Content uploaded by Steve Moxon
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Steve Moxon on May 30, 2021
Content may be subject to copyright.
Content uploaded by Steve Moxon
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Steve Moxon on May 30, 2021
Content may be subject to copyright.
Male Heterogeneity and Female Choice in Human Mating:
Maximising Women’s Fertility in Offsetting Stress, Age and
Unwanted Attention, While Facilitating Extra-pair Conception
Moxon, SP (2021) New Male Studies 10(1) & 10(2).
[the (long) paper is shortly to be published in two parts across two successive issues]
Steve Moxon, Sheffield, UK. stevemoxon3@talktalk.net
Abstract
Women’s mate choice, given profoundly differential male genetic quality (specifically genomic
integrity), is heavily skewed towards topmost-ranked males, producing polygyny with residual monogamy
and bachelordom. Polygyny is ancestral, as in gorilla harems (apparently homologous with human female
cliques): originally predation-avoidance grouping, male-interposed to obviate female-female stress
depressing fertility to sub-replacement (Dunbar). Pair-bonding ensures successive highest-possible-quality
offspring while offsetting age-related fertility decline, and dissuading low-mate-value social-sexual
approach, thereby actually facilitating access by (or to) high-mate-value males for extra-pair conception.
It’s a female fertility platform and springboard for its enhancement. Failure properly to incorporate male
heterogeneity and female discernment explains a longstanding theoretical impasse, with infanticide
prevention a default mistaken hypothesis attempting to account for monogamy’s chimerical opportunity
costs.
Keywords: male heterogeneity, female choice, monogamy, polygyny, pair-bond, genomic integrity
The centrality of differential male mate value
That the human mating system cannot be understood without making central male heterogeneity
and female choice was the conclusion in a key review (Human Origins and the Transition from Promiscuity
to Pair-Bonding) by Gavrilets (2012), as reiterated by Rooker & Gavrilets (2016). This should have come
as no surprise, and was no new insight. It’s a commonplace if not universal perception that men (as for
males generally across species) are seen to vary considerably, indeed enormously as mate prospects.
Complementing this, women (as for females generally across species) are seen to be very particular in
their choosing. With variation, if more limited, also among women, then males and females pair up
according to their equivalent albeit very differently based mate values -- the perception by those of the
opposite sex of an individual’s overall worth as a sexual partner (the sum of traits likely to confer fitness in
terms of reproductive output). Men and women mate assortatively, that is, according to their similar level of
attractiveness. Profound differential male mate value, keen female discernment and consequent
assortative mating would be expected to be at the core of any and every hypothesis of the basis and
evolution of the human mating system (and of pair-bonding -- evolved neuro-hormonally cemented
enduring attachment -- or simply pair-living, across primates, mammals, and species in general). Yet this
has not been considered properly, if at all. One if not the only exception is the 2013 paper by the present
author, which here receives major update, development and different presentation.
With Gavrilets’ corrective unheeded, there is an absence of competing cogent hypotheses to test,
and trying to decide between existing ones unsurprisingly has not been fruitful. There continues to be a
widely acknowledged impasse in understanding of pair-living/-bonded (monogamous) species generically,
not just regarding humans specifically. Reviewers agree on the current impossibility of coming to robust
conclusions, though often cite low data quality and inappropriate comparisons (perhaps scapegoating
methodological for unrecognised root conceptual problems). Most recently, Fernandez-Duque, Huck, Van
Belle & Di Fiore (2020) in examining comparison studies of the evolution of monogamy have “serious
doubts” about all of them, given data so poor as to be “distressing”. Lambert, Sabol & Solomon (2018)
conclude there is no best model, and Kvarnemo (2018) finds overall monogamy is “still surprisingly poorly
understood”, with no single overriding explanation, instead being more taxon-specific (pertaining to a
particular group of individuals; for example, populations of the same species in different ecological niches,
sub-species, a genus or family of species, etc). Klug (2018) sees no way forward but pluralism plus
different explanations of origin as distinct from maintenance (an impasse familiar from the study of the
origin of sex and the sexes, indicating a likely similar failure to see the wood for the trees).
Without considering male heterogeneity, female choice and the resulting assortative mating, paired-
off men and women may be seen and studied simply as interchangeable binary units entirely independent
of each other and of others within the local population not paired up, despite all individuals being part-and-
parcel of what is a mating system: a whole-group phenomenon. The resulting misconstrued hypotheses
generate equivocal data, prompting their over-complex elaboration, and the risk that what seemingly key
factors emerge may be artefactual. However, the failure here is likely not merely an unfortunate constraint
of scientific inquiry through a need for parsimony and circumspection. A driver, at least in part, appears to
be the denial of the reality of hierarchy in a fundamental misrepresentation of the nature of male
heterogeneity. Instead of comprehending hierarchy as the foundational facet of human male sociality it is --
as it is for animal species generically -- there is the notion that hierarchy is an historical, social construct.
Inasmuch as this isn’t simply inappropriate ideological intrusion into science, it both stems from and
creates the false notion that forager / hunter-gatherer societies are egalitarian, in that males do not display
markedly differential possession of or access to resources. But this is because there is little or no facility to
do so in such societies, so rank hardly could be distinguished on that basis (and hierarchy usually would
not be expected to be overt if it is settled and thereby much less salient). Resource-holding is merely
indicative of rank in male hierarchy, which functions not to allocate resources but sexual access (Moxon,
2009). Accordingly, trying to use resource-competition scenarios to assess the ranking of individuals fails:
the rank order appears resource- and situation-specific (Lanctot & Best, 2000). Resource-holding cannot
constitute rank, otherwise males in species where there is no resource-holding to indicate rank could not
display the clear and stable ranking they do. For ranking to be meaningful -- stable and transitive (such
that alpha being dominant to beta, and beta dominant to gamma, then gamma is sub-dominant to alpha) --
it has to be resource-neutral, as it were. Either the summation of a male’s intrinsic qualities or some major
aspect of them (which would be embodied and revealed in ramification across the whole genome through
genic capture, the mutual influence of most if not all genes, such that each and every one has huge
ramification in expression across the whole genome). Belief in an ancestral non-hierarchical sociality
precludes accepting that any sort of inherent distinctions in quality have profound social salience; not least
that anything concerning hierarchy could be invoked in mating system aetiology.
Gavrilets’ 2012 paper remains the key recent one in the field in that not only is it a rare actual test of
several rival models of the evolution of the human mating system, but there is the addition, across all of
them, of the parameters of male heterogeneity and female choice. His results lead Gavrilets to conclude
that no hypothesis is feasible without them, as they “point to the crucial importance of female choice and
emphasize the need for incorporating between-individual variation”. Whether this means existing
hypotheses nevertheless identify factors that are necessary but not sufficient, or that male heterogeneity
plus female choice in themselves, in their ramification, may be the only main factors required, Gavrilets
does not venture. The task herein is to develop this as an hypothesis, along with any necessary
qualifications.
The problem with the whole body of research, reiterated in 2016 (Rooker & Gavrilets), is echoed
(looking across primates generally) by Huck, Di Fiore & Fernandez-Duque (2020), who urge incorporating
into models “competition and variance in reproductive success across a population” -- that is, taking into
consideration all individuals in the reproductive group, including non-reproducers. Kvarnemo (2018), in
discovering, contrary to what is commonly expected, substantial sexual selection under long-term mutual
monogamy, stresses that “mate quality is obviously more important than mate numbers, which in turn
affects the need for pre‐mating mate choice”. Unfortunately, rather than by modelling, hypotheses
continue to be examined usually only by phylogenetic analysis, an examination of the evolutionary history
of the diversification of species. Though usefully delineating the change in possibly relevant factors, often
this does not allow either their separation or to establish causal direction. It tends to miss discovering the
need for missing parameters, and hence why theorising has managed to continue without being obliged to
incorporate male heterogeneity and female choice.
Surprisingly, having outlined what at the very least is a necessary major corrective, Gavrilets himself
fails to apply it properly to his own comparative modelling, restricting interpretation of male heterogeneity
to fighting ability (determining the minority of males who could, supposedly, monopolise multiple females)
and of female choice to only the services males may provide, and not in terms of intrinsic quality of males.
Without such self-hobbling, Gavrilets’ conclusions likely would be doubly underscored. Albeit along the
right lines, the outline of a cogent aetiology is obstructed by largely ignoring foundational biological
principle.
Mating deals with the core problem of maintaining genomic
integrity
The foundational biological principle that is the missing underpinning of hypothesis is this: the core
problem faced by all biological entities of the relentless accumulation of gene replication error,
necessitating repeated purging, the elimination of defective genes by natural and/or sexual selection,
either through reducing the reproductive output of individual carriers, or consigning them to reproductive or
actual oblivion. Given that the female as the gestating sex is always the limiting factor of reproduction, in
effect purging has to be quarantined on the male half of the lineage, leaving the female to reproduce
unhindered. Hence the male functions as the genetic filter, to use Atmar’s (1991) label for the process, or
mutational cleanser, to use West-Eberhard’s (2005). As Martinossi-Allibert, Rueffler, Arnqvist & Berger
(2019) put it: “sexual selection in males has the potential to purge deleterious alleles from the population
while leaving females, who experience weaker selection, spared of the demographic cost of adaptation”.
Consequently, selection acts far more on the male than on the female, as is now extremely well evidenced
and modelled (for citations and a mini review see Moxon, 2019, pp. 42-43).
Several mechanisms have evolved to express pointedly the male genome and to expose it to
natural and especially sexual selection, resulting in males to some degree failing to reproduce if to
reproduce at all, in proportion to the extent to which they carry deleterious genetic material (for an outline,
see Moxon, 2012; 2016, pp. 16-25). It is not just that the male is obliged to take on this function, but that
this functional distinction between the sexes appears to be their origin (Moxon, 2019), with sex itself having
evolved to deal with mutational load (not to produce variation, as has long been mistakenly thought), as
also concluded most recently by MacPherson, Scot & Gras (2021) and Zadorin & Rivoire (2021).
Male heterogeneity here is genetic quality in the special sense of genomic integrity, the
maintenance of good inter-functionality of the whole of an individual’s complement of genetic material (both
coding and non-coding, regulatory genes), rather than the default notion in biology of the quality
distinguishing males being good genes, the possession of the genes or genetic variants most obviously
conferring incremental competitive advantage; for example, height. A good genes understanding is
notwithstanding equivocal meta-analytic findings (Prokopet al., 2012) suggesting males instead may be
attractive to females in ways unrelated to fitness (the sexy sons notion of benefit to females in greater
reproductive output of their own in turn attractive male offspring), plus methodological issues and
questions about interpretation (Achorn & Rosenthal, 2020). The evidence and modelling fall short in
looking for fitness gains when instead it’s an absence of fitness decline that should be sought, in keeping
with simply managing to stand still in what is a red queen scenario -- thus dubbed from the Alice in
Wonderland character obliged to keep moving simply to stand still. Rather than good genes per se,
“female mating biases align with the avoidance of bad genes” (Dugand, Kennington & Tomkins, 2018).
See also Velando, Torres & Alonso-Alvarez (2008).
The principal mechanism here is the assortment of males to rank according to their relative lack of
deleterious genetic material. The resulting dominance (and/or prestige) hierarchy, as already pointed out,
is shown to function to allocate sexual access (not resources per se) (Moxon, 2009). The principal mode of
allocation is the intrinsic part females play in correspondingly keying into the male hierarchy as the mate-
choosers. Given how crucial a function is purging deleterious genetic material, together with the low overall
reproductive output of the female making it important that each conception counts, then it would be
expected that all females vie for the male with the very topmost genomic integrity -- that is, the most-
highly-purged male genome. Thus, male heterogeneity, given the imperative of purging, is greatly
amplified in being very heavily skewed in its translation into male mate value.
Note that if it were quality per se, then it would be additive, and all that would be needed of a male
would be for him to be good enough. All individuals above a certain threshold thereby might be considered
interchangeable. But distinctions between purged male genomes are not in absolute but relative terms. It’s
because constantly emerging genetic defects are potentially lethal, even as a single mutation, and likely to
be synergistic across the whole genome, leading to depressed performance across-the-board, that the
fight against them is a red queen phenomenon. Having to run just to avoid slipping backwards, as it were:
chasing and closing, though never quite catching. Winning an endless series of battles in a war that never
can be won requires constant greatest effort, utilising whichever is the currently top performing individual
as the template for all. The chosen male can never be too good. He needs to be as good as it’s possible to
be, with no female settling for less than the highest-possible genetic quality (genomic integrity) male
obtainable in the circumstances. Hence an evolved enormous skew in the perception of male mate value
towards the apex of an ordinal series. Male hierarchy potentially is a winner takes all scenario in terms of
reproduction, assuming it were practically possible for the alpha to sire all offspring in the local group. This
reproductive skew would be reinforced by the differential reproductive suppression of males that appears
to be inextricable with ranking (Moxon, 2009), increasing in degree with descent down the male hierarchy,
compounding falling male mate value in terms of genomic integrity. The impact of lower status on male
stress physiology, in turn depressing male reproductive physiology and motivation (and the converse re
higher status), has been well studied, and can be either direct behavioural reproductive suppression by
high-rankers or its anticipation by low-rankers in order that it’s obviated in evolved self-suppression
mechanism.
With the female functioning as the conduit to the next generation of the filtered /mutationally
cleansed male genome, then males as well as females have a basis of mate choice through opposite-sex
heterogeneity. Female differential ability to act as the conduit is summed up in fertility. However, this is a
quite particular and at the same time common quality, unlike the general but pre-eminent one looked for in
the male, and concerns a narrow set of restricted parameters manifest in correspondingly narrow and
restricted indicators, so here quality is according to a threshold model. There is no imperative to be as
good as it’s possible to be; just good enough. There is, then, far less scope for variation in mate value
among females than among males. In any case, the great bulk of the variation among human females is
simply age (see below): females not very long after their fertility-peak more or less cease to be under
consideration as part of the mating pool. Most tellingly, females are subject to far less stringent mate-
choosing than are males, given the minimal cost and great reproductive benefit to males of mating
(compared to the huge costs to females): males, given the opportunity, focus on gaining sexual partners in
number more than -- or at the same time as -- just one of notable high fertility. It is easy to see, then, why
the female is considered the choosing sex.
The different basis of mate choice according to sex is illustrated by findings regarding MHC (the
Major Histocompatibility Complex), the key factor in immune response. Hanne, Simmons & Rhodes (2009)
find that a woman seeks a man with a strong MHC indicating immuno-competence, whereas a man seeks
a woman who possesses MHC that merely contrasts with his own. The genetic complement under
selection here clearly is that of the male, with the female’s mate choice being in terms of a particularly well-
functioning important aspect of the male requiring, as far as is possible, a perfectly non-compromised
genetic basis. By contrast, the male’s mate choice is in terms just of adding some hybrid vigour to assist in
transmitting his filtered genome through to the next generation.
The need for pair-bonding and same-partnered successive
conception
With the prodigious sexual capacity of the male, promiscuity at first glance would seem potentially to
suffice as a mating system. The most-highly-purged male could be selected by all the females in the local
reproductive group or wider mating pool. However, this would entail low regularity of sex (if not also
compatibility issues, both physical and/or physiological), on average substantially delaying time taken to
conceive if to conceive at all, including even with the most fertile females. Output/efficiency presumably
would be greatly improved by the most-highly-purged male focusing on a number of very-high-fertility
females over time, as in pair-living/-bonding, thereby ensuring iterated sex on a regular basis, and,
therefore, conception and in minimal time. This presumably is the proximal function of pair-bonding. The
number of these females would need to be restricted -- likewise the extent of sex outside pair-bonding -- so
as not to reintroduce the problem of the male’s mating effort being spread too thinly.
The principal benefit of pair-bonding, however, would be if it is long-term. Conception then would be
repeated, leading to another benefit stemming from male heterogeneity. Offspring not only would continue
to be assuredly produced and at minimal intervals, but all would be the most highly purged possible, as all
would be sired by the same, most-highly-purged male. The alternative of only short-term pair-bonding,
merely sufficient to ensure conception (or, as has been suggested, long enough to support the female
during lactation), would be no different to promiscuity. It would risk the quality of offspring progressively
decreasing with iterated assortative mating.
The quality (genomic integrity) of males subsequently secured in serial short-term pair-bonding
would correspond to the age-related declining fertility of the female herself. Not only is there deterioration
of stored ova (leading to quickly rising rates of implantation failure), but also progressive shortening of the
potential reproductive lifespan (Conroy-Beam & Buss, 2019). A sharp early diminution in a female’s sexual
attractiveness occurs with a first pregnancy, and then the impact of childbirth, as indicated by low waist-to-
hip ratio and BMI (Lassek & Gaulin, 2018), or, more accurately, shallow waist depth and small
circumference (Rilling et al., 2009). It is not fertility that is indicated but being nulligravid (that is, not
currently and never having been pregnant). The female signals not only her current immediate availability
for reproduction, but that she has her full reproductive life ahead of her (that is, none of its being already in
the past); assuredly starting at her fertile peak. This enables a female to secure for a pair-bond partner a
male with the greatest genomic integrity consonant with her other fertility indicators. Pair-bonding in effect
projects forward in time female peak fertility, if at or circa the female age of peak fertility (and, therefore,
attractiveness to males) the female looks for the male with the greatest genomic integrity she can find who
is willing to pair-bond with her. There will never be a more auspicious time to do this, and the pair-bond
effectively time-capsules her mate choice, which she could not do in reproducing promiscuously, as the
genomic integrity of each successive father for her children is likely progressively to diminish in line with
her own rapidly declining mate value. In other words, with pair-bonding the female in effect can cheat time.
Pair-bonding in the human case does appear to be of sufficient duration to effect repeat conception,
albeit its estimation is extremely difficult, as discussed in Moxon (2013), with extremely inconsistent and
very poorly comparable measures. Not least, data on marriage and even cohabitation is missing any
period of initial informal pair-bonding, including the portion of this within those pair-bonds that later become
marriages or cohabitations. The human pair-bond typically is about five years, according to Sefcek,
Brumbach, Vasquez & Miller (2006), which is greater than inter-birth intervals in hunter-gatherer societies
(those presumed closest to ancestral populations) of three to four years (Kaplan, Lancaster & Hurtado,
2000) or 3.65 years (Robson, van Schaik & Hawkes, 2006). Note that pair-bond duration would not have to
be decisively longer than the inter-birth interval but merely comparable for pair-bonding to be adaptive in
respect of repeat conception, as generally in the evolutionary creation of an adaptation even merely
statistical biasing of behaviour usually suffices. Furthermore, pair-bonding would fulfil the putative function
by merely providing a platform for other, usual modes of affiliation and attachment to augment and perhaps
then supersede it. Such affiliation and attachment could have served to reduce in the first place the
requirement for a lengthy period of pair-bonding per se.
Most often cited or used as a basis for estimation is Fisher’s four years (Fisher, 1989, 1994), which
by other measure is a substantial under-estimate, being the modal average of the time from marriage to
divorce. First, it’s only a subset of all marriages, and a severely systematically biased one at that, as all
those that did not end in divorce are excluded. Second, ignored is all of the period of pair-bonding prior to
its formalisation even as cohabitation. Third, all of the very high proportion of marriages that are very
lengthy are missed out in not using the median or mean as the measure. Note, though, the inter-birth
interval data is also lacking, as it does not include the period from the inception of pair-bonding to
conception. Taking the median rather than the mode, even for divorcing couples the duration of the
average marriage almost doubles to seven years, and far longer than that for the whole set. Fisher’s
rationale for taking the modal peak is that in being what is typical rather than merely average we may
detect the underlying natural extent of pair-bonding. Yet divorce itself in not being typical of marriage may
represent less an absence of other affiliative and attachment processes piggy-backing the pair-bond than
extrinsic factors precipitating pair-bond termination. If the latter pertain only to a contemporary and not an
ancestral context, they would not be part of the milieu in which pair-bonding became adaptive.
Consequently, pair-bonding that was highly adaptive ancestrally may be weaker in contemporary
scenarios, reducing average duration to below what it may have been when originally evolved, providing
other than a full picture today, clouding its function.
A key aspect and revealing feature of pair-bond duration is that it’s U-shaped: typically, either long
(if not very long) or very short. Fisher’s data misses both these poles, neither of which can be considered
atypical. Of those pair-bonds that dissolve, there is a very heavy skew toward this being very early in the
relationship, as routinely commented on in the relationships-advice literature and journalism. Data for both
developed-world and hunter-gatherer societies bear this out. Furthermore, specifically marriage data
greatly understates relationship breakdown overall. In the USA, of unmarried couples, 70% break up within
their first year (Rosenfeld, Thomas & Falcon, 2018). In the case of marriages, given the hurdle of the
formalisation of the relationship causing lead times for dissolution, it’s necessary to measure failure within
the first year other than just by the divorce rate. Then it is found that over a fifth -- amounting to half or
more of all those marriages that end in failure -- if not already dissolved were well on the way to that
outcome (Leonard & Roberts, 1998): 1% to 2% of couples had already completed divorce, 5% had
permanently separated, and a further 14% had separated for a period at some point (heralding their
demise). Additionally, much of the divorce rate in the second year should be attributed to the first, given
that’s when proceedings began or when the instability in the relationship had already made one or both
parties minded to initiate them. Regarding hunter-gatherers, Blurton-Jones, Marlowe, Hawkes & O’Connel
(2000), in studying across four quite different populations, note the great number of marriages breaking up
before children are born is owing to their failure in fecundability, the probability of a female conceiving in a
given period of time. Partners wait only so long to test the concrete fertility of the pairing before baling out.
Similar is found with pastoralists. Du & Mace (2019) conclude: “The production of offspring, regardless of
their survivorship, also had a positive effect on marriage duration, as did trial marriage, a time period
before formal marriage”. So, it’s not producing children per se but confirmation of the potential to do so that
is at issue. Trial marriage is commonplace. Pair-bonding generally appears indeed to be on trial until
reproductive output is assured by conception, so it may be that in an important sense this is when bonding
properly begins or fully completes. So, Fisher could well be right to exclude both extremes of duration: long
because it’s not pair-bonding per se sustaining the relationship; short because in important senses it’s pre-
bonding. Matching or exceeding the inter-birth interval might, then, be a good measure of pair-bond
duration to evidence the putative function of ensuring at least one successive conception. The data clearly
supports this.
Polygyny-monogamy-bachelordom
The logic of the most rudimentary polygamy -- polygyny, that is (one male multiply paired with
females) -- with the male of the greatest genomic integrity being the only male females choose for pair-
bonding, affords much less opportunity for most females to mate with him than would be the case
promiscuously, driving fierce female competition. Females would do better to vie for a parallel pair-bond
with not just one but a number (albeit a very limited number) of top-ranking males (the very topmost plus a
tiny few of the next highest-ranking males). Hence a number of polygynous males. A trade-off of a degree
of diminished (compared to the alpha) male genomic integrity against reliability of long-term regular sex in
pair-bonding, then can lead to assortative mating to encompass a larger portion of the male hierarchy.
Males ranking high-to-middling additionally could also pair off polygynously, though each may attract fewer
females with decreasing rank. Given the very strong skew in mate value, this would quickly fall from a
multiple to just one. Polygyny becomes monogyny (just one female per male; in other words, monogamy),
leaving a surfeit of mateless males -- zerogamy, as now popularly labelled. However fine-scaled is this
assortment, as it proceeds the relative genomic integrity of males would decrease at least roughly in step
with the corresponding lesser ability of the female partner to transmit the male’s genes into the next
generation. In this way, whatever the degree of male genomic integrity, it is not compromised by any less
inter-generational transmissibility than it warrants, and vice-versa, overall producing high (if not the highest
possible) reproductive output (quantity x quality) and efficiency of the local reproductive group or mating
pool.
Note that the females are never selecting some interchangeable also-ran male. Those females
mating with males who don’t have the mate value to warrant multiple pairings, and therefore mate
monogamously, still will have chosen a male with a degree of genomic integrity greater than that
possessed by still lower-ranked males (and certainly more than that of the lowest-rankers). The supply of
females will have run out before not just many but (ancestrally, at least, as evidenced below) most males
get any opportunity to assort with them, owing to so many females having paired off multiply with just the
one male -- or even eschewing monogamy with well-below-average-ranked males, preferring instead
intermittent consortship or promiscuity with males of higher rank. This is why it is so mistaken to view a
basis of assortment as merely varied, idiosyncratic or arbitrary, as is implied by and the hidden assumption
of usual hypotheses. The real possibility of complete matelessness would drive males to settle for
partnering merely monogamously. Indeed, partner scarcity is proposed as the basis of monogamy
(Schacht & Bell, 2016).
It is held that monogamy is difficult to explain because the male sustains something of the order of a
fivefold opportunity cost of not having multiple pair-bond partners as in polygyny (for example, Dunbar,
2018), but although this can be argued in the case of obligate monogamy, it is not applicable to monogamy
as a residue of polygyny. Polygyny is not a potential alternative for males who struggle to gain even a
single partner. Far from monogamy entailing opportunity cost, it is a clear benefit to non-polygynous males
because otherwise not only will they be zerogamous but they won’t be able to acquire a sexual partner
outside of a pair-bond either. They will not be able to reproduce at all, because a male finding himself in
the lower realms of assortative mating -- in monogamy clearing, as it were -- will have even less (much
less) chance of mating promiscuously. Unlike men, women require substantially more attractive partners
for extra-pair (no-strings) sex than for pair-bonding (Szepsenwol, Mikulincer & Birnbaum, 2013), just as do
females in other species (eg, Cochaset al., 2006; Kempenaerset al.,1992). Again, male heterogeneity
enters as crucial to reveal what is going on.
A very different picture emerges here to that envisaged in modelling by Gavrilets, who recognises
only the very top-ranking males as pairing up through any intrinsic quality -- and only their fighting ability,
which may recruit only a subset of the full range of genetic quality demonstrating genomic integrity -- and
this by imposition, not female choice. All other males are considered to possess little if any, or effectively
zero mate value, and therefore in effect are interchangeable. Not until some of them realise they can adopt
an alternative mate acquisition mode of offering to provide services beyond mating itself, such as
provisioning. Only then and not before, in Gavrilets’ modelling, does female choice emerge as a factor in
mating systems. Clearly, this is a highly restricted model not reflecting biological reality.
The polygyny-monogyny-zerogyny mix arising from the simple logic of male-female assortment
according to differential intrinsic mate value is an accurate characterisation of the human mating system,
which is not monogamy. Monogamous species are obligately so. Polygyny and monogamy (and
bachelordom) are inextricably linked, with polygyny central and monogamy (and bachelordom) in its
shadow, notwithstanding that not only is there monogamy in all societies, but polygyny never accounts for
more than a minority of pair-bonds. The very severe skew in male mate value produced by the imperative
of purging means it can only be a small minority of males who are polygynous. So it is that in half of the
societies thus categorized, less than five percent of men take on more than one wife (Labuda, Lefebvre,
Nadeau & Roy-Gagnon, 2010). A large preponderance of societies (85%) in the anthropological record
allowed polygyny (White et al., 1988). As well as polygyny being formally sanctioned in most societies, it
occurs overtly in all societies in the guise of serial monogamy (Schacht & Kramer, 2019), as well as
covertly in the de facto polygyny of mistress-keeping. Suda (2007) in a paper on contemporary and
traditional African practice, titled Formal monogamy and informal polygyny in parallel, outlines that
“although much of the ethnographic literature indicates that heterosexual monogamy remains the statistical
marriage norm, polygyny was nevertheless empirically widespread in traditional Africa and is increasingly
being reinvented, often clandestinely …” (p. 56). That polygyny is the human norm is the conclusion, in a
book-length review of the topic, by Baresh (2016), who sees “the underlying prevalence of polygamy as
the default setting for human intimacy” (p. 2).
A particular form of polygyny in the anthropological literature is concubinage (here with a more
restrictive meaning than non-marital co-habitation), also known as polycoity, which might be considered a
hybrid of monogamy and polygyny in that there is a primary pair-bond plus one or more secondary,
substantially lesser ones. Actually, this is the usual nature of polygyny. Chika & Nneka (2014), for example,
point out: “The husband in most cases showers much love on the most favoured wife” (p. 23). Almost
always there is a preferred wife over all others, whether an always-favoured or the newest (youngest), with
the latter case being usual (eg,Gwirayi, 2016), which in effect is serial monogamy. Essien puts it
emphatically: “The hierarchy of wives is indisputable and the inferiority of the secondary wives is beyond
any argument”. This distinction underlines that polygyny is not some collective bonding with one male but
parallel monogamy. Distinguishing between polygyny and monogamy gets harder the more they are
investigated.
The female as the chooser
The full extent of the heavy reproductive skew towards males with the most genomic integrity would
be revealed by adding to the within-pair reproductive output of polygynous males that which is through
extra-pair conception. This is the reproductive output from clandestine polygyny plus any sex outside of
any pair-bonding (casual sex, as it were). The latter would be very largely if not exclusively with
polygynous males, in that (as afore-mentioned) human females require partners of substantially higher
mate value for extra-pair sex than for pair-bonding (Szepsenwol, Mikulincer & Birnbaum, 2013).
Extra-pair paternity is now shown to be extraordinarily high in populations most closely resembling
ancestral ones: foragers or pastoralists. Among African pastoralists, Scelza et al. (2020) find extra-pair
paternity to be 48%. A natural base rate of extra-pair paternity (non-paternity) had thus far been hidden.
Macintyre & Sooman (1991) discuss the impossibility of verifying the usually cited 10% -- medical students
are told it’s 10-15%, which is in line with the worldwide median of 10% arrived at by Baker & Bellis (1995) -
- because known or suspected cases would self-select out of sampling to avoid discovery by the presumed
father, leaving all measures inherently gross under-estimates. Nevertheless, a series of unpublished
studies of English samples put the rate at 30% (20-30% according to a likewise unpublished Liverpool
survey). Research hitherto anyway has been restricted to European or European-descent populations, and
therefore to (long-)developed societies, that profoundly contrast with the traditional agrarian, let alone
those that might more resemble ancestral populations. It might be expected that the former feature factors
depressing non-paternity and/or its discovery that were not present until recently.
The new data from pastoralists on extra-pair paternity indicates monogamy may function in part or
mainly as back-up to supply an already high level of male genomic integrity, for if there has not occurred
extra-pair conception with a male of genomic integrity substantially greater still. The latter is not unlikely to
occur given the heightened sexual motivation of females at ovulation, which, in temporarily reducing,
relatively, the salience of anything but sex, reduces concern for pair-bond maintenance, allowing the risk-
taking required in extra-pair sex. It has been thought that during their brief fertile phase around ovulation
women switch from being attracted to their pair-bond partner to extra-pair males (for example, Larson,
Pillsworth, & Haselton, 2012). However, regular failure to replicate has been reported, most recently by
Thomas, Armstrong, Stewart-Williams & Jones (2021), Stern, Kordsmeyer & Penke (2021), and van Stein,
Strauß & Brenk-Franz (2019) -- who nevertheless confirm heightened sexual motivation -- or that only a
modest or slight effect is evident (Marcinkowska et al., 2020). A new review (Jones, Hahn & DeBruine,
2019) finds largely null results even in old studies. All indicate a faulty interpretation has been at play.
Rather than a preference for extra-pair males over the pair-bond partner, it’s surely conditional on
differential mate value. In the absence of an extra-pair male of substantially greater genomic integrity than
the pair-bond partner, the female simply will have heightened sexual interest in her pair-bond partner. A
general attraction to potential extra-pair males would not make sense. What has been dubbed the dual
mating strategy or (good genes) ovulatory shift hypothesis is an artefact again of failing to incorporate male
heterogeneity, instead to assume that the female, rather than looking for genetic quality (genomic integrity)
in any and every male sexual partner, seeks different or additional qualities in a long-term partner:
investment of some kind, usually assumed to be provisioning of offspring. But this requires evidence,
which is absent, indeed countered (see below). Women instead seek genomic integrity in all male partners,
but substantially more so in specifically extra-pair partners because of the risk of pair-bond dissolution, and
thereby the loss of a genome with high genomic integrity by which to conceive a subsequent series of
offspring -- which she won’t be able to replace with anything like an equivalent male given her own steeply
falling mate value. The extra-pair partner is available only for one conception, unless he too becomes a
pair-bond partner of the female.
Furthermore, women have an aversion to sex during the infertile (luteal) phase, presumably
because sex poses a substantial risk of implantation failure should an ovum be fertilised (Steiner, Pritchard,
Young & Herring, 2014). Hence, it would seem, an evolved implantation-failure avoidance mechanism in
pre-menstrual syndrome (Moxon, 2020). Added together, these phenomena are likely severely to depress
the frequency of sex, which is the age-old principal complaint men have about marriage. Albeit minimal sex
usually suffices to maintain a pair-bond (given the very well-known phenomenon in psychology experiment
of reinforcement regimes that although infrequent nonetheless are effective, especially if they are
unpredictable), this female overall strategy risks partner defection. Should a woman detect lesser
investment in the pair-bond by her partner than by herself -- in other words, a strong possibility of her pair-
bond male defecting -- she increases the regularity of sex with him, though only in the luteal (non-fertile)
phase of her cycle (Grebe, Gangestad, Garver-Apgar & Thornhill, 2013), thereby continuing to facilitate
(albeit not to preference) extra-pair sex during the fertile phase. It’s a measure of the imperative to further
boost fertility overall that even when the pair-bond is under threat the heightened sexual motivation at
ovulation is not directed specifically towards the pair-bond partner.
All entails a large degree of female partner-choice, whether proceptive (taking the sexual initiative)
or through selective acquiescence. Given the various difficulties attending engaging in extra-pair sex and
potential costly implications, it is inconceivable that it could occur on this scale without females being not
only fully complicit but actively the choosing sex. With so much at stake in extra-pair sex, women surely
are the arbiters, whether or not they are the main initiators.
The centrality of female choice to add to that of male heterogeneity is shown in polygyny not being
some male imposition as often supposed: “Many women in Africa choose polygynous over monogamous
marriages even in the absence of pressure from relatives” (Anderson, 2000). There are even benefits in
terms of childcare. Anderson finds other adult females acting as alloparents, taking on parental duties
despite not being parents of the offspring themselves. Female kin and co-wives provide the resources that
contribute to the reproductive success of women married polygynously. There are benefits from polygyny
not just for first but also for subsequent wives (Uggla, Gurmu & Gibson, 2018), contradicting assumptions
that women in polygynous marriages are just making the best of a bad job. There is not only no evidence
that polygynous marriage is a harmful cultural practice, claim Lawson et al. (2015), but any costs of
sharing a husband are offset by greater wealth of polygynous households, consistent (the author himself
notes) with models of polygyny based on female choice. So even on an inappropriate economic analysis
ignoring the centrality of intrinsic male heterogeneity, polygyny is not disadvantageous but beneficial to
women.
That women are the choosers, not men, is very clear whether in polygyny or monogamy.
Corresponding to male advertisement of quality so as to prompt female choice, the female choosing the
particular male is basic in evolutionary theory and long ago confirmed in the case of humans. Cross-
cultural verbal interaction research by Stephens (1963) showed that notwithstanding men being the sexual
initiators, women are the choosers; or, as Moore (1985) put it, the controllers of mate choice (including
initiation). This extends to arranged marriage (the dominant form of match-making across Africa, the
Middle East and Asia, and all but ubiquitous across the world prior to industrialisation), which was and is
invariably orchestrated by women: either family members (aunt, elder sister, sister-in-law, or possibly an
older matriarch) and/or an outsider female matchmaker. It’s the cross-cultural norm today and throughout
history (for a brief review, see Moxon, 2017, p146).
Our mating system’s gorilla-like ancestry
Polygyny is known to have been central to human mating ancestrally. DNA analysis reveals only 40% of
men were ever fathers (Wilder, Mobasher & Hammer, 2004), fitting with data of worldwide Y-chromosome
diversity indicating only a few men may have contributed a large fraction of the Y-chromosome pool at
every generation until only recently (Dupanloup et al, 2003). Some evidence points to this change being in
the era of early modern humans, circa 150,000 years ago (Walker, Flinn & Ellsworth, 2011). Note this
would occur simply from a large increase in local populations, given no reason to suppose the sharp
reproductive skew towards an apex of only a very few males would change. The tendency to winner takes
all suggests that the residue of monogamy and bachelordom has grown without a commensurate
proliferation of polygyny.
Also indicating that polygyny is human-ancestral are the oft-cited long-known results from standard
comparison of sex dimorphism in body size and other parameters across the family tree of hominid
species. From these it has been proposed that the human mating system was never chimpanzee- but
gorilla-like: long-term pair-bonds of one male with multiple females (Nakahashi & Horiuchi, 2012; Geary &
Bailey, 2011). An evolutionary transition from this to the human mating system is discounted by Chapais
(2008) in his assertion that separate harems would be unlikely to fuse to form the human sociality of
multiple males and multiple females all together, and that instead this is more directly our ancestral state --
like the hamadryas baboon today. But this is to ignore a lot of research, notably in the 1990s, reporting
large gorilla groupings of multiple one-male-+-multi-female sub-groups (see the book covering three
decades of this research, by Robbins, Sicotte & Stewart, 2001). Gorillas evidently exhibit group fission-
fusion of modules of a single male and his harem. This is analogous, likely homologous with human family
grouping, and confirmed in gorilla-human comparative work (Morrison, 2019) demonstrating “common
underlying multi-level social structure and the considerable similarities in inter-group territorial dynamics”;
findings that “strongly emphasise the importance of gorillas as a model system for human social evolution”.
Chapais therefore seems right that a multi-male-+-multi-female sociality is ancestral: it’s simply that he
didn’t realise that this is what we have in the gorilla.
Reinforcing this is another window on the extinct ape common ancestor provided by the orangutan, in that
this species is now shown to be gorilla-like and more human-like than is the chimpanzee. The orangutan in
comparison to all other apes has evolved only very slowly (Locke et al, 2011), whereas human evolution
comparatively in major respects has been effectively reversed by neoteny (Franchini & Pollard, 2017).
Thus is explained the uncanny morphological and other human-orangutan similarity, whereas there is
notable human-chimpanzee dissimilarity (Grehan & Schwartz, 2009). The molecular evidence has been
held not to support this, but is not relevant in being in respect only of coding genes, when “most genomic
changes that distinguish humans from their primate relatives are in non-coding sequences with regulatory
functions” (Ligrone, 2019), especially in the so-called Human Accelerated Region (HAR), and not least
those regulating neoteny. Tang et al (2020) demonstrate that some human features indeed may be
explained by neoteny, notably in the brain, with infant human brain growth being a mere third the rate of
that of chimpanzees. It’s likely, then, that the orangutan’s mating system much more closely resembles
those of species in the human phylogeny than does the chimpanzee’s, which appears to be a profound
divergence. The upshot is that there is no utility and instead only hindrance and false trails in looking to the
chimpanzee for our ancestral mating system. The orangutan, despite its semi-solitary living, is, like the
gorilla, polygynous. It’s dubbed short-term polygynous, though this is rather inaccurate given that the
sexually exclusive consortships of up to seven months reported by Utami et al (2002) are a continuation of
long-term affiliations formed in adolescence, which also revive between child-rearing (Grehan, 2006).
Apparently, there is long-term pair-living/bonding in the orangutan, or there would be but for periodic
separation owing to necessary dispersal to ensure sufficient food resources. Any dissimilarity to the gorilla
pattern is through the orangutan’s relatively recent evolution to largely solitary living; the result of a major
environmental change producing food scarcity, according to Harrison & Chivers (2007): “the orang-utan's
present-day mating system most likely evolved from a gorilla-like base, with one dominant male guarding a
harem of females”.
The homologous human female clique
A gorilla-human seeming homology pertaining to mating system is the gorilla harem and the human female
clique. The latter typically numbers four to six, or an average size of 5.11 members (Kwon & Lease, 2007);
the former, a maximum of five individuals -- the limit, across primate species, of the number of females per
polygynous male (Pawlowski, Lowen & Dunbar, 1998). The workings and nature of the clique as the key
form of girl, adolescent, and indeed adult human female sociality has been entirely neglected in the
scientific literature in favour of consideration only of supposed unisexual sociality, despite it being
abundantly clear that male sociality is entirely different, with male (but not female) sociality essentially
group-based as opposed to dyadic (David-Barrett et al, 2015), and the female (but not the male) social
dynamic being exclusion (Benenson et al, 2013). Presumably, this neglect is through fear of usual censure
and career derailment of being considered in some way to negatively portray women. Insights instead
come from parenting literature -- most notably by Wiseman (2016), but also several other authors -- finding
its way into scholarship as teacher resources (Harley & MacNeil, 2017) and via Psychology Today (Powell-
Lunder, 2013).
As Powell-Lunder stresses, girls in general belong to a queen bee-led small coterie; that is, a clique. Not
just those who are the most popular (who are merely the most conspicuous and suitable as protagonists in
famous films such as Mean Girls). Furthermore, Powell-Lunder elaborates, the cliques to which most girls
belong are still fiercer environments than those of the populars, because of the fear that exclusion from this
less exclusive social milieu may leave nowhere else to go. Clique members adopt the various well-
documented (Wiseman, 2016) unranked roles, in an ethos of fierce avoidance of one-upmanship, with just
one of them at any one time a potential replacement in being the deputy of the queen bee, who appears,
therefore, not an alpha at the apex of a hierarchy but first among equals. The hallmark of clique sociality is
of course the extremely well-known intense policing of membership, under the fierce control of the queen
bee (unless and until she is deposed by her deputy). Also, the firm exclusion of all others, the difficulty in
gaining membership, and the constant prospect of losing it. The imperative appears to be an all-
encompassing desire to achieve and maintain clique membership by serving the queen bee and taking
great care not to be seen to challenge her (on pain of expulsion), yet inhabiting or creating a springboard
position from which to be the usurper should there be an opportunity (with sufficiently good prospects of
success).
From a comparative, evolutionary perspective, the human female clique looks like a proto- (though
possibly only facultative, or even vestigial) co-operative breeding unit, with a (potential) sole breeding
female controlling a group of fellow females she reproductively suppresses so they can be utilised (through
channelling their reproductive motivation) as alloparents. It may be that in the deputy there is a reserve
breeding female or a subsidiary as a result of only partial reproductive suppression. Perhaps the rest of the
females, though reproductively suppressed more than is the deputy, nevertheless are not fully so, and may
then breed to a limited degree or in some circumstances. If not obligate, this could be facultative co-
operative breeding triggered by local severe ecological stress, as an adaptation to head off the possibility
of local extinction, by restricting reproduction, possibly to the extent of a 100% skew to the one most fertile
female in the sub-group. In her being paired with one of the males with the least deleterious genetic
complement, and the use of locally very limited resources (including the parenting efforts of other
reproductive-age females) being reserved exclusively for their use, then there would be a good chance
that the one most reproductively fit couple of each sub-group could manage to produce a next generation.
Such a best shot likely would outdo the alternative of too many pairs attempting to breed, as this would
place them in mutual competition over temporarily impossibly limited resources. It may be that in extremis
only one pre-eminent sub-group -- therefore, just one couple -- gets to reproduce from out of the entire
group (collection of sub-groups). This would account for the character of the one popular clique of the most
highly fertile females.
The stresses attending human females together in a breeding unit are evident in the experiences of co-
wives in polygyny. According to Essien (2018), “co-wife conflict especially in the early years of marriage is
pervasive, and often marked by outbursts of verbal or physical violence”. “Ongoing and contentious rivalry”
and “a recurrent motif of strident co-wife hostility” is how Jankowiak, Sudakov & Wilreker (2005) put it: “…
we found women' s sexual desire and reproductive interests paramount factors in promoting co-wife
conflict (that is a) deep-seated resentment”. Oppong, Monebenimp & Nzefa (2019) discuss the “emotional
suppression” felt by co-wives. The chronic stress experienced by co-wives is so severe that a principal
theme of the findings by Tabi, Doster & Cheney (2010) is infertility, with it prompting co-wives to welcome
additional wives so as to avoid divorce. The co-wives’ predicament in their contradictory social dynamic is
neatly summed up in the title of Madhavan’s (2002) paper, Best of friends and worst of enemies:
competition and collaboration in polygyny. Female clique dynamics in a nutshell.
The male bodyguard to fend off female aggression
The human-clique-homologous gorilla pattern of small female sub-groups interpolated by males is now
understood (Dunbar, 2020) originally to be an adaptation to reduce stress on females from females in
other sub-groups, which could not be addressed by group fission given that large overall grouping itself is
an adaptation -- to avoid predation. Failing to deal with female intra-sexual stress would directly reduce
female fertility to sub-replacement, leading to local extinction. Dunbar writes:
“One possible mechanism would be the impact that social stress has on the mammalian female menstrual
system (and hence fecundity), the endocrinology of which is now well understood (Abbott 1984; Abbott et
al. 1984; Gordon et al. 1992; McNeilly et al. 1994; McNeilly 2001a,b; von Borrel et al. 2007; Chatterjee &
Chatterjee 2009; Son et al. 2012; Iwasa et al. 2017; see also Wasser & Barash 1983; Huchard &
Cowlishaw 2011)”.
Human females are no different in stress causing reproductive suppression (Wasser & Isenberg, 1986).
Interpolating males to reduce female-female aggression would be a pre-adaptation to subsequent pair-
bonding. Likewise appears to be concealed ovulation, which also functions to reduce female-female
aggression, according to Krems et al (2021), who, in testing a male investment model of concealed
ovulation against one of female rivalry, find clear support for the latter and none for the former. The
evidence here is that females evolved concealed ovulation because cues to ovulation trigger aggression
from other females trying to boost their own mating opportunities by reducing those of others.
It’s long been known that low level agonistic interactions between female gorillas increase dramatically in
frequency with the number of females, and not with group size (males and females both) per se (Watts,
1985). A strong parallel is evident in the closely-related primates, baboons. Within-group female coalitions
attack and thereby reproductively suppress their female victims, who experience more cycles before
conception and longer inter-birth intervals (Wasser & Starling, 1988), with female group size causing
increased female-female competition that correspondingly elevates stress levels (Hill, Lycett & Dunbar,
2000). “Conflicts between neighbouring harems are usually initiated by one, occasionally two, females; if
the conflict escalates, more females will become involved, until eventually the harem males are drawn into
the dispute and force the separation of the two groups of females (Dunbar 1983b, 2018)” (Dunbar, 2020).
The parallel appears to be very general indeed, and recognised some time ago by Gowaty (1996): “In fact,
female-female aggression may be the most parsimonious explanation for socially monogamous males in
many species” (p 28).
Both sexes experience crowding stress from same-sex others, but whereas for male mammals this is from
spatial proximity, for females it’s caused simply by their total number (Brown & Grunberg, 1995). It’s social
dynamics per se. Splitting the group of course would merely reintroduce the very predation threat that
increasing group size evolved to counter. A separation of females is required that is more complete than is
the merely spatial. Interceding males, one per each female sub-group, would be an adaptive solution if this
socially buffered the female sub-groups from each other, at the same time facilitating sufficient cohesion to
create overall one coordinated large group to dissuade or deal with predators. As noted by Dunbar (2012):
“It seems that in the large groups adult males act as bridges, or weak links, that help maintain the cohesion
between clusters of females”. This is strongly echoed in the afore-mentioned new work (Morrison, 2019)
showing unexpected ape contiguity with human multi-level social structure and inter-group dynamics.
This interceding male Dunbar dubs the bodyguard, which is to borrow a term coined by Mesnick (1997) but
which was on the understanding that deterrence was of male aggression. Dunbar himself formerly had
considered the bodyguard to dissuade unwanted social-sexual advances from males, which had been
proposed by Lumkin (1983), and as a possible basis of primate pair-bonding by Norscia & Borgognini-Tarli
(2008). It was also the view of the present author in Moxon (2013), but there qualified to be specifically in
respect of social-sexual advances from low-mate-value males, thereby actually facilitating the female pair-
bond partner’s accessibility to and by males of high mate value -- that is, of a mate value substantially
higher than that of the female’s pair-bond partner. In other, colloquial words: clearing away the riff-raff
leaves the deck clear for hob-nobbing. Indeed, this may be the principal benefit of bodyguarding, on top of
and in the wake of the original function to reduce female-female stress. Low-mate-value males are unlikely
anyway to present a threat to the female in terms of unwanted conception, given rank-appropriate
behavioural self-inhibition by males, backed up by community sanction as well as that by the pair-bond
male. Being of greater genomic integrity (in this scenario), the pair-bond male is likely to be physically and
in other ways superior (more confident, belligerent, part of an effective coalition, etc), so would be
anticipated to win any fight. In this way, bodyguarding appears to be routinely facultative.
Its workings in this respect are tapped into by Hoplock, Stinson & Joordens (2019) in finding that “highly-
attractive men engage in mate-poaching behavior (proximity seeking) when a romantically-involved woman
is accompanied by a less-attractive boyfriend, but not when she is alone or accompanied by a boyfriend
who matches her attractiveness”. Here, the redundancy and abandonment of bodyguarding in the scenario
where it is not required by the female appears as if formalised, with high-mate-value males actually
preferring the presence of the erstwhile bodyguard during extra-pair courting of women. Indeed, the tactic
appears to be itself the very mode of courtship in attempts to poach pair-bonded females. High-mate-value
males overtly usurp low-mate-value males with women partners they perceive may be in the market for
extra-pair sex owing to substantial mate-value disparities. This is plainly what Moran, Kuhle, Wade & Seid
(2017) discovered. And in this scenario, Fugère, Cousins & MacLaren (2015) find there is reciprocal
behaviour from the female: more flirting, feeling less committed to the pair-bond and unconstrained by
(what the authors term) mate-guarding.
Bodyguarding has been misconstrued as mate-guarding
Fugère, Cousins & MacLaren appear to misconstrue bodyguarding as instead mate-guarding, which is
understandable in its being a far more familiar conceptualisation. A supposed defence of the female not in
the female’s but the male guarder’s own interests: and of the female from all social-sexual approach
(supposedly from high-mate-value as well as from low-mate-value male potential mate-poachers). It is a
thus conceptualised defence that the aforementioned Lumkin (1983) suggested was usurped in the
guarded female’s interests to become defence specifically against unwanted male approaches: what is
herein termed bodyguarding.Mate-guarding is a notion based on a chain of assumptions. The assumed
male need to be assured of paternity, as a consequence of assumed male investment in offspring.
Underlying all is the default assumption of male proprietorial control of the female, which appears to be
inappropriate incursion of contemporary ideology -- that only male interests ever are served. This notion
has no scientific basis and is flatly contradicted by a diametrically opposite insight from biology: the fact
that the female is the limiting factor in reproduction dictates that the female interest must be preferenced,
as indeed it is.
The human mating system did not evolve from a need for male investment in offspring. Not only is
evidence for paternal investment equivocal (for a very brief review, see Moxon, 2013, p27), but as is now
well evidenced, modelled and very widely agreed, any paternal investment that may have evolved did so in
the wake of the evolution of the human mating system, so cannot be the basis of it. This was the
conclusion of an across-species (including human) key investigation by Brotherton & Komers (2003), and
specifically regarding humans by Chapais (2008). Chapais (2011) concludes that human pair-bonding
originated as “a pre-adaptation for the evolution of parental cooperation in the provisioning of progressively
altricial (helpless) children”. Similarly outlining a primate phylogeny of pair-bonding, Geary & Bailey (2011)
conclude that the emergence of a specifically human mating pattern merely coincided with increasing male
provisioning. Opie et al (2013) applied phylogenetic comparative methods widely to 230 different species,
confirming an antecedent evolutionary pathway. Lukas & Clutton-Block (2013) confirm this.
With the evidence overwhelming that male provisioning was not the basis of the human mating system,
then the notion that its foundation is the need for the male to be assured of his paternity (in order to
protect his investment) evaporates. There is no investment to protect. As it is the male’s investment
that is taken to be the reason why males supposedly persist in trying to prevent the female partner
from mating with other males, then such attempts would be pointless. The evidence indeed is that
mate-guarding does not work -- that is, what is presumed to be mate-guarding actually does not thus
function. It fails so badly that by some measures extra-pair paternity is actually greater with mate-
guarding, according to Kempenaers, Verheyen & Dhondt (1995), who conclude: “despite mate guarding,
paternity seems to be largely under female control and unattractive males guarding their mate are making
the best of a bad situation”. Little if any relationship exists between the strength of mate-guarding and
paternity in avian species (Johnson & Burley, 1998), despite their seeming strict monogamy. Kokko &
Morrell (2005) ask “if females regularly escape mate-guarding attempts, we face an enigma: why does
mate-guarding evolve if it is so inefficient?“ The answer is because the male is not guarding his own
interests but the female’s, as in bodyguarding. What has been taken to be mate-guarding of the male’s
interests would appear in fact -- as outlined above -- to deter social-sexual advance only by males of lower
mate-value (lesser genomic integrity) -- that is, lower than that of her pair-bonded partner -- who would not
serve the female’s interests to accept, and surely she would not want. In marked contrast, higher mate-
value (greater genomic integrity) suitors -- that is, higher than that of her pair-bonded partner -- would be in
the female’s interests to accept, if the mate-value difference were significant enough to outweigh the risk to
the endurance of the pair-bond. Again to reiterate: even if the male wished to try to prevent such mating,
ultimately he would not be able to do so, as the adverse difference in ranking would be reflected in the
suitor’s greater fighting ability or coalitional strength. Not that an agonistic encounter likely would occur: it
would be obviated by the psychological and physiological mechanisms that have evolved in the service of
hierarchy.
Infanticide prevention is a red herring
Not considered bodyguarding, though which might be thought a putative special form of it, is infanticide
prevention: supposed male defence of a female to keep at bay other males who might kill unweaned
offspring so as to prompt the female to end lactation and thereby resume cycling and fecundability. As a
possible basis of the evolution of pair-living / -bonding it’s in major doubt even in principle. Supposedly to
cut her losses in anticipation of infanticide in a male takeover scenario, a female may spontaneously abort
a foetus (what is dubbed the Bruce effect), but again there is here a failure to take account of male
heterogeneity. With the new male necessarily of a higher genomic integrity sufficient to have been able to
effect takeover, the female gains in fertility, which quickly manifests in improved reproductive output in
quality-x-quantity terms, given an immediate return to cycling, and then not just a replacement offspring in
short order, but subsequent offspring of the same high genomic integrity. The imperative to maximise
purging manifests again. Not only has the female not sustained any net cost, but has benefited. It is
anyway frequently acknowledged how extraordinarily difficult it is to find evidence of the occurrence of
infanticide, let alone of its prevention, in any species.
Infanticide prevention as the foundation of monogamy in humans and primates generally is championed
most recently by Opie et al (2019), but their phylogenetic analysis considers only a highly restricted set of
other alternative key factors as hypotheses (just parental care and a distribution of females too thin for
males practically to have harems, with neither of these incorporating male heterogeneity & female choice),
so the analysis is set up as a forced choice where only infanticide prevention is likely to be supported.
Fernandez-Duque, Huck, Van Belle & Di Fiore (2020) in reviewing competing hypotheses take particular
issue with the infanticide prevention hypothesis, citing a phylogenetic analysis (Lukas & Clutton-Brock,
2013) completely at odds with Opie’s earlier outline (Opie, Atkinson, Dunbar & Shultz, 2013) -- which last
has been the subject of rebuttals and counters to counter-rebuttals -- going into considerable detail about
poor methodology. Fernandez-Duque et al explain that support for the infanticide prevention hypothesis
(though here not alone among evolutionary explanations in sharing the same fault) is a case of the fallacy
known as affirming the consequent. Making a poor case for its significance are unsatisfactory proxies of
infanticide risk, that supposedly is addressable by the adaptation of pair-living/ -bonding. But the existence
of the adaptation is itself the basis of inferring infanticide prevention is the problem the adaptation evolved
to solve.
If infanticide were a significant problem for such as the gorilla, Dunbar (2020) points out, then fertility
decline of females would be in line with increasing numbers of males, not exclusively through the increase
in the number of females (as is found). Instead, infanticide in the wake of takeovers always remains a risk.
If a harem’s male is deposed, there is no other male to defend against the usurping male if he chooses to
be infanticidal. In the case of the harem male still being in place, there is no logical rationale for infanticide
in the first place. There would be no benefit for another male to attempt to bring back into cycling a
lactating harem female belonging to a harem still with its male, because the long delay between ending
lactation and resuming cycling means the opportunity to capitalise on the initiative would be in the future,
when the harem male would have to be challenged anew for the sexual access. Unless the male
challenger has the wherewithal to take over the harem, then he’s unlikely to achieve sexual access, and
the female won’t be co-operative in any case. This is to return to the situation in bodyguarding, where
males of lower mate value than the pair-bonded (or harem) male are easily dissuaded from making socio-
sexual advances, and indeed, would internalise this as self-inhibition. A male of substantially higher mate
value than the pair-bond (or harem) male is a different proposition. His takeover would be part-and-parcel
of the species’ reproductive system, serving to increase reproductive output and efficiency, and the only
individual who loses out is the deposed lower-mate-value male. A female harem member may suffer the
immediate loss of a newborn through infanticide, but this is not a loss in even slightly wider perspective --
just as in the spontaneous abortion scenario (above) -- as it’s a clear gain in the greater genomic integrity
provided by the new harem male, which will be embodied in an immediate replacement offspring if one
were to be lost to infanticide, and, more importantly, several subsequent offspring. Even if the harem male
is replaced simply through his aging, this too is of significant benefit to the harem females in that the
likelihood of gene replication error in the male’s gametes will have increased dramatically. It’s hard to see
how the female would benefit in being protected from the threat of infanticide even if it were real.
Whether as social-sexual advance or attempting infanticide, the concern that lower-mate-value males may
gain the system, as it were, is misplaced, as these are the very males not in a position to do so. By
contrast, higher-mate-value males, who are of actual benefit to females, are not gaining the system, being
very much a part of how the mating system works, which is to the benefit of females generally and only for
a minority of males. The issue of infanticide-prevention and the scope for a male service to the female in
this regard is a theoretical problem only -- if that, in that the theory appears awry.
Another apparent misconception regarding infanticide prevention is that concealed ovulation serves this
function. As already outlined, modelling now shows instead that it reduces female-female aggression
(Krems et al, 2021). It has long been claimed that the most parsimonious conclusion about concealed
ovulation is that it is not an adaptation at all: simply loss of function through the absence of selection
pressure (Burt, 1992; Pawlowski, 1999). It is an untested presumption that concealed ovulation causes
paternity uncertainty, sufficient that as a consequence a potentially infanticidal male sees a significant risk
of unintentionally killing his own offspring.
Furthermore, strangely there has not been considered that concealed ovulation is of most utility to females
in reducing the benefits and increasing the costs to lower-mate-value males in their social-sexual
approaches in attempt to usurp pair-bonding. Together with what anyway are the difficulties for low-mate-
value males in approaching a bodyguarded non-receptive female, the strategy of sneak mating attempts
would not be worth the risks if it were made impossible to time them to when the female is fertile. In thus
augmenting bodyguarding in keeping lower-mate-value males at bay, then again, as with the bodyguard,
thereby is allowed mutual social-sexual approach of higher-mate-value males and pair-bond females. For
a higher-mate-value extra-pair male, concealment of ovulation is not an issue. On the contrary, ovulation
prompts female proceptive and receptive behaviour towards them, notwithstanding its not being
specifically so: nevertheless it would be in this context -- of extra-pair sex with a substantially higher-mate-
value male being in the offing. There’s another advantage. With the female allowing, indeed encouraging
him to be close, he is in a position to detect subtle indications of impending ovulation (eg, Lobmaier et al,
2018) and sexual arousal (Wiseman & Shrira, 2020), that a lower-mate-value male, who, in not being
allowed close and instead positively distanced, could not. He will never be in a position to increase the
probability of conception to sufficiently offset the likely costs, to render a bid for a sneak mating worth the
risk. Further disadvantaging lower-mate-value suitors may explain why human coitus itself is concealed.
With the timing of sex a good indicator of likely heightened female sexual receptivity prompted by ovulation,
its discovery by a lower-mate-value male would encourage his social-sexual approach in the immediate
future so as still to be within the female’s fertile window. Not concealing coitus would be provocative and
potentially very destabilising, in line with the interpretation of new data by Yitzchak (2020) that hidden
coitus serves to maintain cooperation with those within the group who are prevented from mating.
Placing infanticide prevention at the heart of the aetiology of the human mating system appears to be
unwarranted inference, evoked as a default hypothesis through a false understanding that essentially
humans are monogamous and that (as aforesaid) this has a seeming fivefold opportunity cost compared to
polygyny, as might thus be considered obligate monogamy. In the human case, at least, with monogamy
not being obligate, and simply a reduced form of polygyny for those males not able to secure multiple
females, there is no opportunity cost to sustain. The misconception at root is through the failure to
appreciate the centrality of male heterogeneity and female choice. Infanticide prevention is proffered for
want of an alternative in the paucity of hypothesis generation that stems from mis-framing what is here at
issue.
Conclusion
With pair-bonding to ensure repeat offspring of the greatest-possible genomic integrity (least mutationally
compromised), featuring bodyguarding to dissuade low-mate-value male social-sexual approach, thereby
actually facilitating approach by/to high-mate-value males for extra-pair sex; all while buffering against
female age-related fertility decline, and built on a pre-adaptation of interposed males to reduce female-
female stress … the overall picture of the basis of the human mating system is one of service by the male
to the female. Yet neither provisioning (the erstwhile assumed mode of such service) nor infanticide-
prevention (the still current oft-assumed mode) is its basis. Instead, it’s the set of ramifications from keen
female choice and profound heterogeneity of males, in turn from the imperative to purge relentlessly
accumulating gene replication error.
Service by the male is investigated in a new review of the evolution of monogamy in a primate model by
Dolotovskaya, Walker & Heymann (2020) by pitching against each other three categories of hypotheses:
male-services,resource-defence and mate-defence -- this last being mate-guarding. The authors conclude
that “Our data is most consistent with the ‘male-services’ hypothesis for pair-bond maintenance, where a
female contributes more to the proximity and affiliation maintenance while a male provides beneficial
services”. Note the authors are cautious in making their claims in respect of maintenance rather than origin
per se, because they include care of infants, which they concede evolved in the wake of the evolution of
pair-bonding. The principal male services they ascribe to protection from predation and territorial defence,
though these are not from pair-bonding but are the platform on which it was possible. What remains may
be simply the way male heterogeneity and female choice play out.
Male services, with the female the party keeping the pair together, chimes with the data on mate-retention
tactics showing that most are women’s or mostly used by women (for a brief outline and citations, see
Moxon 2020, p10), and the research concerning the various other ways women in comparison to men
reveal a far greater concern for and interest in their pair-bond (for a referenced account, see Moxon 2016,
pp73-75). Of romantic attachment itself, males but not females are dismissive -- in a near universal sex
difference (Schmitt, 2003). All lines of evidence converge on a conclusion that human pair-living/-bonding
is not at all the presumed proprietorial control by men of women. Indeed, it appears more the converse.
Objectively, the human mating system is just that; a system, in which all individuals are engaged to play a
part in what is a group-level phenomenon, with the goal of maximising overall reproductive
output/efficiency. This is rather too obvious understanding to have been lacking -- though still there are
those hidebound by the outdated group selection debate, unaware of the now multiple complementary
theoretical perspectives on how/why mutualism works. Appreciating the purging imperative driving the
profound skew amplifying male heterogeneity, and even accepting that profound male heterogeneity exists,
may be a different matter. Yet (the pre-adaptation of reducing female-female stress aside) a highly
parsimonious hypothesis unfolds from the one premise of purging.
References
Achorn, A.M. & Rosenthal, G.G. (2020). It's Not about Him: Mismeasuring 'Good Genes' in Sexual
Selection. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 35(3), 206-219. doi:10.1016/j.tree.2019.11.007
Anderson, C.M. (2000). The Persistence of Polygyny as an Adaptive Response to Poverty and
Oppression in Apartheid South Africa. Cross-Cultural Research, 34(2), 99-112.
doi:10.1177/106939710003400201
Atmar, W. (1991). On the role of males. Animal Behaviour, 41(2), 195-20. doi:10.1016/S0003-
3472(05)80471-3
Baker, R.R. & Bellis, M.A. (1995). Human sperm competition: Copulation, masturbation and infidelity.
Chapman and Hall. London
Baresh, D. (2016). Out of Eden: The Surprising Consequences of Polygamy. Oxford University Press
Benenson, J.F., Markovits, H., Hultgren, B., Nguyen, T., Bullock, G. & Wrangham, R. (2013). Social
exclusion: more important to human females than males. PLoS ONE, 8(2), e55851. doi:
10.1371/journal.pone.0055851
Blurton-Jones, N., Marlowe, F., Hawkes, K. & O’Connel, J.F. (2000). Paternal investment and hunter-
gatherer divorce rates. In Adaptation and Human Behavior: an Anthropological Perspective by Cronk, L.,
Chagnon, N.A. & Irons, W. Aldine De Gruyter, NY.
Brotherton, P. & Komers, P. (2003). Monogamy: Mating strategies and partnerships. In Birds, Humans
and Other Mammals, eds Reichard, U. & Boesch, C. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK. pp 42-
58
Brown, K.J. & Grunberg, N.E. (1995). Effects of housing on male and female rats: crowding stresses
males but calms females. Physiology & Behavior, 58, 1085-1089. doi: 10.1016/0031-9384(95)02043-8
Burt, A. (1992). ‘Concealed Ovulation’ and Sexual Signals in Primates. Folia Primatologica, 58, 1-6.
doi: 10.1159/000156600
Chapais, B. (2008). Primeval Kinship: How Pair-Bonding Gave Birth to Human Society. Harvard
University Press, Cambridge, MA).
Chapais, B. (2011). The Evolutionary History of Pair-bonding and Parental Collaboration. Chapter 3
Chika, I.S. & Nneka, U. (2014). Discriminatory cultural practices and women's rights among the Igbos
of south-east Ngeria: a critique. Journal of Law, Policy and Globalization, 25, 18-27
Cochas, A., Yoccoz, N.G., Da Silva, A., Goossens, B. & Allainé, D. (2006). Extra-pair paternity in the
monogamous alpine marmot (Marmota marmota): the roles of social setting and female mate choice.
Behavioral Ecology & Sociobiology, 59, 597-605. doi:10.1007/s00265-005-0086-8
Conroy-Beam, D. & Buss, D.M. (2019). Why is age so important in human mating? Evolved age
preferences and their influences on multiple mating behaviors. Evolutionary Behavioral Sciences, 13(2),
127-157. doi:10.1037/ebs0000127
David-Barrett, T., Rotkirch, A., Carney, J., Behncke Izquierdo, I., Krems, J.A., Townley, D., et al.
(2015). Women Favour Dyadic Relationships, but Men Prefer Clubs: Cross-Cultural Evidence from Social
Networking. PLoS ONE, 10(3): e0118329. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0118329
doi:10.1016/j.paid.2015.07.048
doi:10.17863/CAM.43619
Dolotovskaya, S., Walker, S. & Heymann, E.W. (2020). What makes a pair bond in a Neotropical
primate: female and male contributions. Royal Society Open Science, (1), 191489.
doi:10.1098/rsos.191489
Du, J. & Mace, R. (2019). Marriage stability in a pastoralist society. Behavioral Ecology, 30(6), 1567-
1574. doi:10.1093/beheco/arz115
Dugand, R.J., Kennington, W.J. & Tomkins, J.L (2018). Evolutionary divergence in competitive mating
success through female mating bias for good genes. Science Advances 4(5) eaaq0369.
doi:10.1126/sciadv.aaq0369.
Dunbar, R.I.M. (2012). The Science of Love and Betrayal. Faber and Faber
Dunbar, R.I.M. (2018). Defending the Undefendable: Male Territorial Behaviour and Mating System in
Monogamous Primates. bioRxiv. doi:10.1101/354118
Dunbar, R.I.M. (2020). Fertility as a constraint on group size in African great apes. Biological Journal
of the Linnean Society, 129(1), 1-13. doi:10.1093/biolinnean/blz172
Dupanloup, I., Pereira, L., Bertorelle, G., Calafell, F., Prata, M.J., Amorim, A. & Barbujani, G. (2003). A
recent shift from polygyny to monogamy in humans is suggested by the analysis of worldwide Y-
chromosome diversity. Journal of Molecular Evolution, 57(1), 85-97. doi: 10.1007/s00239-003-2458-x
Essien, E.D. (2018). The interplay between conflict and solidarity in co-wife family relationship:
Experience from Africa. International Journal of Development and Sustainability, 7(4), 1544-1563
Fernandez‐Duque, E., Huck, M., Van Belle, S. & Di Fiore, A. (2020). The evolution of pair‐living,
sexual monogamy, and cooperative infant care: Insights from research on wild owl monkeys, titis, sakis,
and tamarins. Yearbook of Physical Anthropology, 171, 118-173. doi:10.1002/ajpa.24017
Fernandez‐Duque, E., Huck, M., Van Belle, S. & Di Fiore, A. (2020). The evolution of pair‐living,
sexual monogamy, and cooperative infant care: Insights from research on wild owl monkeys, titis, sakis,
and tamarins. Yearbook of Physical Anthropology, 171, 118-173. doi:10.1002/ajpa.24017
Fisher, H.E. (1989). Evolution of human serial pair-bonding. American Journal of Physical
Anthropology, 78(3), 331-354. doi:10.1002/ajpa.1330780303
Fisher, H.E. (1994). Anatomy of Love: The Natural History of Mating, Marriage and Why We Stray.
Ballantine Books
Franchini, L.F. & Pollard, K.S. (2017). Human evolution: the non-coding revolution. BMC Biology, 15,
89. doi:10.1186/s12915-017-0428-9
Fugère, M.A., Cousins, A.J. & MacLaren, S.A. (2015). (Mis)matching in physical attractiveness and
women's resistance to mate guarding. Personality and Individual Differences, 87, 190-195.
Gavrilets, S. (2012). Human origins and the transition from promiscuity to pair-bonding. Proceedings
of the National Academy of Sciences, 109 (25), 9923-9928. doi:10.1073/pnas.1200717109
Geary, D.C. & Bailey, D.H. (2011). Reflections on the human family. Chapter 21 in The Oxford
Handbook of Evolutionary Family Psychology (ed Salmon, C. & Shackelford, T.K.) Oxford University Press
Gowaty, P.A. (1996). Battles of the sexes and origins of monogamy: 21-52 in Black, J.L. Partnerships
in Birds. Oxford Series in Ecology and Evolution. Oxford University Press
Grebe, N.M., Gangestad, S.W., Garver-Apgar, C.E. & Thornhill, R. (2013). Women’s luteal-phase
sexual proceptivity and the functions of extended sexuality. Psychological Science, 24(10), 2106-2110.
doi:10.1177/0956797613485965
Grehan, J.R. & Schwartz, J.H. (2009). Evolution of the second orangutan: phylogeny and
biogeography of hominid origins. Journal of Biogeography, 36, 1823-1844. doi:10.1111/j.1365-
2699.2009.02141.x
Grehan, J.R. (2006). Mona Lisa Smile: The Morphological Enigma of Human and Great Ape Evolution.
The Anatomical Record (Part B: The New Anatomist), 289B, 139-157. doi:10.1002/ar.b.20107
Gwirayi, C. (2016). Bachelor of Adult Education students’ perceptions of polygamy at a state university
in Zimbabwe. Dzimbahwe Journal of Multidisciplinary Research, 1(1), 25-35.
Hanne, C.L., Simmons, L.W. & Rhodes, G. (2009.) Genetic dissimilarity, genetic diversity, and mate
preferences in humans. Evolution and Human Behavior, 31(1), 48-58.
doi:10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2009.07.001
Harley, V. & MacNeill, N. (2017). Queen Bees, Wannabes, relational aggression and inappropriate
socialisation [online]. Australian Educational Leader, 39(4), 26-28.
Harrison, M.E. & Chivers, D.J. (2007). The orang-utan mating system and the unflanged male: A
product of increased food stress during the late Miocene and Pliocene? Journal of Human Evolution, 52 (3),
275-293. doi:10.1016/j.jhevol.2006.09.005
Hill, R.A., Lycett, J. & Dunbar, R.I.M. (2000). Ecological determinants of birth intervals in baboons.
Behavioral Ecology, 11, 560-564. doi:10.1093/beheco/11.5.560
Hoplock, L.B., Stinson, D.A. & Joordens, C.T. (2019). “Is she really going out with him?”:
Attractiveness exchange and commitment scripts for romantic relationships. Personality and Individual
Differences, 139, 181-190. doi:10.1016/j.paid.2018.11.014
Huck, M., Di Fiore, A. & Fernandez-Duque, E. (2020). Of Apples and Oranges? The Evolution of
“Monogamy” in Non-human Primates. Frontiers in Ecology and Evolution. doi:10.3389/fevo.2019.00472
in The Oxford Handbook of Evolutionary Family Psychology (ed Salmon, C. & Shackelford, T. K.).
Oxford University Press
Jankowiak, W., Sudakov, M. & Wilreker, B.C. (2005). Co-wife conflict and co-operation. Ethnology,
44(1), 81-98.
Johnson, K. & Burley, N.T. (1998). Mating tactics and mating systems of birds. Ornithological
Monographs 49. Avian Reproductive Tactics: Female and Male Perspectives. University of California
Press. 21-60
Jones, B.C., Hahn, A.C. & DeBruine, L.M. (2019). Ovulation, sex hormones and women's mating
psychology. Trends in Cognitive Science, 23(1), 51-62. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2018.10.008
Kaplan, H., Hill, K., Lancaster, J. & Hurtado, A.M. (2000). A theory of human life history evolution: Diet,
intelligence, and longevity. Evolutionary Anthropology, 9, 156-185. doi:10.1002/1520-
6505(2000)9:4<156::AID-EVAN5>3.0.CO;2-7
Kempenaers, B., Verheyen, G.R. & Dhondt, A.A. (1995). Mate guarding and copulation behaviour in
monogamous and polygynous blue tits: do males follow a best-of-a-bad-job strategy?. Behavioral Ecology
& Sociobiology, 36, 33–42 (1995). doi:10.1007/BF00175726
Kempenaers, B.M., Verheyen, G.R., Broeck, M.V., Burke, T., Broeckhoven, C.V. & Dhonth, A.A.
(1992). Extra-pair paternity results from female preference for high-quality males in the blue tit. Nature, 357,
494-496. doi:10.1038/357494a0
Klug, H. (2018). Why Monogamy? A Review of Potential Ultimate Drivers. Frontiers in Ecology and
Evolution, 6. doi:10.3389/fevo.2018.00030
Kokko, H. & Morrell, L.J. (2005). Mate guarding, male attractiveness, and paternity under social
monogamy. Behavioral Ecology, 16, 724-731. doi:10.1093/beheco/ari050
Krems, J.A., Claessens, S., Fales, M.R., Campenni, M., Haselton, M.G. & Aktipis, A. (2021). An
agent-based model of the female rivalry hypothesis for concealed ovulation in humans. Nature Human
Behavior. 2021 Jan 25. doi:10.1038/s41562-020-01038-9. Epub ahead of print. PMID: 33495572.
Kvarnemo, C. (2018). Why do some animals mate with one partner rather than many? A review of
causes and consequences of monogamy. Biological Reviews, 93, 1795-1812. doi:10.1111/brv.12421
Kwon, K. & Lease, A.M. (2007). Clique membership and social adjustment in children's same-gender
cliques: The contribution of the type of clique to children's self-reported adjustment. Merrill-Palmer
Quarterly, 53(2), 216-242. doi:10.1353/mpq.2007.0012
Labuda, D., Lefebvre, J-F., Nadeau, P. & Roy-Gagnon, M.H. (2010). Female-to-male breeding ratio in
modern humans -- an analysis based on historical recombinations. The American Journal of Human
Genetics, 86(3), 353-363. doi:10.1016/j.ajhg.2010.01.029
Lambert, C.T., Sabol, A.C. & Solomon, N.G. (2018). Genetic monogamy in socially monogamous
mammals is primarily predicted by multiple life history factors: a meta-analysis. Frontiers in Ecology and
Evolution, 6, 139. doi:10.3389/fevo.2018.00139
Lanctot, R.B. & Best, L.B. (2000). Comparison of methods for determining dominance rank in male
and female prairie voles. Journal of Mammalogy, 81(3), 734-745. doi: 10.1644/1545-
1542(2000)081<0734:COMFDD>2.3.CO;2
Larson, C.M., Pillsworth, E.G., Haselton M.G. (2012). Ovulatory Shifts in Women’s Attractions to
Primary Partners and Other Men: Further Evidence of the Importance of Primary Partner Sexual
Attractiveness. PLoS ONE, 7(9), e44456. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0044456
Lassek, W.D. & Gaulin, S.J.C. (2018). Do the Low WHRs and BMIs Judged Most Attractive Indicate
Higher Fertility? Evolutionary Psychology,16(4), 1474704918803998. doi:10.1177/1474704918800063
Lawson, D.W., James, S., Ngadaya, E., Ngowi, B., Mfinanga, S.G.M. & Borgerhoff Mulder, M. (2015).
No evidence that polygynous marriage is a harmful cultural practice in northern Tanzania. Proceedings of
the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 112 (45), 13827-13832.
doi:10.1073/pnas.1507151112
Leonard, K.E. & Roberts, L.J. (1998). Marital aggression, quality, and stability in the first year of
marriage: Findings from the Buffalo Newlywed Study. In Bradbury, T.N. (ed.), The Developmental Course
of Marital Dysfunction (pp. 44-73). Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511527814.004
Ligrone, R. (2019). The Emergence of Humanity. In Biological Innovations that Built the World.
Springer, Cham. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-16057-9_12
Lobmaier, J.S., Fischbacher, U., Wirthmüller, U. & Knoch, D. (2018). The scent of attractiveness:
levels of reproductive hormones explain individual differences in women's body odour. Proceedings of the
Royal Society B Biological Sciences, 285. doi:10.1098/rspb.2018.1520
Locke, D., Hillier, L., Warren, W. et al. (2011). Comparative and demographic analysis of orang-utan
genomes. Nature, 469, 529-533. doi:10.1038/nature09687
Lukas, D. & Clutton-Brock, T.H. (2013). The evolution of social monogamy in mammals. Science, 341,
526-530. doi:10.1126/science.1238677
Lumkin, S. (1983). Female manipulation of male avoidance of cuckoldry behavior in the ring dove. In
Social Behavior (Ed Wasser, S.K.), 91-112. Academic Press. New York
Macintyre, S. & Sooman, A. (1991). Non-paternity and prenatal genetic screening. Lancet, Nov 2;
338(8775), 1151. doi:10.1016/0140-6736(91)91513-T
MacPherson, B., Scott, R. & Gras, R. (2021). Sex and recombination purge the genome of deleterious
alleles: An individual based modeling approach. Ecological Complexity, 45, 100910.
doi:10.1016/j.ecocom.2021.100910
Madhavan, S. (2002). Best of Friends and Worst of Enemies: Competition and Collaboration in
Polygyny. Ethnology, 41(1), 69-84. doi:10.2307/4153021
Marcinkowska, U.M., M.Mijas, M., Koziara, K., et al. (2020). Variation in sociosexuality across natural
menstrual cycles: associations with ovarian hormones and cycle phase. Evolution and Human Behavior.
doi:10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2020.06.008
Martinossi-Allibert, I., Rueffler, C., Arnqvist, G., & Berger, D. (2019). The efficacy of good genes
sexual selection under environmental change. Proceedings of the Royal Society B. Biological Sciences,
286(1896), 20182313. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2018.2
Mesnick, S.L. (1997). Sexual alliances: evidence and evolutionary implications. In: P.A. Gowaty (ed.)
Feminism and Evolutionary Biology, pp. 207-60. London: Chapman & Hall
Moore, M.M. (1985). Nonverbal courtship patterns in women: Context and consequences. Ethology
and Sociobiology, 6(4), 237-247. doi:10.1016/0162-3095(85)90016-0
Moran, J.B., Kuhle, B., Wade, T. & Seid, M.A. (2017). To poach or not to poach? Men are more willing
to short-term poach mated women who are more attractive than their mates. The Journal of the
Evolutionary Studies Consortium. NEEPS X, 58-69
Morrison, R. (2019). Western Gorilla Social Structure and Inter-Group Dynamics. (Doctoral thesis).
Moxon, S.P. (2009). Dominance as adaptive stressing and ranking of males, serving to allocate
reproduction by differential self-suppressed fertility: Towards a fully biological understanding of social
systems. Medical Hypotheses, 73(1), 5-14. https://stevemoxon.co.uk/dominance-as-adaptive-stressing-to-
allocate-reproduction/
Moxon, S.P. (2012). The origin of the sexual divide in the ‘genetic filter’ function: Male disadvantage
and why it is not perceived. New Male Studies, 1(3), 96-124.
http://newmalestudies.com/OJS/index.php/nms/article/view/47
Moxon, S.P. (2013). Human pair-bonding as primarily a service to the female (in excluding other
males of lower (but not higher) mate-value, and a buffer against her own age-related mate-value decline).
New Male Studies, 2(2), 24-38. http://newmalestudies.com/OJS/index.php/nms/article/view/71
Moxon, S.P. (2013). Human pair-bonding as primarily a service to the female (in excluding other
males of lower (but not higher) mate-value, and a buffer against her own age-related mate-value decline).
New Male Studies, 2(2), 24-38. http://newmalestudies.com/OJS/index.php/nms/article/view/71
Moxon, S.P. (2016). Sex Difference Explained: From DNA to Society — Purging Gene Copy Errors.
New Male Studies. https://www.newmalestudies.com/OJS/index.php/nms/article/view/236/271
Moxon, S.P. (2016). Sex Difference Explained: From DNA to Society — Purging Gene Copy Errors.
New Male Studies. https://www.newmalestudies.com/OJS/index.php/nms/article/view/236/271
Moxon, S.P. (2017). Only Male Genital Modification is a Form of Control; its Female Counterpart
Originated as a Female-Initiated Competitive Ploy. New Male Studies, 6(2), 126-165.
http://newmalestudies.com/OJS/index.php/nms/article/view/262/318
Moxon, S.P. (2019). The sexes serve to purge mutations by selection on males, boosting the function
of sex to maintain genomic integrity. New Male Studies, 8(1), 25-51.
https://newmalestudies.com/OJS/index.php/nms/article/view/293/354
Moxon, S.P. (2020). How and Why Partner Violence is Normal Female Behaviour but Aberrational
Male Behaviour. New Male Studies, 9(1), 1-23.
www.newmalestudies.com/OJS/index.php/nms/article/view/310/372
Moxon, S.P. (2020). How and Why Partner Violence is Normal Female Behaviour but Aberrational
Male Behaviour. New Male Studies, 9(1), 1-23.
www.newmalestudies.com/OJS/index.php/nms/article/view/310/372
Nakahashi, W. & Horiuchi, S. (2012). Evolution of ape and human mating systems. Journal of
Theoretical Biology, 296, 56-64. doi:10.1016/j.jtbi.2011.11.026
Norscia, I. & Borgognini-Tarli, S.M. (2008). Ranging behavior and possible correlates of pair-living in
South-eastern Avahis (Madagascar). International Journal of Primatology, 29(1), 153-171.
doi:10.1007/s10764-007-9219-4
Opie, C. (2019). Monogamy and infanticide in complex societies. Chapter 5 in Dunbar's Number.
Shankland, D. (ed.). Royal Anthropological Institute, 45, 59-74.
Opie, C., Atkinson, Q.D., Dunbar, R.I.M. & Shultz, S. (2013). Male infanticide leads to social
monogamy in primates. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America,
110, 13328-13332. doi:0.1073/pnas.1307903110
Oppong, G., Monebenimp, F. & Nzefa, L.D. (2019). ‘You just have to grin and bear’ – emotional
suppression among women in polygyny in Cameroon, Culture. Health & Sexuality, 21(8), 946-956,
doi:10.1080/13691058.2018.1527944
Pawłowski, B. (1999). Loss of oestrus and concealed ovulation in human evolution: The case against
the sexual-selection hypothesis. Current Anthropology, 40(3), 257-275. doi:10.1086/200017
Pawłowski, B.P., Lowen, C B. & Dunbar, R.I.M. (1998). Neocortex size, social skills and mating
success in primates. Behaviour, 135(3), 357-368. doi:10.1163/156853998793066285
Powell-Lunder, J. (2013). Understanding why queen bees are able to hold court. Psychology Today.
https://www.psychologytoday.com/blog/lets-talk-tween/201311/understanding-why-queen-bees-are-able-
hold-court
Prokop, Z.M., Michalczyk, Ł., Drobniak, S.M., Herdegen, M. and Radwan, J. (2012), Meta-analysis
suggests choosy females get sexy sons more than "Good genes". Evolution, 66, 2665-2673.
doi:10.1111/j.1558-5646.2012.01654.x
Rilling, J.K., Kaufman, T.L., Smith, E.O., Patel, R. & Worthman, C.M. (2009). Abdominal depth and
waist circumference as influential determinants of human female attractiveness. Evolution and Human
Behavior, 30(1), 21-31. doi:10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2008.08.007
Robbins, M.M., Sicotte, P. & Stewart, K.J. (Eds.). (2001). Mountain Gorillas: Three Decades of
Research at Karisoke. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press
Robson, S.L., van Schaik, C.P. & Hawkes, K. (2006). The derived features of human life history. In
Hawkes, K. & Paine, R.R. (eds.), The Evolution of Human Life History (pp.17-44). SantaFe, NM: School of
American Research Press
Rooker, K. & Gavrilets, S. (2016). Evolution of long-term pair-bonding in humans. In Shackelford, K. &
Weekes-Shackelford, V.A. (eds.) Encyclopedia of Evolutionary Psychological Science, 7(472), 1-
25.doi:10.1007/978-3-319-16999-6_99-1
Rosenfeld, M.J., Thomas,R.J. & Falcon, M. (2018). How Couples Meet and Stay Together, Waves 1,
2, and 3: Public version 3.04, plus wave 4 supplement version 1.02 and wave 5 supplement version 1.0
and wave 6 supplement ver 1.0 [Computer files]. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Libraries
Scelza, B.A., Prall, S.P., Swinford, N., Gopalan, S., Atkinson, E.G., McElreath, R., Sheehama, J. &
Henn, B.M. (2020). High rate of extrapair paternity in a human population demonstrates diversity in human
reproductive strategies. Science Advances, 6(8). doi:10.1126/sciadv.aay6195
Schacht, R. & Bell, A.V. (2016). The evolution of monogamy in response to partner scarcity. Scientific
Reports, 6, 32472. doi:10.1038/srep32472
Schacht, R. & Kramer, K.L. (2019). Are we monogamous? A review of the evolution of pair-bonding in
humans and its contemporary variation cross-culturally. Frontiers in Ecology and Evolution, 7.
doi:10.3389/fevo.2019.00230
Schmitt, D.P. et al. (2003). Are men universally more dismissing than women? Gender differences in
romantic attachment across 62 cultural regions. Personal Relationships, 10, 307-331. doi:10.1111/1475-
6811.00052
Sefcek, J.A., Brumbach, B.H., Vasquez, G. & Miller, G.F. (2006). The evolutionary psychology of
human mate choice: how ecology, genes, fertility and fashion influence mating strategies. Journal of
Psychology & Human Sexuality, 18(2-3), 125–182. doi: 10.1300/J056v18n02_05
Steiner, A.Z., Pritchard, D.A., Young, S.L. & Herring, A.H. (2014). Peri-implantation intercourse lowers
fecundability. Fertility and Sterility, 102(1), 178-182. doi:10.1016/j.fertnstert.2014.03.01
Stephens, W.N. (1963). The Family in Cross-Cultural Perspective. New York: Holt, Rinehart and
Winston.
Stern, J., Kordsmeyer, T.L. & Penke, L. (2021). A longitudinal evaluation of ovulatory cycle shifts in
women's mate attraction and preferences. Hormones & Behavior,128. 104916.
doi:10.1016/j.yhbeh.2020.104916. Epub 2021 Jan 6
Suda, C.A. (2007). Formal Monogamy and Informal Polygyny in Parallel. Inaugural Lecture, University
of Nairobi, October 4. http://erepository.uonbi.ac.ke:8080/handle/123456789/795
Szepsenwol, O., Mikulincer, M. & Birnbaum, G.E. (2013). Misguided attraction: The contribution of
normative and individual-differences components of the sexual system to mating preferences. Journal of
Research in Personality, 47(3), 196-200. doi:10.1016/j.jrp.2013.01.002
Tabi, M., Doster, C. & Cheney, T. (2010). A qualitative study of women in polygynous marriages.
International Nursing Review, 57, 121-127. doi:10.1111/j.1466-7657.2009.00762.x
Tang, H., Tang, Y. & Zeng, T. et al. (2020). Gene expression analysis reveals the tipping points during
infant brain development for human and chimpanzee. BMC Genomics, 21, 74. doi:10.1186/s12864-020-
6465-8
Thomas, A.G., Armstrong, S.L., Stewart-Williams, S. & Jones, B.C. (2021). Current fertility status does
not predict sociosexual attitudes and desires in normally ovulating women. Evolutionary Psychology.
doi:10.1177/1474704920976318
Uggla, C. , Gurmu, E. & Gibson, M.A. (2018). Are wives and daughters disadvantaged in polygynous
households? A case study of the Arsi Oromo of Ethiopia. Evolution and Human Behavior, 39 (2), 160-165.
doi:10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2017.11.00
Utami, S.S., Goossens, B., Bruford, M.W., de Ruiter, J.R. & van Hooff, J.A.R.A.M. (2002). Male
bimaturism and reproductive success in Sumatran orangutans. Behavioral Ecology, 13(5), 643-652.
doi:10.1093/beheco/13.5.643
van Stein, K.R., Strauß, B. & Brenk-Franz, K. (2019). Ovulatory Shifts in Sexual Desire But Not Mate
Preferences: An LH-Test-Confirmed, Longitudinal Study. Evolutionary Psychology.
doi:10.1177/1474704919848116
Velando, A., Torres, R. & Alonso-Alvarez, C. (2008). Avoiding bad genes: oxidatively damaged DNA
in germ line and mate choice. Bioessays, 30 (11-12), 1212-1219. doi: 10.1002/bies.20838
Walker, R.S., Hill, K.R., Flinn, M.V. & Ellsworth, R.M. (2011). Evolutionary history of hunter-gatherer
marriage practices. PLoS ONE, 6, 1-6. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0019066
Wasser, S.K. & Isenberg, D.Y. (1986). Reproductive Failure among Women: Pathology or Adaptation?,
Journal of Psychosomatic Obstetrics & Gynecology, 5(3), 153-175, doi:10.3109/01674828609016754
Wasser, S.K. & Starling, A.K. (1988). Proximate and ultimate causation of reproductive suppression
among female yellow baboons at Mikumi National Park, Tanzania. American Journal of Primatology, 16,
97-121. doi:10.1002/ajp.1350160202
Watts, D.P. (1985). Relations between group size and composition and feeding competition in
mountain gorilla groups. Animal Behaviour , 33, 72-85. doi:10.1016/S0003-3472(85)80121-4
West-Eberhard, M.J. (2005). The maintenance of sex as a developmental trap due to sexual selection.
Quarterly Review of Biology, 80(1), 47-53. doi:10.1086/431024
White, D.R., Betzig, L., Borgerhoff Mulder, M., Chick, G., Hartung, J., Irons, W., Low, B.S. & Otterbein,
K.F. (1988). Rethinking polygyny: co-wives, codes, and cultural systems. Current Anthropology, 29,
529(44). doi:10.1086/203674
Wilder, J.A., Mobasher, Z. & Hammer, M.F. (2004). Genetic evidence for unequal effective population
sizes of human males and females. Molecular Biology & Evolution, 21(11), 2047-2057.
doi:10.1093.molbev/msh214
Wiseman, R. (2016). Queen Bees & Wannabees: Helping Your Daughter Survive Cliques, Gossip,
Boys, and the New Realities of Girl World. Harmony Books, New York
Wisman, A. & Shrira, I. (2020). Sexual chemosignals: evidence that men process olfactory signals of
women’s sexual arousal. Archives of Sexual Behavior, 49, 1505-1516. doi::0.1007/s10508-019-01588-8
Yitzchak, B.M. (2020). Why do human and non-human species conceal mating? The cooperation
maintenance hypothesis. Proceedings of the Royal Society B,28720201330 doi:10.1098/rspb.2020.1330
Zadorin, A. & Rivoire, O. (2021). Sex as information processing: optimality and evolution. eprint
arXiv:2102.05459