognition
of females as equal moral agents, also and at the same time with distinctly female sexed
bodies, in order that the fastest highest and strongest females are celebrated at elite and
Olympic levels. Given these female Olympians viewed the IOC Transgender guidelines as
unjust, it is unsurprising they thought, in the words of two athletes, ‘Our Human rights to
equal opportunities (are) not being protected’ and asked ‘Why don’t women matter?’
37
Acknowledgments
I would like to thank nineteen female Olympic athletes for taking the time to generously
contribute to this research since without them this work would not have been possible.
Further, I would like to thank the editor and reviewers for their extremely helpful input.
References
Anderson W and Loland S (2015) Sport and the obligation of solidarity. Sport, Ethics and
Philosophy 9(3): 243-256.
Anderson E and Travers A (2017) Transgender Athletes in Competitive Sport. London:
Routledge.
BBC (2021a) Japan's LDP party invites women to 'look, not talk' at key meetings. 17
February.
BBC (2021b) Caitlyn Jenner opposes trans girls in women's sports as unfair. 2 May.
Bazelon E (2012) Cross-Court Winner. In: Foer F and Tracey M (eds) Jewish Jocks: An
Unorthodox Hall of Fame. New York: Twelve.
Bermon S, et al. (2019) Sex, gender, and sports. BMJ 364(l): 1120.
Bhargava A, Arnold AP, Bangasser DA et al. (2021) Considering sex as a biological variable
in basic and clinical studies: An endocrine society scientific statement. Endocrine Reviews
42(3): 219–258.
Blackburn L, Murray K and Mackenzie L (2021) Losing sight of women's rights (again): a
response to Cowan et al. Scottish Affairs 30(1): 74–95.
Brown N, et al. (2020) Pushing Boundaries: Women in Sport and Exercise Conference UK
2019. Women in Sport and Physical Activity Journal 28(1): 53-54.
38
Burt C (2020) Scrutinizing the U.S. Equality Act 2019: A Feminist Examination of
Definitional Changes and Sociolegal Ramifications. Feminist Criminology 15(4): 363-409.
Bryman A (2015) Social Research Methods. Oxford: OUP.
Butler J (2006) Gender Trouble. Oxford: Routledge.
Collin L, et al. (2016) Prevalence of Transgender Depends on the "Case" Definition: A
Systematic Review. The journal of sexual medicine 13(4): 613–626.
Crenshaw K (1989) Demarginalizing the Intersection of Race and Sex: A Black Feminist
Critique of Antidiscrimination Doctrine, Feminist Theory and Antiracist Politics. University
of Chicago Legal Forum: 1:8.
De Coubertin P (2000) The Women at the Olympic Games. In: De Coubertin P, Olympism:
selected writings. Lausanne: IOC: 711–713.
Del Giudice M (2019) Measuring sex differences and similarities. In VanderLaan DP and
Wong WI (eds) Gender and sexuality development: Contemporary theory and research. New
York: Springer.
Devine C (2013) London 2012 Olympic legacy: a big sporting society? International Journal
of Sport Policy and Politics 5(2): 257-279.
Devine C (2016) Sex, sport and justice: reframing the ‘who’ of citizenship and the ‘what’ of
justice in European and UK Sport Policy. Sport Education and Society 21(8): 1193-1212.
Devine JW (2019) Gender, Steroids, and Fairness in Sport. Sport, Ethics and Philosophy
13(2): 161-169.
Elling A (2015) Assessing the sociology of sport: On reintegrating quantitative methods and
gender research. International Review for the Sociology of Sport 50(4-5): 430-436.
39
Fraser N (2008). Scales of justice. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Fausto-Sterling (n.d.) Gender and Sexuality. Available at: Gender & Sexuality - Dr. Anne
Fausto-Sterling (accessed 5 May 2021).
García-Acero M, et al. (2020) Disorders of Sexual Development: Current Status and Progress
in the Diagnostic Approach. Current Urology 13(4): 169-178.
Gleaves J and Lehrbach T (2016) Beyond fairness: the ethics of inclusion for transgender and
intersex athletes. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 43(2): 311-326.
Gooren LJ and Bunck MC (2004) Transsexuals and competitive sports. European Journal of
Endocrinology 151(4): 425-429.
Handelsman D, Hirschberg A and Bermon S (2018) Circulating Testosterone as the
Hormonal Basis of Sex Differences in Athletic Performance. Endocrine Reviews 39(5): 803–
829.
Harper J, et al. (2021) How does hormone transition in transgender women change body
composition, muscle strength and haemoglobin? Systematic review with a focus on the
implications for sport participation. British Journal of Sports Medicine doi: 10.1136/bjsports-
2020-103106.
Heidari S, et al. (2016) Sex and Gender Equity in Research: rationale for the SAGER
guidelines and recommended use. Research Integrity Peer Review 1(2).
Hilton EN and Lundberg TR (2021) Transgender Women in the Female Category of Sport:
Perspectives on Testosterone Suppression and Performance Advantage. Sports
Medicine 51: 199–214.
Horne J (2015) Assessing the sociology of sport: On sports mega-events and capitalist
modernity. International Review for the Sociology of Sport 50(4-5): 466-471.
40
Hull C (2006) The Ontology of Sex. Oxford: Routledge.
IAAF (n.d.) Season Toplists. Available at: 100 Metres - women - senior - outdoor - 2019
(worldathletics.org) and 100 Metres - men - senior - outdoor - 2019 (worldathletics.org)
accessed 5 May 2010.
IAAF (2019a) IAAF publishes briefing notes and Q&A on Female Eligibility Regulations.
Available at: IAAF publishes briefing notes and Q&A on Female Eligibility Regulations |
PRESS-RELEASE | World Athletics accessed 5 May 2021.
IAAF (2019b) World athletics eligibility regulations for transgender athletes. Available at:
Microsoft Word - WA-EligibilityRegulations-TransgenderAthletes-1oct2019-Eng.docx
(athletics.org.tw) accessed 5 May 2021.
Ingle S (2019a) IOC delays new transgender guidelines after scientists fail to agree. The
Guardian, 24 September.
Ingle (2019b) British Olympians call for IOC to shelve ‘unfair’ transgender guidelines. The
Guardian, 12 June.
IOC (2003) Statement of the Stockholm consensus on sex reassignment in sports. Report,
Sweden, October.
IOC (2015) IOC Consensus Meeting on Sex Reassignment and Hyperandrogenism. Report,
Lausanne, November.
IOC (2018) IOC Gender Equality Review Project. Report, Lausanne.
IOC (2020a) Olympic Charter. Report, Lausanne, July.
IOC (2020b) Promotion of Gender Equality in Sport. Available at:
https://www.olympic.org/gender-equality accessed 12 November 2020.
41
ISNA (n.d.) What's the difference between being transgender or transsexual and having an
intersex condition? Available at: What's the difference between being transgender or
transsexual and having an intersex condition? | Intersex Society of North America (isna.org)
accessed 5 May 2021.
Jennings A (2011) Investigating corruption in corporate sport: The IOC and FIFA.
International Review for the Sociology of Sport. 46(4): 387-398.
Knox T, Anderson LC and Heather A (2019) Transwomen in elite sport: scientific and ethical
considerations. Journal of Medical Ethics 45: 395-403.
Lister R (2003) Citizenship: Feminist perspectives. New York: New York University Press.
Noy C (2008) Sampling Knowledge: The Hermeneutics of Snowball Sampling in Qualitative
Research. International Journal of Social Research Methodology 11(4): 327-344.
Lowrey K (2021) Trans Ideology and the New Ptolemaism in the Academy. Archives of
Sexual Behaviour 50: 757–760.
Pavitt M (2020) IOC confirms existing guidelines on transgender athlete eligibility to remain
for Tokyo 2020. Inside the Games, 3 March.
Pateman C (1988) The Sexual Contract. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Pitsiladis Y, et al. (2016) Beyond Fairness: The Biology of Inclusion for Transgender and
Intersex Athletes. Current Sports Medicine 15(6): 386-388.
Pringle R and Falcous M (2018) Transformative research and epistemological hierarchies:
Ruminating on how the sociology of the sport field could make more of a
difference. International Review for the Sociology of Sport 53(3): 261-277.
42
Ratna A (2018) Not just merely different: Travelling Theories, post-feminism and the
racialized politics of women of color. Sociology of Sport Journal 35(3).
Sax L (2002) How common is lntersex? A response to Anne Fausto ‐Sterling. The Journal of
Sex Research 39(3): 174-178.
Stone A (2007) An Introduction to Feminist Philosophy. Cambridge: Polity Press
Stonewall (n.d.) The truth about trans. Available at: The truth about trans (stonewall.org.uk)
accessed 5 May 2021.
Suissa J and Sullivan A (2021) The Gender Wars, Academic Freedom and Education.
Journal of Philosophy of Education 55: 55-82.
Teetzel S (2020) Allyship in Elite Women’s Sport. Sport Ethics and Philosophy DOI:
10.1080/17511321.2020.1775691.
Thibault, V, et al. (2010) Women and Men in Sport Performance: The Gender Gap has not
Evolved since 1983. Journal of Sports Science & Medicine 9(2): 214–223.
United Nations (1979) Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against
Women. United Nations Treaty Series 1249: 1.
WADA (2017) TUE Physician Guidelines: Transgender Athletes. Available at: Microsoft
Word - Document1 (wada-ama.org) accessed 5 May 2021.
Wiik A, et al. (2020). Muscle Strength, Size, and Composition Following 12 Months of
Gender-affirming Treatment in Transgender Individuals. Journal of Clinical Endocrinology
and Metabolism. 105(3): dgz247.
World Athletics (2019) International federations discuss consensus on establishing rules for
transgender athletes. Report, Lausanne, October.
43
World Rugby (2020a) World Rugby Transgender Guideline. Report, October.
World Rugby (2020b) 19. Transgender meeting 2020: Player results. Available at:
https://resources.world.rugby/worldrugby/document/2021/02/22/fec411ad-b1f2-4095-9779-
17d07787331b/17.-Transgender-Group-2020-Player-Survey-Results.pdf accessed 5 May
2021.