PreprintPDF Available

Authority (I): A Promise Theoretic Formalization

Authors:
  • Researcher and Advisor at ChiTek-i
Preprints and early-stage research may not have been peer reviewed yet.

Abstract and Figures

Authority is a central concept in social systems, but it has a variety of meanings. Promise Theory offers a simple formalized understanding of authority, and its origins, as polarization within a network of collaborative interactions. This idealized approximation stands in contrast to the usual deontic view of authority in socio-philosophical literature,
Content may be subject to copyright.
Authority (I): A Promise Theoretic Formalization
Mark Burgess
April 23, 2021
Abstract
Authority is a central concept in social systems, but it has a variety of meanings. Promise
Theory offers a simple formalized understanding of authority, and its origins, as polarization within
a network of collaborative interactions. This idealized approximation stands in contrast to the usual
deontic view of authority in socio-philosophical literature, and unifies the various interpretations
with a single idea. It’s shown that the elementary meanings of authority can all be understood as a
promise, analogous to that of a ‘compass direction’ within some decision space, with which agents may
choose to align voluntarily. Authority is therefore separated from the embodiment by any particular
agency or kind of agent, and is closely related to the concept of leadership in management science.
Agents may try to impose authoritative directives onto subordinates, but imposition will generally be
ineffective, due to their autonomy or causal independence. Stable configurations may be formed from
resonant interactions that employ both semantics and dynamics to bind agents. This simple-minded
formalization serves as an foundation for later study about the dynamics of authority and derived
‘power’.
Contents
1 Introduction 2
1.1 Definitions from literature .................................... 2
1.2 Outline .............................................. 3
2 Promise Theory and voluntary cooperation 4
2.1 Notation and conventions .................................... 5
2.2 Relevance to notions of authority ................................ 5
3 Authority as the alignment of intent either by promise or by imposition 6
3.1 Intent and the ‘reference promise’ as compass for alignment ................. 7
3.2 Patterns of authority ....................................... 8
3.3 Trust in authority by mandate ................................. 10
3.4 Delegation of partial authority ................................. 11
3.5 Authority as a calibrator of standards ............................. 11
3.6 Ownership as absorption of a subordinate by a superordinate ................ 12
3.7 Direct appointment: face to face authority by invitation ................... 13
3.8 Indirect appointment: authority imposed by third parties .................. 15
4 Discussion of direct and indirect authority (timescales) 19
5 Scaling of authority 20
5.1 Collective authority ....................................... 21
5.2 Formation of hierarchy and persistence ............................. 21
5.3 Incentives and disincentives for alignment with authority ................... 22
5.4 Type blindness and mistaken mandates ............................ 22
6 Authority as emergent (dynamical) symmetry breaking 23
7 Summarial remarks 24
1
1 Introduction
The concept of authority is filled with associations and experiences from daily life. Most of us probably
think we know what it is, yet the concept is loaded with subtleties from the dynamics of its origin to
the semantics of its application. Our personal experiences with it likely distort our perception of its
underlying nature, as a natural phenomenon—perhaps even make it seem more complicated than it is,
because its effects are certainly complicated. However, in this paper, I want to show how the various
interpretations of authority boil down to some quite simple Promise Theoretic patterns—rooted in the
autonomy of agents and their capacity for voluntary cooperation. Following this approach, we can render
authority as a phenomenon of natural science rather than humanism, loosed from spurious subjectivities
and opinions about the things or persons that embody them. We might find an underlying formalization
to unify all cases.
Accomplishing this, will require some forbearance from readers with strong opinions about the special
nature of human phenomena. It will require some discipline around the separation of concerns and
idealized approximations. In this first part, the initial step will form a foundation for the larger problem
of describing the dynamics of authority on different scales, in both an informatic and socio-political
setting.
1.1 Definitions from literature
In social science, conceptual definitions inevitably begin with linguistic semantics. While words are the
initial anchor we have to normalize shared meaning, language can be both multivalued and ambiguous.
Promise Theory offers a simple way to be precise with a formal diagrammatic and symbolic concision,
but we must begin with language. A familiar search engine defines authority as:
‘The power or right to give orders, make decisions, enforce obedience’,
which places an emphasis on ‘obedience’ as a concept—i.e. a loss of autonomy. The Oxford English
Dictionary, by contrast, defines authority to be
‘The power or right to influence others or act in a specified way’,
which leaves room for influence to be voluntary, without loss of autonomy. By peering through the lens
of Promise Theory [1], this paper reconciles these meanings for authority with the ‘power’ and the ‘right’
to propagate influence—to invoke influence by command or by invitation. These two branches, in fact,
correspond loosely to the promise theoretic terms imposition of intent and the promise of cooperation,
respectively.
The literature on authority seems relatively sparse. Some recent references on the topic are helpful
in reviewing and summarizing the documented philosophical semantics [2,3]. They express authority as
a pivotal concept, but keeping to the doctrine of deontic tradition prominent in philosophy and social
discourse—claiming the existence of inexplicable yet inevitable forces of ‘obligation’ and ‘right’, rather
than finding an interpretation in terms of autonomy, voluntary determination, and agent cooperation.
This top down view suffers from the usual ‘who authorizes the authorizer?’ problem, while an autonomous
agent model avoids this by providing a natural localization of authority in ‘self’.
As pointed out by Morselli and Passini [2], the word authority comes from the Latin words auctoritas
(auctor), which derives from the verb ‘augere’ (to enhance, increase, or reinforce). Auctor expressed
the meaning of author, creator, promoter, enhancer, which suggests the laying out of a direction or a
path—an interpretation which matches well with the simple analysis in this work. Haugaard [3], on the
other hand, relates the views of philosophers, summarizing three conspicuous reasons for authority from
Weber’s analysis action types, where a sense of legitimacy (what I’ll call an expression of mandate in this
paper) is an additional key to unlocking its meaning. What stands out from Weber is the uncommon
admission of a notionally voluntary decision at play:
“Weber (1978) argued that commands of authority contain a certain minimum of voluntary submis-
sion; thus an interest (based on ulterior motives or genuine acceptance) in obedience’. This interest
can either be purely practical, related to specific pragmatic interests or from the belief in its legit-
imacy’ (Weber, 1978: 213). The belief that sustains authority is of greater theoretical interest to
Weber than crude ulterior motives as belief relates to the Verstehen sociological enterprise. Socio-
logically, permanent relations of authority are sustained by the beliefs of the grantee of authority.
The various forms that the belief in legitimacy can take define the types of authority. There are
three ideal types of authority which are based upon Weber’s characterization of different sources of
validating legitimacy (legal rationality, value rationality, traditional action and affective action).
2
Weber [4] divided legitimate authority into three types: the first type discussed by Weber is legal-
rational authority; the second type of authority, traditional authority, derives from long-established
customs, habits and social structures; the third form of authority is charismatic authority. I believe
these forms can all be accounted for using the model below.
Rational grounds (value). resting on a belief in the legality of normative rules’.
Traditional grounds (habit or inertia to change). resting upon established belief in the sanctity
of immemorial traditions’.
Charismatic grounds (trust and mesmerism). resting upon devotion to the specific and excep-
tional sanctity, heroism or exemplary character of an individual person ...” [3]
The italicized parentheses in the final three points have been added here as comments. No particular
ranking is attached to the relative priority of these. The concept of legal authority crops up, which is
a ubiquitous topic that requires explanation. In this work, I’ll show how legal convention comes about
from the scaling of authority to larger groups. Of deeper interest is the admission of the role of voluntary
cooperation, which aligns precisely with the Promise Theory viewpoint.
Haugaard relates further on Arendt’s philosophy—namely her remarks that on authority can be
viewed as an ‘opposite’ of argumentation, violence, and coercion, in the sense that authority has to be
deserved to be accepted. This underlines the primacy of autonomy again. Some of these inferences
may read more into the notion of authority than is strictly necessary to explain it structurally, and the
nuances might better be discussed in terms of the dynamics of ‘power’ in the human sense [5]. In Promise
Theory, the remarks align with the idea that one may win a ‘mandate’ as a source of authority, i.e. where
authority refers to an appointment made perhaps by group selection. Along these lines, Arendt defines
overwhelming force as non-authoritative, implying that authority has to be deserved. while others might
see it as a kind of ‘appointment by natural selection’.
In the light of these few sample remarks, it seems all the more important to understand the dynamical
origins of authority, not merely discuss its semantics, in order to progress to an understanding that can
be applied to all kinds of system whether physical, biological, social, or even informatic. By describing
such a dynamical ‘physics’ for the phenomenon of authority we may offer the kind of ‘suitably idealized
approximation’ to observed behaviours, which is the norm for natural science, while being fully compatible
with the descriptive semantics of the interactions.
It’s striking that societies seem conditioned to think of authority through the lens of power and
powerlessness, rather than as a straightforward division of roles. The former seems to belong more
naturally as part of a resulting dynamical theory. The legal stability of a state is often built on the threat
of overwhelming force to deter deviations from imposed ‘lawful’ behaviour, but the stability is only
achieved by normalization of acceptance [5]. Only later do such behaviours become norms and habits
that require only a lower level of maintenance. As a result, we perceive governments, bosses, and leaders
in a historically ‘authoritarian’ light (even the word has even come to take on a pejorative meaning, versus
‘authoritative’ which is more positive). In other usage, an authority is a source of singular expertise on
a particular subject.
There is understandably some cultural bias in these views. The idea of external force as the centre
of explanation was also the traditional view of physics, for similar reasons [6]. The natural philosophers
believed in a divine power and aligned their reasoning to be compatible with those beliefs. However, the
twentieth century upturned that belief and reversed it in favour of one based on ‘locality’ and ‘autonomy’
or ‘causal independence’. Meanwhile, Promise Theory has made a convincing case for the primacy
of voluntary cooperation as a phenomenon between autonomous agents, not one based on speculative
coercion or invisible forces but rather on the primacy of autonomy (what modern writers call ‘agency’
in a human context). Promise Theory shows that this principle is in no way unique to qualities. This
thinking has been applied to numerous scenarios now across a wide range if phenomena from information
systems to sociological processes [711]. For some, attempting to unify the different meanings will be
viewed as an anathema—for a natural scientist, the idea that a single notion can explain all cases is
attractive and powerful. I ask the forbearance of the reader in this effort.
1.2 Outline
The outline of the paper is follows:
A brief outline of Promise Theory essentials, where the starting assumption is that decisions are
the autonomous capability of every agent, without the need for external authorization. This is the
3
assumed ground state of every individual agent, and any deviations from this condition must be
explained by a voluntary choice to subordinate by aligning with an intention offered by another
agent.
A chain of dependence for authority is described and assumed to have the following form:
1. The existence of one or more discriminating observers or processes, which point to authority.
2. The explicit acceptance of the appointed authority by subordinate agents.
3. A subsequent flow of authoritative decisions by the authority, to be accepted by the subordi-
nate, and forming a relationship over time.
We discuss how the order in which these come into play may vary in different processes.
Agents are assumed more likely to use another agent’s decisions to override their own autonomous
ability to decide if they assess there to be economic value in doing so. This may change the order
in which promises are made between authority and subordinates.
Networks of promises allow for additional roles, and several ways for a mandate to be issued to
delegate decisions, including: i) directly face to face, or ii) indirectly by ‘third parties’, such as an
appointed board of directors. This is related to the scaling of autonomous behaviour by groups
that form ‘superagents’. Promise Theory shows how different networks lead to either voluntary
cooperation (by promise) or attempted inducement by imposition. Networks of interrelated agents
can achieve a kind of agency of their own (called ‘superagency’ in Promise Theory). We have to
bear in mind that such virtual agents can also play a role—what is sometimes called a ‘memeplex’,
or a collection of ideas and practices, even ceremonies, that have some inertial or confining role that
has a perceived authority of its own, e.g. ‘The System’ or ‘The State’.
Finally, scaling of authority is considered—from individual agents to collectives and even entities
which present as ‘networks of interior process’ (sometimes called memeplexes). The complexity and
incompleteness of information available to agents in networks implies that authorizations involving
third party delegation may become difficult for potential subordinates to understand and assess,
especially where networks become larger and more intricate. This may have one of two effects:
agents may lose trust in the appointed authorities, or they may assess promises incorrectly based
on limited or approximate information leading to a degradation of the fidelity of cooperation. Agents
may believe things about their own promises that are inaccurate or even erroneous. The may be of
benefit or harm to the integrity of an organization’s own promises.
A secondary aspect of scaling is the alignment of norms amongst the population of agents. Once a
norm becomes dominant, agents may perceive this as a threat to making a different choice, and thus
an imposed authority becomes harder to refute. Agents will therefore be more likely to align their
voluntary acceptance of an imposed decision with those of others for fear of negative consequences.
This is a source of stability, for better or for worse.
For reasons of limitations on space, readers are assumed to know a minimum about the motivations and
assumptions for Promise Theory (see [1] and online resources). This introduction cannot be an exhaustive
look at the dynamics of authority, in relation to power. The goal here is to provide a clear and inscrutable
definition on which to build in subsequent work.
2 Promise Theory and voluntary cooperation
Promise Theory is a model of autonomous cooperation expressed between generalized ‘agents’. Agents
can be human, animal, vegetable, mineral, or virtual (software) in nature. For some, describing human
agents on a par with non-sentient processes might be considered a kind of philosophical or even religious
heresy—as Darwin experienced—but that is indeed the goal of this work, which turns out to be powerful.
Using Promise Theory, we may explore universal aspects of authority, i.e. those which do not depend
specifically on the nature of agents, except in the sense of what they claim, embody, or represent—
whether by original ideation or by proxy. All humans lives are enveloped ‘systems’, cultural and utilitarian
(memeplexes), as well as tools that are not human, even when they are the products of human activity.
These automate and stand in place of human behaviour by proxy. Promise Theory’s focus is on how
underlying possibilities—‘intentions’ and ‘behaviours’—can be defined. These are separable and may by
4
carried or wielded any intermediary, thus forming a kind of ‘directionality’ that agents can subsequently
align with. Promise Theory offers a description of such an impartial network of processes, which may
then be scaled from an individual to mixed groups of different size.
We shall assume that the agents in a collaborative process are a priori independent or autonomous,
meaning that their behaviours are self-determined. One could say that the unadorned ‘ground state’ of
agents is one of causal independence, without bias, labels or unignorable influences. What happens to
constrain those basic behaviours then depends on the voluntary interactions within groups.
2.1 Notation and conventions
The basic tenet of autonomy is that ‘no agent can make a promise about any agent other than itself’.
Any agent can make decisions, but not every agent would be able to keep a promise without violating
this fundamental tenet. In order to authorize access (i.e. to promise permission to access a resource one
controls), the resource has to be part of (or be owned by) the promiser. Anyone can try to impose a
decision, but that would require a voluntary subordination as described in this paper: only the owner of
the resource can make a keepable promise about it.
A brief summary of notation is in order [1]. We write a promise about bfrom an agent A1to A2using
an arrow
A1
b
A2.(1)
The next point is important to those new to Promise Theory. We are no dealing with a theory of
obligations in which agents necessarily must do this or that, rather we have a theory of autonomous
choices. From the assumption of autonomy, an agent cannot make a promise on behalf of any agent other
than itself, so this arrow implies a constraint on A1, not on A2. In order for influence to pass between
them, A2must accept the promise to make use of it. We use the (+) sign for offer and the (-) sign for
acceptance by convention:
A1
+b
A2(2)
A2
b
A1.(3)
A third kind of interaction is an ‘imposition’, written with a fist-like arrow:
A1
bA2,(4)
which is understood to mean an attempt to induce A2to change its behaviour, e.g. by throwing a ball
and shouting ‘catch!’. The fundamental autonomy of the agents implies that this will only succeed if A2
has already promised to accept such impositions. So the promise of (3) is needed for this too. Impositions
are generally ineffective, and rely on a substrate of promises or voluntary cooperation to succeed. Readers
are referred to [1] for more details.
2.2 Relevance to notions of authority
A theory of essentially voluntary cooperation, Promise Theory, may sound initially contrary to the notion
of authority, but this is not the case. While the traditional view of authority is based on the notion that
we are compelled either by duty or rationality to follow orders provided by some privileged body, Promise
Theory proposes instead that such behaviour is emergent from within rather than induced from without.
Even if one takes the view that there is no circumstance in modern society in which humans are free of
the need for authorization—that we are born into circumstances beyond our control—Promise Theory
explains how that view is not representative of the fundamental nature of agents and is not irreversible.
It is probably not true of individuals’ activities in a hunter-gathering society (though these often have
intransigent belief systems on a different level), nor would it be true of the birds in a flock, the cells in
fœtus, or the cars in traffic. But, surely humans are totally different from these absurd examples!? In fact,
we can discuss all these on comparable terms, without prejudice. This leads to how we may understand
the scaling of intent—starting from an individual’s autonomous deliberations, to such pervasive power
structures as nation states, or rain forests. We expose the answer as the scaling of intent [12].
The terms and nomenclature of authority have a few related cases and meanings, worth noting for
clarity:
5
An authority may be a thing (an agent): appointed or self-declared to have the right to originate
some kind of service on behalf of others, such as decision-making, e.g. an authority on Shakespeare
or a tax authority.
A condition of authority refers to the notional right (state of cooperation), embodied by the agent
in the previous point, to exercise the aforementioned service e.g. possessing the authority to lead.
An authoritarian agent (regime or individual) is one that imposes the aforementioned service role
onto others, without seeking a mandate to legitimize the role.
To authorize is to originate a (usually written) work, or to originate the service, such as decision-
making.
An authorization is either the act (verb) or outcome (noun) of authorizing an outcome relating to
the aforementioned service.
An agent may be assessed authoritative on some matter if it is accepted as an authority by others.
All of these meanings can be accounted for comfortably within the simple-minded framework of
Promise Theory. Promise Theory tells us that agents are always free to act independently and voluntarily.
Nevertheless, Promise Theory also grants us a model in which to compare those assumptions and what
they say about the participating agents within a system. Thus, we do not begin with the assumption of
omnipresent top-down authority, where one cannot make progress without seeking permission from some
installed ruler, rather we begin from the bottom up as society must have done in an evolutionary picture.
It’s not the purpose of this article to quarrel with any of the interpretations, rather to examine how
they can be supported and explained by the dynamics of agent interactions. In fact, all of them seem
to be straightforwardly explicable in terms of alignment. Rather, what Promise Theory has taught us,
from experiences in human-technical systems, is that semantics emerge from the possible dynamics of a
system in a way that has to be consistent with those constraints. A system can only do what it can do.
An interpretation can therefore only be built on a stable behavioural knowledge, which is typically built
over multiple learning interactions. So, we now turn to the interaction dynamics to look for a deeper
foundation.
The making of decisions can be represented as a service abstraction. We view an individual or
organization as a generic agent that can promise decisions or any other process outcome as a service:
A+decision outcome
A0.(5)
The decision has to be accepted in order to be useful,
A0decision outcome
A. (6)
By the rules of Promise Theory, both these declarations are needed for autonomous intentions, expressed
as promises, to lead to a propagation of the intent behind the decisions. This simple observation is all we
need to know to build a consistent picture of authority from the bottom up. When we subscribe to such
decisions either briefly or over time, we ascribe a sense of authority to the promise of decisions, which
then typically attaches to the agent itself. This authority can be ephemeral or lasting.
3 Authority as the alignment of intent either by promise or by
imposition
Promise Theory tells us that authority over other agents is never an inherent ‘right’—i.e. something to
impose upon them. The principle of autonomy tells us that agents themselves are the only ones who
can grant that right directly. An agent’s rights extend only over what resources they consist of, or have
been promised by others. Subordinates may voluntarily signal their ‘willingness’ to accept influence, such
as commands (as in military operations) or they can promise the de facto willingness to accept others’
authority by promising a mandate for another to act in that role—a mandate in this sense is a kind of
invitation to a position of authority. This is the meaning of ‘appointment’ in Promise Theory.
6
3.1 Intent and the ‘reference promise’ as compass for alignment
A key concept we’ll refer to in the promise theoretic understanding of authority is that of a ‘direction’ of
‘alignment’, which can be thought of as the selection of a path within a space of possible decisions. This
is a simple notion of intent (yet to be parameterized and formalized). Again, this is a topic which has
been discussed in philosophy [1315]
A promise, in whatever language it’s expressed, is simply a declaration of such an intent in such a
way as to describe the distinction between a successful outcome and an unsuccessful outcome—either the
promise was kept, partially kept, or not kept. We can think of this in a fully general sense. This is what
we mean by ‘direction’ and ‘measure’ in this context. For the sake simplicity we may assume that every
agent has only a single intention in this discussion. This is simplistic, but it’s a useful formality.
The selection of a decision outcome from a body of possibility takes the form of a ‘service’ provided
by some agent, which we typically refer to as a leader or decision-maker. Again, there is no need to think
too narrowly in terms of human roles. A leader or authority could be anything, from compass pointing
North or a signpost pointing the way to Rome, to a Google search that selects best hits on a search
topic. This is the virtue of a model with universal characteristics. We may then say that an agent is
authoritative in its promise if other agents accept it as a reliable source of the reference promise, and
assess its outcomes to be of high quality (giving their trust). Notice that the exact nature of the promise
is not important. The concept of authorization is closely associated with trust [16], as well as semantics
like expertise, and quality—but the precise specification remains true whatever the nature of the promise
offered by an agent.
Assumption 1 (Authorization) Authorization is not a property of an agent, but is concerned with a
specific promise, such as a promise to lead, to make decision, to provide information, etc. We can call
this the reference promise:
source +reference offer
seeker.(7)
The reference promise implies a role, which is distinct from the agent that promises the role at any given
moment, and may outlive any single agent (e.g. the office of the president). Authority is not conferred
on the source agent unless the recipient or seeker agent accepts this promise:
source reference acceptance
seekersource.(8)
The degree of acceptance may be full or partial. This is a necessary condition for authorization. The
resulting binding leads to a degree of authorization lies in the overlap between what is offered and what is
accepted:
degree of authorization := reference offer reference acceptance.(9)
This overlap has the basic characteristics of a mathematical ‘inner product’, which may therefore be
formalized to play the role of a degree of alignment with the quasi-direction of the reference promise
within a ‘space’ of possible outcomes.
Corollary 1 (Authority) An agent which has been authorized may be called an authority. The degree
of authorization be be called the degree of authority and an individual assessment of the quality and
reliability with which the agent keeps its promised role, to be made by each and every agent.
Note, once again, for absolute clarification that an agent need not be a person, nor even an individual
of any kind. It could be a collective, a government, a system of historical and cultural practices (‘meme-
plex’), etc, that floats on top of any number of individuals human or otherwise, as a persistent source
of intentional guidance—whether in the form of books, traditions, or any other persistent memory. An
agent assessed to be an authority may be called an authoritative ‘provider’ or ‘source’ of information
(e.g. in technology the DNS master) is also the ultimate arbiter of the information. Similarly an expert
is considered authoritative if in perceived command of the information, usually by first hand experience.
Authority can be about the right to make decisions, but it’s broader than that. Authorized agents,
authorized electricians and plumbers are agents who wear a badge of membership in a certain organization
which rubber stamps their promises with a certain standard promise. The conclusion, in simple dynamic
terms, is that authorization is in the same class of phenomena as a kind of trust signal: a badge of
membership, signalling trust in a custodian of a specific resource, which in turn aligns with the need of
7
agents willing to subordinate to its promise. The reference promise may be about information, work,
procedural standards, or something else.
Promise Theory is quite useful in stripping away the fogginess of these concepts to reveal this simple
core. The unifying concept of authority is ultimately the appointment of ‘trusted’ agents. By implication,
an authoritative agent is one that promises to serve as a calibrator concerning the definition of a kind of
the reference promise. We thus may define authority more carefully and generically as follows:
Definition 1 (Authority about X)An agent Smay be called authoritative by another agent Rif it
is the source of a promise +XS,
S+XS
R, (10)
which is fully or partially accepted by other agents,
RXR
S, XSXR6=.(11)
and who in turn assess that its promised outcomes in the matter of XSare of high value
αR(XSXR)0.(12)
In other words, such an agent is a trusted source of Xto the receiving agents.
And as a corollary:
Definition 2 (Subordinates with respect to X)The agent(s) R, who promise XRin some degree,
where the promise overlaps at least partially with the offer +XShave—in so promising—voluntarily
subordinated themselves to Sin the matter of X(only).
The apparent circularity of the definition reveals that authority is not an absolute property—it’s a
relativistic concept. As we see below, it makes sense as self-consistent role within a network of promises
between a group of trusted agents. The role of trust may imply the need for extended or long term
interactions between agents, in general, wherein they assess each other’s reliability (see [16]).
3.2 Patterns of authority
The structure of authority, within a network, can be subtle, but we can unravel it straightforwardly, in
stages, using Promise Theory. The language of promises may be unfamiliar, so readers will hopefully
indulge some repetition of the essential points, in what follows, for clarity. The right to determine and
provide the reference promise may be granted within a network of complicated relationships, with the
side effect that the weary but voluntary acceptance of imposed authority could be interpreted as an
effective mandate (it masquerades as the same formal role, however illegitimate). Thus, while the ‘right’
to issue commands and directives originates entirely autonomously in every agent, any such promise or
imposition must ultimately accepted by the agents who would become subordinates to the authoritative
source. There are plenty of avenues for deception, incentive, disincentive, etc to shape the outcome.
However, before getting into such complexities, it’s important to start, in the traditions of science, by
sketching out the notions with suitably idealized approximations and simplifications that reveal the
essence of what’s going on.
The interpretations of authority, as power or right, may be sketched as follows:
Imposition: an authority attempts to impose its influence on a subordinate:
Authority +influence Subordinate.(13)
Because the imposee is an autonomous agent, it needs to accept the uninvited imposition to make
it effective:
Subordinate influence
Authority.(14)
Without this explicit acceptance, an imposition (any attempt to induce cooperation uninvited in
another agent) is powerless in the face of their autonomy.
In more complex scenarios, while direct imposition is ineffective, agents could be ‘tricked’ into
acceptance of them (see section 5). If subordinates do not accept the imposition, one can still
8
imagine that the imposer could assert its authority by force. For instance, if the imposer could
conquer, overwhelm and subsume the subordinate, then the agent would become a part of it, and
autonomy would then rule over it too. By absorbing the agent within a larger superagent boundary,
its autonomy is lost as far as exterior agents are concerned.
Promise: the promise of authority can be accepted purely on a voluntary basis, without obligation,
especially where the authoritative candidate has been volunteered a mandate Mby a number of
willing subordinates, to issue its commands or make decisions X:
Subordinate +M
Authority (15)
Authority M
Subordinate (16)
Authority +X|M
Subordinate (17)
Subordinate X
Authority.(18)
The unconditional promise of +Mis the promise theoretic understanding of an invitation by the
subordinate [1]. In this way, authority is a symbiotic relationship. Followers promise their support,
the authority accepts that and uses it as a basis for making singular decisions conditionally on
the mandate, which are then accepted by the followers. This is part of the basis structure used in
democracy. The mandate Mmay be interpreted as the ‘right’ or permission to lead [1].
The implications of these simple patterns are profound: unless a boss or manager’s commands can be
upheld by overwhelming brute force, or perhaps by threat of later consequences (e.g. suspending wages),
then he or she or their office has to seek this cooperative mandate to play its role as manager. If the
manager does not actually control the policy about wages, then it does not have that leverage, and needs
to maintain support by mutual cooperation. A manager or authority is therefore a role by appointment.
The manager and subjects are in fact coupled in a symbiotic state of mutual subordination, rather than a
unidirectional hierarchy of subordination. We can summarize these observations in two points as follows:
Definition 3 (Implicitly appointed authority) An agent A, which is in receipt of one or more
promises to subordinate themselves from agents {S}, by accepting a reference promise X, given a mandate
M:
A+X
→ {S}(19)
{S}X
A. (20)
The common promise of Xforms the appointment to the position of manager or boss. This appointment
to take on the capability of deciding Pis what makes the manager an ‘authority’. The ‘right to manage’
is the promise to accept P.
In this most basic form of authority, agents accept a direction +Xan agent, effectively appointing it to
the role of leader, or trusted authority. Although this simplest form of alignment is not precisely what we
typically consider to be authority in a society, it’s a pattern which is so widespread that the implications
are wide, deep, and worthy of consideration by anyone: simply accepting goods or services from some
agent gives that agent temporary authority to define their content. Having made this observation, we
can construct a more recognizable dynamic for selection of a leadership role.
Definition 4 (Explicitly appointed authority (by invitation)) An agent A, which is in receipt of
one or more promises to subordinate themselves from agents {S}, by accepting a reference promise X,
given a mandate M:
{S}+M
A(21)
AM
→ {S}(22)
A+X|M
→ {S}(23)
{S}X
A. (24)
The common promise of Xforms the appointment to the position of manager or boss. This appointment
to take on the capability of deciding Pis what makes the manager an ‘authority’. The ‘right to manage’
is the promise to accept P.
9
Notice that, in the case where agents are interacting directly ‘face to face’ and vote for their leader
by promising +M, the acceptance of a mandate from the subordinates themselves has the implication
that the appointed agent Ais also subordinate to the group $S}, by a different promise, leading to a
symbiotic state of mutually self-mandated authority. The direct interaction is the only case where this is
true.
The broader mechanisms by which the foregoing promise exchanges arise need not be speculated on
here. We treat them in the mathematical spirit of ‘necessary and sufficient conditions’ for direct authority.
Perhaps, in general, a coherent balanced symbiosis might have to be seeded by the imposition of force in
order to stabilize a behaviour into a habit initially, which has interesting implications for statecraft and
popular moral positions on leadership. This is a matter for empirical studies to reveal and confirm or
refute this theoretical picture.
3.3 Trust in authority by mandate
From the patterns above, we find two main cases to discuss, concerning the appointment of authority.
Starting from the assumption of agent autonomy, it follows that agents never cede control of their decisions
or behaviour under any circumstances. This leaves only two choices by which to exert authority over
them:
Direct appointment as in section 3.7: To undertake an asymmetric relationship voluntarily in which
one is offered a mandate to be dominant over some aspects of behaviour X, or,
Indirect appointment as in section 3.8: For one party to overwhelm the other so that it becomes
only a part of a larger agent with autonomy.
In the latter case, one agent can effectively gobble up another (as in a corporate takeover) so that its
own autonomy becomes an insignificant part of the behaviour of the conquering agent, i.e. its underlying
autonomy is masked by other agents. This typically happens at scale within a collective, where the
interior details need further explanation. We can sketch these scenarios roughly as in figure 1.
A
conqueror
lead
+mandate
cheer
+service | mandate
(b)
(a)
Figure 1: Two approaches to the power to influence. In (a) agents align voluntarily with a service. The
appointment of the source of the service is by the offer of a mandate or tenure as a voluntary act. This leads to a
symbiosis of mutual value. In (b), agents are conquered or subsumed by another superagent which then owns the
boundary for outward expression around them. If there is any deviation of what the subordinate and conqueror
voluntarily promise, the subordinate’s view may be shielded or overridden by overwhelming force.
The latter act of overwhelming another agent in order to take ownership is, in fact, a simplified
rendition of a more complication process based on the former exchange of promises [9]. Using Promise
Theory, we can unpick these issues to any level of detail, but no further details will be give here. The
simple conclusion is that, ultimately, all authority can be seen to arise by some form of ‘voluntary’
subordination, motivated by value judgements of the agents concerned. Herein lies a connection to two
person (non)-cooperative Game Theory [17,18], in which the initial symmetry between agents is broken
by ‘winning’.
10
3.4 Delegation of partial authority
Developing the notion of conditionality further, we can extend the semantics in a simple way to include
partial authority delegated by a manager—say to middle managers or delegates D, by conditionally
promising to accept a restricted mandate M(XD) to follow their decisions on a subset XDX.
A+M(XDX)
D(25)
D+M(XDX)
A. (26)
Technically, this is a basic application of the matroid calibration pattern from [1]. The managers now
have a mandate to decide matters XXD:
D+XD|M(XD)
S, (27)
We are now in the realm of a new kind of mandate, which is not face to face between authority and
subordinates, but involves a third party. There are further implications here for the autonomy of the
agents, which we can expand on in 3.8.
There are many examples in systems where one agent or process grants the authority to act as a proxy
on behalf of another agent involves intermediate agents. This introduces new issues (see the intermediate
agent law in [1]). Intermediates, or ‘middle-men’, lead to great uncertainty, because as autonomous agents
themselves they may not align their intentions with direct owner.
Example 1 (Power of attorney) Granting someone to act on behalf of oneself.
Example 2 (Payment Authorization and Proxy Resource Authorizations) Banks can delegate
access to accounts by giving a mandate to a particular credit card or payment method to represent that
account, in online transactions. This is an indirect authorization. A different piece of plastic, or a note
with the account number details might not be authorized.
Authorization of any shared resource (e.g. access to a building) involves either a direct promise of
access rights by the owner of the resource, or appointing a decision maker to approve access on its behalf.
The decision maker has to own or control the resource at least by proxy, else it ‘doesn’t have the authority’.
So actually, authority to decide is a form of ownership, or boundary management.
Example 3 (Authorized Delivery Agent) The end to end delivery problem [1] is an example of this.
A retailer promises its goods via a third party delivery agent, such as the postal service. The delivery
agent is authorized to deliver packages on behalf of the retailer and the customer by a series of promises,
but how do we know that the delivery agent will keep its promises exactly as the retailer and the customer
intend? Of course, we don’t know—indeed, no agent knows this with certainty. The agents use trust to
seal their commitment to the promises.
3.5 Authority as a calibrator of standards
When a source is said to be authoritative, it has an implicit power (used heuristically here, in the absence
of a proper definition), in the sense that it will often be accepted as the final word on the matter of
X, whatever that is. It may be prioritized over other alternative sources. This power is thus over the
subordinates who accept its reference promise of X(whatever that might be). The appointed role does
not make the agent unique, as other authorities may have a different version of what appears to be the
same promise, and may have been appointed by other agents. So the appointment of authority may have
a fracturing effect causing populations of subordinates to cleave into different subsets.
Corollary 2 (Calibration) The subordinates, as recipients of an authoritative promise, can always
assesses whether two promises are equivalent and whether the outcomes between different authorities are
compatible or not. An authority is thus a calibrating agent, or the arbiter of a standard, in the language
of [1].
Example 4 (Judges and courts) Judges are indirectly appointed authorities who calibrate the inter-
pretation of the law, comparing the interpretations of events by parties for prosecution and defence. A
single judge can be trivially authoritative. A panel of judges may still disagree about its interpretation.
Each judge is an authority, and the panel of judges can form its own authority as a ‘supreme’ superagent
whose collective assessments are combined by from their individual assessments.
11
3.6 Ownership as absorption of a subordinate by a superordinate
Ownership is related to the notion of boundaries and what they mean for agents’ autonomy. By taking
ownership of an agent that can be owned, the owner effectively envelops and overwhelms the other, and
it becomes part of an extended superagent that contains the property of the owner. This process has
been described in more detail in the context of Promise Theory and voluntary cooperation in [9]. It’s
not the intention to repeat that discussion here, only to point out the relevance of boundaries to what
resources an agent can make promises about.
Ownership plays a role in authority because the owner of a resource is assumed to ‘speak for’, i.e.
to literally or figuratively control it. This means that agents owned by an agent are effectively a part
of it, and the agent can make promises on behalf of those and only those things it contains and owns.
The use of quotes seems necessary to emphasize that we should not take words too literally in whatever
direct meanings the reader would normally understand. Rather, be aware that concepts of being a part
of may be physical or virtual, especially in the modern world of information. We understand a person
to be in control of their possessions, at least on some level, if only to speak with some authority on their
behalf—yet, they may not have direct literal control over a house or a business as if it were a part of their
bodies. These details can simply be subsumed into the notion of a promise as an expression of intent
rather than absolute guaranteed outcome.
super sub
sub
super
sub
super
sub
super
sub
super
sub
super
+X
−X ?
(d)
+X
+X
+X +X
+X
+X
+X | def(X)
−def(X)
+def(X)
(c)
(b)
(a)
Figure 2: Alignment of intent, with the subordination of some agents, can take several forms, all expressible in
Promise Theory by means of promises and impositions. These illustrations capture the subtle distinctions. In
(a), an agent attempts to impose its service onto a subordinate, which may or may not promise to accept the
imposition. In (b), the two agents are voluntarily and accidentally aligned in their promises and therefore appear
indistinguishable in their behaviours. In (c), one agent (the superordinate) absorbs the subordinate and speaks
in its behalf, effectively imposing its behaviour onto the subordinate ad hoc. Note that, Promise Theory tells us
not to think of this absorption as being necessarily physical—a company can take over another without physically
enveloping its headquarters. Finally, in (d), two agents join into a single molecular configuration voluntarily. The
superordinate promises its definition of some behaviour Xand this is accepted and parroted by the subordinate
voluntarily.
The conquest of an agent can be understood and interpreted in several forms, all expressible in
Promise Theory by means of promises and impositions (see figure 2). Once conquered, an agent is
effectively owned, hence the relationship between these terms. All of these must (in Promise Theory)
12
amount to a voluntary (self-authorized) promise by an agent to align itself with an outside direction.
3.7 Direct appointment: face to face authority by invitation
The basic conception of authority arises in interactions such as the two person game [17,18]. It is a direct
face to face configuration of agent promises, whose aim is to engineer a stable on-going interaction between
two kinds of agent, both of whom assess beneficial value from the interaction. The result is an equilibrium
configuration in which the symmetry between the agents is broken by a separation of concerns. One party
effectively subordinates itself to the other with respect to one role, while the other party subordinates to
the former in a different sense. We can call the two agent roles leader and subordinate. The subordinate
will be the agent which makes a promise Lto accept a service +Lfrom an agent in the role of leader.
The appointment of the leader is equivalent to the promise of a mandate. The is an act of invitation, as
described in [1,19]. We can summarize this direct ‘face-to-face’ configuration in words before formalizing
in promises:
1. A group of voluntary subordinates ASinvites the service +Xof a leader agent or body AL, effec-
tively promising it a mandate Mto lead the group. The details of the mandate need not be defined
in detail, and could be quite variable—written in different languages, with different phrasing etc.
What matters is only whether the mandate is accepted in the spirit in which it was intended, as
this is what will lead to alignment with Xand a stable binding.
2. If ALaccepts this invitation M, it then promises to lead (as a kind of service offering), based on
this (which we write L|M). Again, the precise nature of what is promised is not important; what
matters is whether the promise is accepted in the mutual interaction and leads to a stable separation
of roles and a cohesive binding.
3. Thus, the final step is the ASto accept the offer of leadership as promised.
Notice how all promises are made voluntarily, and the suggestion of a mandate is in no way an obligation
that binds the leader to make a particular promise. The mandate and the offer of leadership based on
the mandate are still independent and autonomous choices.
We can write the picture more formally in Promise Theory, in terms of two generic agents ALand
ASrepresenting a leader role and a subordinate role [1]. We needn’t make any assumptions about the
interior structure of these agents, e.g. are they individuals or groups working together. All that matters
is the promises made at the boundaries of the agents.
The agents Ai={AL, AS}are initially symmetrical, and break their symmetry (autonomously or
voluntarily) when ASappoints ALto a special role, such as in an election or job assignment, by promising
a mandate Mto play that role:
π(+)
M:AS
+M
AL.(28)
By making this promise, the symmetry between the two agent roles has already been broken to any
observer (in scope) to whom the promise is observable. If ALaccepts this promised appointment,
π()
M:AL
M
AS,(29)
then there is now an axial symmetry or cephalization of the agents with a head ALand tail AS. Each
agent can already assess the value of these promises to itself:
αSπ(+)
M=vS(π(+)
M) (30)
αSπ()
M=vS(π()
M) (31)
αLπ(+)
M=vS(π(+)
M) (32)
αSπ()
M=vS(π()
M),(33)
where αA(π) is the assessment, by agent Aof the promise π, in the usual way [1]. Each agent makes
its own relative assessment, using its own units of measurement or criteria. They may or may not be
based on real numbers or a discrete menu of outcomes. When matters to the collaboration is whether
the agents make an assessment which leads to the continuation or stability of the promise binding.
13
The leader agent now makes a conditional promise to deliver its service conditional on the mandate,
which is the only acceptable response to this offer of the mandate π(+)
Mto AS:
π(+)
L:AL
+L|M
AS.(34)
Notice the conditional notation, represented by the vertical bar: a promise of leadership L‘if I am in
possession of and have accepted a kept promise of’ M. The recipients must similarly accept this offer of
‘leadership’ Lto complete the binding.
π()
L:AS
L
AL.(35)
Although we call the promise L‘leadership’, it could be any service provided by AL. The structure of
the pattern will always allow it to be identified as a form of leadership. This tells us that leadership may
not be explicit, with uniforms and trappings of power, but something more subtle which is based entirely
on information asymmetry.
ASAL
+M
ASAL
+M
−M
ASAL
+M
−M
+L | M
ASAL
+M
−M
+L | M
−L
TAIL HEAD
(iii)
(iv)
(ii)
(i)
Figure 3: Basic authorization, step-by-step, as a symmetry breaking phenomenon in timelike stages. One set of
agents subordinates themselves to another by appointing a leader. Appointment occurs by promising a mandate
for conditional authority to lead (appointing ‘decision rights’), which ‘authorizes’ (i) a leadership role. Assuming
the mandate is accepted (ii), the recipient of the mandate can conditionally promise leadership L|M(iii). If that
promise is accepted, then the binding is complete (iv), and the pair of roles orients with a head and a tail in some
semantic interpretation. The sustainability of this interaction configuration depends on the assessment of value
over a timescale. Notice that, in this version, it’s ALthat we associate with possession of ‘authority’.
14
The agents can, once again, assess these new promises
αSπ(+)
L=vS(π(+)
L) (36)
αSπ()
L=vS(π()
L) (37)
αLπ(+)
L=vS(π(+)
L) (38)
αSπ()
L=vS(π()
L),(39)
and if the sum of these, for each agent, passes a certain acceptable threshold (measured in its own units),
then the agents will continue to keep their promises.
vS(π(+)
M) + vS(π()
M) + vS(π(+)
L) + vS(π()
L)VS(40)
vL(π(+)
M) + vL(π()
M) + vL(π(+)
L) + vL(π()
L)VL.(41)
Notice that the assessment of value, a process undertaken by an agent, implies the existence of a timescale
for sampling and interaction of events (messages or information) that can be associated with observation
of promise keeping. The language of those messages need not be decided here. The cumulative ‘payoff’
from these individual valuations ultimately determines the course of the interaction as a two-person
game [1], without needing to assume any universal scheme of value. Valuations are entirely private
assessments.
Notice also that we’re assuming that the important quantity is the sum of the assessments, as one
would consider in iterative Game Theory, where payoffs are real-valued quantities, accumulated over
many plays or ‘moves’, but even this is not really necessary. Qualitative assessments work just as well.
If each of the promise assessments passes some simple threshold of classification as ‘valuable’ that may
be sufficient to settle the outcome, e.g. as a tuple:
vS(π(+)
M), vS(π()
M), vS(π(+)
L), vS(π()
L)(a, b, c, d).(42)
for some constants a, b, c, d on the interior of AS.
We interpret this basic face to face scenario as the basis of authorization. In practice, it’s a symmetry
breaking of roles (see section 6). Time plays a role in the sense of partial ordering of the agents in which of
them offers their side of the binding promises first, and it plays an only going role as a scale for sampling
one another’s outcomes to assess (e.g. verify or validate) the truth of the compliance with the promises
made. The initial assessment of value, associated with promise keeping. is a prototype for a notion of
trust between agents [16]. If trust is favourable then the agents will continue to make these promises and
the game will iterative in a stable manner, as predicted by [20,21].
There is no imposition and no force involved between the agents that compels them to accede to a
separation of roles. The principle of autonomy of agents is upheld. Each agent voluntary promises to
adopt a certain role, even though this may be interpreted as a subordination of one by the other. The
reason is that the leadership agent ALis assessed to offer value in this role, which presumably exceeds
what of the uncooperative symmetrical state. This is the phenomenon of specialization. Moreover, since
the ‘decisions’ to accept these offered promises are made entirely autonomously by each side, we can
claim that the promise of specialization leads to an emergent symmetry breaking (a cephalization or the
organism in the biological sense) [12,22,23].
To summarize, agents that are able to promise asymmetric qualities to one another, with offer and
acceptance affinities can separate into leader and subordinate. This leads to a direction which is the
basis of a hierarchy. However, the concept of authorization here is in fact mutual. Without the initial
mandate, the leader is not empowered to promise its leadership service, and the subordinates will not
accept it. Clearly this resembles the nature of voting in a kind of democratic process; however, we should
be careful in applying such a simple model. As we’ll see below, this simple mutuality does not easily
survive the scaling of the process through indirection.
3.8 Indirect appointment: authority imposed by third parties
The direct face to face scenario above reveals that authority begins as a form of symbiosis. This status
as a mutually beneficial interaction becomes harder to maintain as the number of agents grows, and
multiple roles emerge. This balanced hierarchy is not the form of authority that we are most familiar
15
with in society; that’s because modern societies have layers of sophistication based on separations into
many roles, which place value on different promises and make their independent assessments. So we need
to extend the pattern of authority by mandate include further asymmetries.
ASALAD
TAIL
+L | M
+M
HEAD
Figure 4: A common case in business and elsewhere is that leaders (e.g. CEO) are appointed by a third party,
such as the board of directors of a company rather than the agents who are the recipients of the services they
provide. Unlike the previous case of figure 3, it’s now the third party promiser ADof the mandate whom we
associate with the having of authority or decision rights concerning the appointment of a leader, and the ALwho
has decision rights over AS. So we have a chain of authority, or a hierarchy.
Consider the scenario in figure 4. Here, the mandate for authority is no longer provided by the
subordinate recipient ASof the leadership service L, but by a third party AD, which we could interpret
as a higher level ‘director’. This is a common scenario in larger firms, for example, where a board of
directors appoints a leader (giving their mandate to lead) and the leader then promises (or even imposes)
their decisions based on this mandate to a different agent AS, who has now offered no mandate for
providing the service.
If we, once again, associate subordination with the voluntary act of accepting a service (leadership)
L. The leader agent ALis now also subordinate to the director AD, and the ASare subordinate to AL,
which suggests that there might be an implicit subordination of ASto ADtoo, by transitivity. However,
promises are not generally transitive, and (as yet) no direct promise has been made between ADand AS,
so the situation lacks the necessary information to make that assessments.
Let’s once again summarize in words before attaching symbols to the interactions.
1. The director offers a mandate for an agent to lead a group of (now possibly involuntary) subor-
dinates, thus appointing a leader. The status of the subordinates is different now, because the
group has not explicitly signalled its invitation to be led. The decision to appoint a leader is a kind
of imposition onto the subordinates. It’s not quite making a promise on behalf of another agent,
so the tenets of autonomous promising are not violated, but the presence of the intermediary AL
means that the invitation to lead is not made by the potential recipients of that leadership, so the
authority of the appointment is now in question.
2. Assuming that the leader accepts the mandate of the director, it promises both the director and
the now ‘appointed subordinates’ its offer of leadership according to that mandate. Both of these
have to accept that promise in order to create a influential binding. The value of the binding
can be assessed by each. Presumably the director sees the value of this promise, having made
the invitation, and would therefore accept—but the value to the subordinates is unclear. Their
acceptance is less clear. It must be taken on its own merits—with a higher degree of ad hoc trust,
as the subordinates have not signalled their wishes and thus the alignment of the leadership with
their wishes is no longer clear by design. It may or may not align with their wishes, and thus the
subordinates may or may not accept the leadership.
3. The subordinates may therefore accept or not.
The situation is now unclear. We can ask ‘on what authority does the director appoint the leader on
behalf of others?’. A common and perhaps most meaningful answer is that the director is the de facto
‘owner’ of the organization, in total, and therefore controls them without question. This is a common
and convenient legal fiction that builds on a litany of conventional promises. From the viewpoint of
Promise Theory, it needs to be unravelled. For machinery or any other non-human agents, ownership
is uncontroversial; however, the idea that humans can be fully owned is no longer widely accepted in
the modern world. For example, this may mean the subordinates have already promised to be a part of
the organization, in certain roles, by signing a contract (voluntarily). More usually, we consider that the
owner of the organization can ‘own’ a work processes, even a slice of an agent’s time, but not the human
agents themselves—but that is only a convention.
16
Let’s examine the necessary and sufficient conditions to sustain a stable configuration of agents in the
Promise Theory formulation.
ASALAD
TAIL −L
−M
+L | M
+M
−M
HEAD
Figure 5: Full acceptance of a third party authorization mandate. Unlike the previous case of figure 3, it’s
now the giver of the mandate whom we associate with the having of authority or decision rights concerning the
appointment of a leader.
In the figure, all the promises go in the same direction. However, they have neither been accepted
nor do they have any causal implications until accepted. If we add acceptance promises, ad hoc, then
according to the laws of assisted promising, we have (see figure 5):
AD
+M
AL(43)
AD
M
AL(44)
AL
+L|M
AS(45)
AL
M
AS(46)
AS
L
AL.(47)
Notice that (because the source of +Mis now dissociated from AS,ALhas to promise ASexplicitly that
it has acquired and accepted such a promise to validate its conditional promise).
The natural question to ask now is why would ASaccept the promise of leadership from ALwithout
having chosen the agent itself, or mandated its promise of L? The simple answer has to be that ASstill
assesses a positive value to accepting this state of affairs. However, the scenario is now different because
ASno longer has a veto on that role in the same way, by being able to withdraw its mandate. At best
is can refuse to accept the promise by revoking its acceptance L.
The difference now is that AShad no say in the selection of AL. That may or may not be a problem.
AScan still vote with its feet, in a sense, and not accept AL’s promises. As long as it does accept
(see (47)), then it has effectively selected AL. So all that remains to discuss is the stability of that
configuration. What if ASfails to assess a positive value from the service +L|M?
Indirection adds complications. A priori, ASmay not know about the agent ADand its role, but it
can infer that such an agent exists (in principle) by the promise (46) which indicates that ALreceived
its conditional mandate from a third party. If the mandate had come from ALdirectly, it would have
promised +Mas well as +L|M, effectively cancelling the reference to M. The fact that it promises
Moffers distinct information about indirection. By exposing this information to AS,ASmay form an
assessment of that information, and thus its sampling and assessment, followed by interior decisions to
continue accepting the promise binding, involves sufficient information to revoke the acceptance based on
whatever reasoning is implied by this assessment. If the agents are subatomic particles, we assume the
reasoning is rather mechanical; if the agents are humans the reasoning could be complex.
The position of ADin this new hierarchy seems ad hoc, in the current configuration. It may be
supported by happenstance or by assessment of functional benefit, but this is not the state of affairs in
organizations of agents on a more sophisticated level. For instance, in a firm ADrepresents the owner
of the firm. The concept of ownership does not exist for primitive collaborations, but it does exist in
commerce. We can cement that authority, representing ownership as a right to decide by adding more
promises—promises that we perhaps leave implicit on a day to day basis, but which form the foundation
of legal ownership and acceptance of that system.
The implications of ownership are not defined clearly in general, but may be considerable. If we
expand the ownership promise (figure 7) to be a promise that offers membership with associated benefits,
subject to a set of conditions, then the conditions are now used as a form of incentive or coercion.
Naturally, a potential employee does not have to accept—they can walk away. However, this is a
clear attempt to induce a promise, with a potential reward for doing so. That makes an imposition [1]
masquerading as a bundle of promises—one might even say that involves deception, though the practice
17
ASAD
AL
AL
AS
AD
TAIL −L
−M
+L | M
+M
−M
HEAD
+own
+own
−own
−own
TAIL HEAD
−own
+own
+own
−own
Figure 6: Adding the concept of authority to give the mandate by prior ownership of the collaboration. In the
lower figure we can suppress the other internal promises and focus on the main alignment of the collaboration,
induced by the promises called ‘ownership’.
of imposing such restrictions is so widespread as to be almost common knowledge. We should be careful
not to assume that common practice implies inevitability. There are many alternatives to this practice.
In spite of convention, humans may be deceived by contractual terms, which persuade unsophisticated
human workers into believing that they have been bought and must accept the appointed leader out of
a sense of obligation (i.e. a belief that they have promised this). This is a form of systemic authority,
in which the meta authority of the system or ‘memeplex’ overwhelms or subordinates by habit. More
emancipated agents, however, might take a different view. Ultimately, autonomous agents will always
assess these relationships individually. The concept of ownership is complex in the modern world, and
we won’t delve into the extensive infrastructure of promises it depends on here. Suffice it to say that the
owner of an ownable thing is taken to control it in a meaningful sense.
Example 5 (Ownership and human rights) The difference here is that a director (presumed owner)
owns the rights to the organization resources, and acts as the voice of the entire superagent. In the case
of the brain speaking for a whole animal, this is more straightforward. We tend to get confused when
individual wants and desires—indeed ‘human rights’ granted by even greater agents of collective society’
that may be considered to override local considerations. The idea that human rights are intrinsic to all
humans is mere rhetoric, however desirable. I’ll return to this is in section 5.
Example 6 (Democratic governance) When an owner or director imposes itself a priori, it has its
autonomous power to control (see [9]). The situation can be different in the case of indirect authoriza-
tion, if the ‘owner’ or director were in fact invited into the role i.e. in possession of a voted mandate
to take on the appointed role to decide. This would cement a cohesive mandate around the otherwise
separated agents (see figure 6) for the entire collaboration from director, through intermediate leader to
subordinates. That is the approximate state of affairs in so-called democratic governance, for example.
In that case, a mandate for top level authority may be won over an extended ‘face to face’ relationship
between subordinates and director (e.g. president figurehead or governing party campaigning directly to
its ‘base’ of voters, thus bypassing the delegated middle layer(s)).
The indirection described in this section proves important as a way of scaling delegation across a
coherent organization, but it’s a non-trivial matter. The more layers of indirection encountered in a
chain of this kind, the more likely the support for accepting and keeping the binding promises is fragile
and will fail to cohere. An intermediate agent is an obvious fracture point.
Notice that, if ASaccepts the bundle of promises called ‘own’, then embedded within these is an
authorization pattern, which provides the mandate to ADto make decisions on behalf of AS, and which
18
ASAD
AL
TAIL −L
−M
+L | M
+M
−M
HEAD
+own
−own
= −membership, +conditions
+own
−own
= membership | conditions, −conditions
Figure 7: Promising another agent membership subject to conditions is one way to say of claiming a form of
limited ownership over that agent. Here AHpromises (+) that it is the owner of ASand AL, and the agents accept
this (-). In these imposed conditions is the expectation that ASpromise to give its mandate for authority to the
agent appointed by AD. Since this was not an autonomous choice, there is a concealed imposition here. However,
impositions are known to be ineffective in general. When agents don’t give a mandate freely, the acceptance of
authority is indirect and the value associated with it may be considerably reduced.
may therefore include decisions about the choice of AL:
AS
+M=conditions
AD(48)
AD
+L=membership|M=conditions
AS,(49)
as well as the matching acceptance promises. In other words, the acceptance of the imposition to promise
the conditions of membership acts as a mandate to grant decision-making power to the director role
through membership. The use of a conditional is interesting because it allows ADto ‘trick’ ASinto
promising to give a mandate for authority to AL, by burying intentions in the fine-print. However, this is
not a direct promise to AL, so there is only a second order ‘promise to make another promise to someone
else’ which is implicit in the relationship. This might be enough to induce the cooperation, but now the
direct value of doing so is less obvious because the indirectness could make the assessment of whether
that promise is kept less frequent and less rigorous. There is effectively a trust in a collaborative outcome,
perhaps with a promise of penalties, etc.
The offer of employment to ASand ALby ADcould include a number of conditions (imposed, since
they were not invited or requested). Acceptance of this bundle of promises could therefore be considered
as a mandate to appoint a leader. Since the promise is to AD, the acceptance of ownership can’t include
acceptance of promises made by AL, but it would include acceptance of the decisions of AD, which could
include delegation of leadership to ALimplicitly.
In practice, these delegations are not promised explicitly, only implicitly in a model of hierarchy, which
is institutionalized as a norm to become ‘organizational culture’. It’s sometimes referred to as learned
helplessness [19].
4 Discussion of direct and indirect authority (timescales)
It’s useful to compare two other scenarios of these types with slightly different structure: i) the election
of a government by a vote (where the mandate to lead the voters is given by the vote) and ii) the
appointment of a board of directors ADby shareholders Sof a company (where the shareholder voters
are not the employees, and their mandate is once again given the a board of directors who give the
mandate to a leader to lead). There are multiple levels of indirection in these chains of authorization,
from face to face symbiosis to multiple levels of indirection (see figure 8).
A dynamical issue, which we haven’t mentioned thus far, is that of timescales: the timescales of the
promise-keeping processes are very different in different organizational structures. This affects assessments
of promise-keeping as well as trust. A company might be a more agile organization than a government
body, which makes decisions on a timescale of days or weeks, whereas a government makes decisions on a
timescale of months and years. The assessment of outcomes, the reevaluation of trust, and the blindness
to promise specifics all become coarser and less reliable with increased time—principally because the
19
timescale of human life-processes is fixed. Humans are unable to adapt to perceive processes on shorter
or longer timescales without technological assistance.
ALshareholdersAD
AL
workers
voters
(a)
(b)
+M
−M
−D
+D | M+L | D
X?
+M
+L | M
Figure 8: Comparing two common chains of authorization with only the main promises drawn. In (a) a govern-
ment election where the voters are the ones delegating authority to promise a number of laws as a trusted service,
which voters promise to accept. This is an example of the case in section 3.7, so in this idealized representation
a government has the direct mandate of the people to lead. Next, in (b) a share company where shareholders
select a board of directors who in turn select a leader (CEO), who is delegated the authority to make decisions
for the company. The principal difference between these is that i) is a closed loop, whereas ii) is an open chain
of imposition in which shareholders make no promises directly to workers. This is what we often refer to as
‘authoritarian’ governance.
So, if we compare two well known chains of authorization: the election of a government, and a
shareholder vote, we see a few differences. In a government election, the voters are the ones delegating
authority to promise a number of laws as a trusted service, which voters promise to accept. This is an
example of the case in section 3.7, so in this idealized representation a government has the direct mandate
of the people to lead. In a share company, shareholders select a board of directors who in turn select a
leader (CEO), who is delegated the authority to make decisions for the company. The principal difference
between these is that i) is a closed loop, whereas ii) is an open chain of imposition in which shareholders
make no promises directly to workers. This is what we often refer to as ‘authoritarian’ governance. In
society, most workers experience the latter kind of governance on a daily basis, even when they participate
in the former election process, because the effects of their voting act only on a very slow timescale.
Shareholders are self-appointed, when they are offered a mandate to purchase shares in a company.
They require no further authorization to make their decisions. Nevertheless, we begin to see the potential
complexity of the interactions: a company issues shares, voluntarily subordinating itself to a mixture of
authoritative agents who become partial owners. They do this in return for money to sustain the company,
generating a small ecosystem.
A representation of ownership in terms of voluntary cooperation might feel unfamiliar, as legal matters
are typically represented as legal matters, i.e. deontic impositions by the power of the state onto its
subjects. In reality, the situation is that the powerful state is only a background which documents norms
and conventions associated with voluntary behaviours.
5 Scaling of authority
In physics, scaling is about how properties change or are preserved as the key sizes of system variables
change. For example, a rectangle cannot be the same shape if we change only the length of one side;
to preserve the shape, we have to scale width and height in proportion. So, shape has a specific scaling
law based on the ratio of sides (like a television format 4:3 or 16:9). Similarly, there are different ways
in which the scaling from a small number of agents to large numbers affects the derived properties of
a collection of agents. Promise Theory allows us to formalize these notions from the details of promise
bodies X. Promise Theory extends the notion of scaling to include semantics— not only quantitative
but also qualitative measures. For example a promise might or might not depend on the nature of the
agents, i.e. whether agents are human, machine, animal, vegetable, mineral, etc. There are many issues
to tackle around scaling. Let’s sketch just a few suggestive cases.
20
5.1 Collective authority
When agents come together to behave as a single superagent (see figure 9), the behaviour of individual
agents may be fully or only partially aligned, yet their dominant behaviour can still characterize the
collective. On the other hand it may not—the agent could split into two.
An example of a superagent might be a company, with all of its bylaws and traditions, or a country with
cultural and legal norms, but also active services that corral members into certain behaviours implicitly.
Member agents might have to actively abstain from these default rails in order to reject their promises.
Nevertheless, they can always do so one way or another.
In a collective, what can begin with a clear expression of a promise may evolve into a distribution
of promises, qualitatively or quantitatively different—some of which may be more aligned than others.
There is no need to consider a collection of agents to be a single cohesive swarm (or mob) aligned on all
issues: a more reasonable picture is that a collection of agents that fall into different groups on different
issues. The fact that some dominate in number might not be the decisive measure of their impact,
because the latter depends not only on what is offered, but also how it is received. The seed of authority
behind the ‘dominant’ directions could be different for each distinct promise type. This is consistent with
the modern idea of leadership being a distributed quality based on expertise in teams and organizations,
rather than being a single appointment for all issues in a single entity. It’s how we organize specialist
bodies within a society, like health organizations, economic forums, environmental groups, etc, though
it’s still less common in smaller groups perhaps due to resource constraints.
owner
possessions
virtual
superagent
+X
Figure 9: An agent that takes possession of things may (for some purposes) regard those things as part of its
interior resources. Thus the superagent formed from the owner and its possessions forms a virtual superagent,
which behaves for some intents and purposes as if it were an singular autonomous entity.
Of course, it’s clear from Promise Theory, that agency is not a purely individual quality. It too can
be scaled. A strongly aligned group of agents can maintain a strictly consistent direction for alignment
to guide a large number of subordinates authoritatively. A key mechanism here is hierarchical scaling.
5.2 Formation of hierarchy and persistence
At different scales most systems and organizations adopt a hierarchical structure. Agents form supera-
gents, superagents form larger superagents, and so on. At each scale there can be authoritative coordi-
nation of direction from a single source, rather than a consensus approach to decision-making. This is
simply explained on an economic basis [24,25] by the fact that promises are not transactional information,
they have on-going costs: a 1 to Nrelationship (O(N)) is considerably cheaper to maintain than an N
to N(O(N2)) relationship, as long as N > 1. This explains why group cohesion tends to favour singular
authority structures over consensus structures, even when they are the result of a mandate by voting.
This point has obvious repercussions for societies in which agents are dynamical populations, which
come and go by birth and death. When a new agent is born into a pre-existing ecosystem of promises
(‘memeplex’), it may experience these as ‘boundary conditions’ or ‘exterior fixtures’ rather than matters
to negotiate. A social system of pre-aligned promises can survive longer than any individual agent,
so what happens at society scale is not necessarily aligned with what individual agents would select
had they started from scratch. In a system of voluntary cooperation, the ground state of autonomy
means that agents are not compelled (except by indirect incentive) to agree to the network of promises
instigated by prior circumstances and agents. Thus suppose, having established a voluntary hierarchy
of authority in a social collective by voting, a child is born into such a scheme, having played no role in
the selection process by which the rules and norms of society were decided. Does the authority vested
by the prior population oblige the child to agree and be cooperative? The Promise Theory answer is
21
clearly no, though by the same token it is a matter for individual assessment—however, the penalty for
non-acceptance could be to lose other rights granted by that system, which are effectively ‘owned’ by
the pre-existing representative authorities. The temporal persistence of collective promises is therefore a
form of collective inertia present in all multi-agent systems. There is indeed power in this simple form of
‘mob rule’ by incentive and disincentive at any scale.
Dunbar and coworkers have pointed out that cognitive limits on agents lead to a natural limit on
the scaling of relationship hierarchy [26,27]. Moreover, the intensity of the relationship (timescale for
interactions) matters too—the more intense a relationship, the fewer an agent can manage. The numbers
for human cognition start at 2-5 others for intense interactions, and fall into groups of 10-15 for larger
teams, 30-40 for tribal groups, and 100-200 for agents whose characteristics we ‘know’.
These limitations must apply to knowledge of things as well as persons. So we can predict that
authority could be represented by the placement of something as neutral as a road (e.g. the old native trail
of Broadway, which defies its otherwise rectilinear promises). Our working relationships and interactions
with tools consume even more of our time than our friendships in the modern world, so it’s natural
that those promises are persistent. Moreover, we are bombarded with ephemeral promise offers from all
quarters on different issues. As the capacity to comprehend specific promises and types fades or is coarse
grained away by sheer number, cooperation may be either assisted or arrested by such lack of capacity
to retain informational fidelity.
5.3 Incentives and disincentives for alignment with authority
Elementary low level agents, such as molecules and machinery, tend to have fixed and predictable be-
haviours. Higher level, more sophisticated agents are less predictable, as they contain many more variables
and may calculate their behaviours in realtime, embody strategies to optimize their responses, etc. They
can experience effective incentives or disincentives, which may shape their responses. Studying this issue
in depth is a subject for a different paper, but we can point out a few examples here for future work.
The scaling of influence, when authority is diluted amongst multiple leadership appointments, always
leaves the recipient (downstream) with a role in selecting between the different promises. In the case of
company shareholders, there isn’t much discrimination between different mandates and conditions (but
there is some, with preferred shares etc). If one takes a view based on the primacy of obligations, then
it’s hard to escape from the moral trap of needing approval for one’s actions. More entrepreneurial
spirits may care less for these indirect constraints. These are issues that can be studied and compared
to empirical results in future work.
The threat of negative consequences could lead an agent (or superagent) to not accept a promise of
directed leadership. Scaling plays a role here, because the magnitude of a threat may increase or scale with
the number of agents making it. As the disparity between the value of offer and (non)acceptance grows,
with number of individuals in each superagent, the assessments about repercussions for non-acceptance
of an imposed direction may also grow beyond a threshold for tolerance. This is the meaning of ‘force’
in a scheme of voluntary cooperation.
Promise Theory predicts that force is not the classically deterministic force as physicists and social
physicists often choose as their model [6], but rather an individual likelihood for interaction outcome,
more like the mechanics of the quantum and statistical realms. Force is nonetheless still a matter for
voluntary cooperation, which depends on a threshold for inertial intransigence amongst agents potentially
subordinate to the authoritative force. Although every agent is free, in principle, to choose their own
course, they may assess the repercussions of that choice to be unacceptable. This is especially true when
agents of comparable importance come together as a ‘mob’, with sufficient number as to be potentially
threatening to the well-being an agent choosing its course.
Promises to sanction agents, should they not act in a way aligned with another agent’s intentions, are
how we understand threats [8]. Promise Theory predicts that threats that are imposed may or may not
be effective. Promise Theory tells us that this is an autonomous assessment, for each agent individually.
It depends on the extent to which the agents know and trust one another. An agent which frequently
bluffs or cries ‘Wolf!’ may not be heeded and be ineffective, while an agent whose reliability in is judged
to be high might be feared more. In the same way, imposition of threats (without an established trust
relationship to rely on) would also be ineffective in general.
5.4 Type blindness and mistaken mandates
A limitation of scaling, in the face of limited processing capacity, is how it can affect the fidelity or
integrity of promise information. The inability to process interactions in detail, at scale, may involve
22
the need to ‘coarse grain’ or ‘average out’ information. This much affect the resolution of information
available to processes at each scale [28,29]. Every agent’s facility for processing information is limited by
its internal resources, so the reliability and timeliness of assessments made by agents falls into question
at scale.
In order to keep up with cognitive load, an agent may have to sacrifice its attention to detail, i.e.
its fidelity in preserving the precise essence of what is promised. This may lead to semantic errors of
interpretation and associated misunderstandings. In this section, let’s consider a possibility inherent
in autonomous agents of limited fidelity. As the mismatch of scales between information and resources
becomes more debilitating, agents must become somewhat blind to the details of the promises they have
given. It’s possible for agents to assess their own promise networks incorrectly.
This brings us back to the matter of indirect authority in section 3.8. It becomes easier to impose
authority (without an accurate assessment of a mandate) at scale, because agents may not have the
capacity to validate it—especially where agents are forced to overlook detail in order to preserve their
normal functions. Consider, for example, the case where an agent assesses that it has, in fact, voted for
a mandated leader (promised its support), when in fact it has only signed up to be a member of the
organization to do a specific task, because it misunderstood the terms. This is likely a common situation
in employment agreements. Employers and service providers can impose the suggestion of conditions on
employment, in the small print, to ‘trick’ employees into this de facto promise unknowingly, by implication,
which the co-signers of the agreements unwittingly attach their promise of cooperation to. Many legal
cases have been fought in this way too, leading some countries to forbid weak contract behaviour in basic
law.
Again, this phenomenon is not a human issue, but one of information resolution that occurs in any
channel over which information is passed [28,29]. The promises may seem to play similar roles from a
semantic or structural perspective, connecting the same agents with different intent, but do not explicitly
grant them any rights to make decisions on their behalf. This is the risk in placing interpreted meanings
over and above highly specific and ‘inevitable’ dynamics. This kind of indirection may have either positive
or negative consequences. It can clearly lead to great dissatisfaction if agents discover that they have
agreed to be a part of an organization in which they have no decision rights—no say in decisions that
affect them. On the other hand, they might accidentally be happy with the decisions being made, in
which case there would be no need to rock the boat and withdraw cooperation because of formalities.
This might then be called ‘emergent satisfaction’.
6 Authority as emergent (dynamical) symmetry breaking
To crown the argument for authority as a universal phenomenon, in a dynamical sense, let’s briefly divert
into the fully abstract to point out that authority is part of a wider class of phenomena in nature, which
exists even on an elementary level. Authority need not be treated as an exclusively human characteristic.
In physics, the concept of symmetry breaking refers to a pervasive phenomenon, whereby previously
indistinguishable phenomena become distinguishable, i.e. they lose their commonality or symmetry.
This is true when a plain bar of metal becomes a magnet and takes on a magnetic North and South
pole, or a single cell fœtus develops a head and a tail. It’s also true when a vanilla population of humans
divides itself up as supporters of particular sports teams or by job specialization.
Authority is an example of axial symmetry breaking, whereby a body of agents forms source and
receiver ends (heads or tails) from what begins as a symmetrical state [12]. The fundamental autonomy
of agents (their assumed group state, in which they acknowledge or even shield themselves from exterior
influence) leads to the most basic form of alignment of roles, based on voluntary cooperation [12]. From
this starting point, we can later understand how coercion and involuntary impositions attempt to simulate
this configuration. The outcomes appear somewhat similar to exterior agents, but the uncertainties make
be quite different.
Begin with the simplest directed relationship in figure 10. In this figure, one agent offers an attribute
or service, by promising +L, and another avails itself of the service l. We write this is conventional
notation as:
AL
+L
AS(50)
AS
L
AL.(51)
Implicit in this notation (and in Promise Theory) is the idea that there is no implication of force or
obligation (necessity) in these expressions. Both agents are free to withdraw their promises at any time,
23
ASAL
TAIL HEAD
−L
+L
Figure 10: The simplest directed relationship which induces the beginnings of a hierarchy. One agent offers an
attribute or service, by promising +L, and another avails itself of the service l.
so no autonomy (causal independence) is violated. This is what distinguishes Promise Theory from modal
logics and deontic formulations, which abound across the sciences, and form the dominant viewpoint on
reason. By contrast, the more successful application of physics has continued to point to the importance
of locality, or causal separation of influence in spacetime, which is expressed by the principle of autonomy
in Promise Theory. However, locality introduces new conundrums, one of which is the mechanism by
which localized agents express properties and effectively discriminate other agents of different types (from
elementary charge at the subatomic level to job descriptions at a human level, etc). Promise Theory does
not try to answer that, but rather invokes elementarily of promises as its semantic primitive.
The agents individually assess a kind of utility to the binding. Note. however, that the offer of
something ‘intended’ (in this case, a service called Lflows entirely in one direction). The invariance
of Lis what we mean by ‘intent’ in this case. Intent, in a promise theoretic sense, is a form of causal
alignment.
Notice how, in the invited forms, e.g. (23), the conditionality of promises associated with the mandate
is what implies a partial ordering of events in time, i.e. a notional direction which breaks the time
symmetry and leads to authorization in time. Without that, there is semantic asymmetry and dynamical
symmetry. Note also that a basic amount of ‘internal state’ or memory to remember past state can
affect the assessment of an agent about whether a promise has been kept satisfactorily or not. Thus, we
expect—as agents become more sophisticated on the scale from atoms to humans and ecosystems—that
their judgements will likely also be more intricate and subtle. An agent which forgets past states (like a
Markov process) always has the same level of trust in its counterpart, but an agent that holds a grudge
for past digressions may be fickle. Thus, one expects primitive interactions to be somewhat invariant
over long timescales, while complex agents with interior structure may have unpredictable and non-linear
behaviours.
7 Summarial remarks
This paper proposes a definitive way of understanding authority as a universal phenomenon—composing
the elementary interactions between autonomous agents and their semantics. Its aim is to unify many
apparently different interpretations in common usage as a single application of Promise Theory. As a
contribution to Social Science, it attempts to go beyond statistical or anecdotal evidence, to follow the
Natural Science tradition based on structure of information—agent configuration and interaction. It
doesn’t make particular assumptions about human nature, norms or social institutions, but neither does
it attempt to explain the full range of dynamics from which authority waxes, wanes, evolves, or resonates
with individuals. The complicated relationship with ‘power’ and related topics are deferred until future
work.
Authority comes in many flavours. There is no single configuration of agents, nor interpretation of
events that typifies the authority-subordinate relationship. Collective social phenomena may derive from
networks of arbitrary complexity. What I have tried to show is that all such cases must have some
necessary and sufficient features: authority is associated with a specialization of roles leading to a quasi-
service relationship of some kind, such that a number of agents or ‘subordinates’ may begin to align with
the service autonomous or ‘voluntarily’. The role of time order is not decisive, i.e. who came first, though
timescale is key in interactions; nor is it necessarily about prior privilege, suitability, or competence. It’s
not a race to win, rather it’s principally about the voluntary acceptance of roles with respect to the
reference promise or service conferred by the authority, which is built in tandem with mutual trust. The
reasons why agents accept such a breaking of symmetry between roles could be many and varied. There
is plenty of scope to study these further in this framework.
What Promise Theory predicts is that a dynamics of authority lie in an individual perception of
economic benefit—i.e. in the assessment of some ‘payoff’ in its most general meaning. Reader beware,
24
however, this statement does not necessarily imply a real valued von Neumann type utility metric [30]
as the only way of selection. The depth and sophistication of assessments depends very much of the
assessment capabilities of agents at various scales: a human has more scope for complex assessment than
an amoeba or a machine, but the same underlying dynamic applies to all. Assessment may be seen
through the lens of optimization, morality, group compliance, and so forth. In short:
An authority (as an agent) is basically a trusted party.
The emergence of its authority (as a promise) is an outcome of symmetry breaking between agents’
characteristic promises, as a result of interior processes. One such promise is identity or title, e.g.
family background, but in general a more functional role is the arbiter of distinguishable identity
rather than an agent’s proper name. Promise Theory predicts that some agents will not be able to
distinguish between different possible authorities and therefore may appoint several or appear to
choose irrationally.
If there is no individual and direct mandate, then agents may abdicate from their subordinate
positions and choose a different path, which is not aligned from a single source, e.g. ‘go AWOL’.
Regardless of whether an agent accepts a mandate or appointment as an authority, any agent is
free to appoint its own authorities on different matters.
Lying, deceptions, and threats are kinds of promise. They can apply both to the mandate promise
and the appointed service (leadership) promise. In both cases, the promises also have to be
accepted—even after the mandate has been given. So voting someone in is a necessary condition
but not a sufficient one.
When an agent authorizes some other’s behaviour, one should be sceptical, as that is a promise on
behalf of another—which violates the tenet of basic autonomy. Once formed, authority may persist
on its own by force of habit or systemic inertia, as the underlying assessments and promises may
be shrouded in layers of indirection and may thus take some time to assess and decay.
There is plenty of room for extending the method to address additional matters. In the spirit of the
natural sciences, the goal here has been to find a suitably idealized approximation which can be used as
tool for predictive reasoning. In closing, the reader could apply the derived concept of authority to this
document. Is it authoritative on the subject of authority? Might one take a vote to secure a mandate,
or merely assess the emergence of promises made individually? I’ll leave that assessment to the reader,
and defer other questions to future work.
Acknowledgement: I’m grateful to Jan Bergstra, Mark Haugaard, and Chuck Pezeshki, and Jim
Rutt for generously providing detailed comments and criticisms over the past year.
References
[1] J.A. Bergstra and M. Burgess. Promise Theory: Principles and Applications (second edition).χtAxis
Press, 2014,2019.
[2] D. Morselli and S. Passini. New perspectives on the study of the authority relationship: Integrating
individual and societal level research. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 41(3):291–307,
2011.
[3] M. Haugaard. What is authority? Journal of Classical Sociology, 18(2):104–132, 2018. DOI:
10.1177/1468795X17723737.
[4] M. Weber. Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology (ed G. Roth and C. Wittich).
University of California Press, 1978.
[5] M. Haugaard. The Four Dimensions of Power: Understanding Domination, Empowerment, and
Democracy. Manchester University Press, 2020.
[6] S. Galam. Sociophysics. Springer, 2012.
[7] J. Bergstra and M. Burgess. Promise Theory Case Study on the 2016 Brexit Vote.χt-axis Press,
2017.
25
[8] J. Bergstra. Promises and Threats by Asymmetric Nuclear Weapon States.χt-axis Press, 2019.
[9] J. Bergstra and M. Burgess. Money, Ownership, and Agency.χt-axis Press, 2019.
[10] J.A. Bergstra and M. Burgess. A promise theoretic account of the boeing 737 max mcas algorithm
affair. arXiv:2001.01543 [cs.OH], 2019.
[11] J.A. Bergstra and M. Burgess. Candidate software process flaws for the boeing 737 max mcas
algorithm and risks for a proposed upgrade. arXiv:2001.05690 [cs.CY], 2019.
[12] M. Burgess. Spacetimes with semantics (ii). arXiv.org:1505.01716, 2015.
[13] J. Searle. Intentionality. Cambridge, 1983.
[14] J. Searle. Speech Acts. Cambridge, 1969.
[15] F. Flores. Conversations for Action and Collected Essays. (independently published), 2012.
[16] J.A. Bergstra and M. Burgess. Local and global trust based on the concept of promises. Technical
report, arXiv.org/abs/0912.4637 [cs.MA], 2006.
[17] J.F. Nash. Essays on Game Theory. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, 1996.
[18] R.B. Myerson. Game theory: Analysis of Conflict. (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA),
1991.
[19] D. Mezick and M. Sheffield. Inviting Leadership: Invitation-based Change. Freestanding Press, 2018.
[20] R. Axelrod. The Complexity of Cooperation: Agent-based Models of Competition and Collaboration.
Princeton Studies in Complexity, Princeton, 1997.
[21] R. Axelrod. The Evolution of Co-operation. Penguin Books, 1990 (1984).
[22] M. Burgess. Spacetimes with semantics (i). arXiv:1411.5563, 2014.
[23] M. Burgess. Spacetimes with semantics (iii). arXiv:1608.02193, 2016.
[24] M. Burgess and S. Fagernes. Voluntary economic cooperation in policy based management. IEEE
Transactions on Network and Service Management, page (submitted).
[25] M. Burgess and S. Fagernes. Laws of human-computer behaviour and collective organization. sub-
mitted to the IEEE Journal of Network and Service Management, 2008.
[26] R. Dunbar. Grooming, Gossip and the Evolution of Language. Faber and Faber, London, 1996.
[27] W.X. Zhou, S. Sornette, R.A. Hill, and R.I.M. Dunbar. Discrete hierarchical organization of social
group sizes. Proc. Royal Soc., 272:439–444, 2004.
[28] C.E. Shannon and W. Weaver. The Mathematical Theory of Communication. University of Illinois
Press, Urbana, 1949.
[29] T.M. Cover and J.A. Thomas. Elements of Information Theory. (J.Wiley & Sons., New York), 1991.
[30] J.V. Neumann and O. Morgenstern. Theory of games and economic behaviour. Princeton University
Press, Princeton, 1944.
26
ResearchGate has not been able to resolve any citations for this publication.
Article
Full-text available
We begin with two axioms: that system behaviour is an empirical phenomenon and that organization is a form of behaviour. We derive laws and characterizations of behaviour for generic systems. In our view behaviour is not determined by internal mech- anisms alone but also by environmental forces. Systems may 'announce' their internal expectations by making "promises" about their intended behaviour. We formalize this idea using promise theory to develop an reductionist understanding of how system behaviour and organization emerges from basic rules of interaction. Starting with the assumption that all system components are autonomous entities, we derive basic laws of influence betwe en them. Organization is then understood as persistent patterns in the trajectories of the system. We show how hierarchical structure emerges from the need to offload the cost of observational calibration: it is not a design requirement for control, rat her it begins as an economic imperative which then throttles itself through poor scalability and leads to clustered tree structures, with a trade-off between depth and width.
Article
Full-text available
Abstract Systems with decentralized authority are sometimes,considered to be ‘unmanaged’ or even unman- ageable. Promise theory is an approach to policy that assumes complete,decentralization of authority. Cooperation between agents or systems is entirely voluntary, so why would agents cooperate in forming policy? By exhibiting the relationship between promise theory and game theory, we propose that there is a natural economic,incentive for cooperation in distribu ted systems with autonomous,control. The possibility of trading between,agents motivates the definit ion of a common,currency. Our results are especially applicable to the analysis of policy in a Service Oriented Architecture. We derive minimal requirements for the existence of stable Agreements between agents, with or without monetary payment.
Article
Full-text available
The concept of authority crosses many social sciences, but there is a lack of common taxonomy and definitions on this topic. The aims of this review are: (1) to define the basic characteristics of the authority relationship, reaching a definition suitable for the different domains of social psychology and social sciences; (2) to bridge the gap between individual and societal levels of explanation concerning the authority relationship, by proposing an interpretation within the framework of social representations. The authority relationship can be conceived as a negotiation of meanings and it is closely linked to shared value orientation and the attribution of meanings negotiated within a society. We assume that the authority relationship is socially constructed and represents both a shared representation of society and a normative principle of social life. A multidisciplinary approach is adopted, crossing definitions and studies provided in sociology, political science, law and social psychology.
Article
This section presents the third volume of Max Weber's fundamental work Economy and Society which has been translated into Russian for the first time. The third volume includes two works devoted to the sociology of law. The first, 'The Economy and Laws', discusses differences between sociological and juridical approaches to studies of social processes. It describes peculiarities of normative power arenas (orders) at different levels and demonstrates how they influence the economy. The second, 'Economy and Law' ('Sociology of Law'), reviews the evolution of law orders (primarily, the three "greatest systems of law" including Roman Law, Anglo-American Law, and European Continental Law) in the context of changes in the organization of economy and structures of dominancy. Law is considered an influential factor of the rationalization of social life which in turn is affected by a rationalized economy and social management. The Journal of Economic Sociology here publishes an excerpt from the chapter 'Law, Convention and Custom' in this third volume, which shows the role of the habitual in the formation of law; explains the importance of intuition and empathy for the emergence of new orders; and discusses the changeable borders between law, convention and custom. The translation is edited by Leonid Ionin and the chapter is published with the permission of HSE Publishing House. © 2018 National Research University Higher School of Economics. All rights reserved.
Book
"This is the classic work upon which modern-day game theory is based. What began more than sixty years ago as a modest proposal that a mathematician and an economist write a short paper together blossomed, in 1944, when Princeton University Press published Theory of Games and Economic Behavior. In it, John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern conceived a groundbreaking mathematical theory of economic and social organization, based on a theory of games of strategy. Not only would this revolutionize economics, but the entirely new field of scientific inquiry it yielded--game theory--has since been widely used to analyze a host of real-world phenomena from arms races to optimal policy choices of presidential candidates, from vaccination policy to major league baseball salary negotiations. And it is today established throughout both the social sciences and a wide range of other sciences. This sixtieth anniversary edition includes not only the original text but also an introduction by Harold Kuhn, an afterword by Ariel Rubinstein, and reviews and articles on the book that appeared at the time of its original publication in the New York Times, tthe American Economic Review, and a variety of other publications. Together, these writings provide readers a matchless opportunity to more fully appreciate a work whose influence will yet resound for generations to come.
Chapter
Half-title pageSeries pageTitle pageCopyright pageDedicationPrefaceAcknowledgementsContentsList of figuresHalf-title pageIndex