ArticlePDF Available

Abstract

In this commentary, we explore some ways in which insights from experimental philosophical bioethics (bioxphi), combined with the use of immersive digital technologies, may yield an even clearer picture of the concepts, intuitions, reasoning, and empirical assumptions commonly implicated in bioethics debates than is currently possible with existing methods.
1
Advancing methods in empirical bioethics:
bioxphi meets digital technologies
Emilian Mihailov,1 Ivar Hannikainen,2 and Brian D. Earp3,4
1 University of Bucharest, Romania
2 University of Granada, Spain
3 Yale University, USA
4 University of Oxford, UK
Summary
In this commentary, we explore some ways in which insights from experimental
philosophical bioethics (bioxphi), combined with the use of immersive digital
technologies, may yield an even clearer picture of the concepts, intuitions, reasoning,
and empirical assumptions commonly implicated in bioethics debates than is currently
possible with existing methods.
Historically, empirical research in bioethics has drawn on methods developed within the
social sciences, including qualitative interviews, focus groups, ethnographic studies, and opinion
surveys, to advance understanding of key issues in the field (Davies et al. 2015). In their target
article, Pavarini and colleagues (2021) emphasize some limitations to the ecological validity of
previous methods, and advocate a new approach they call design bioethics. Most saliently, this
This is the authors’ copy of an accepted manuscript, now published. It may be cited as:
Mihailov, E., Hannikainen, I., & Earp, B. D. (2021). Advancing methods in empirical
bioethics: bioxphi meets digital technologies. American Journal of Bioethics, 21(6), 53-
56. [version of record at https://doi.org/10.1080/15265161.2021.1915417]
2
approach harnesses the research potential of digital technologies, such as computer games and
virtual reality (VR). Pavarini et al. argue that immersive digital tools have the potential to simulate
lived contextual experience, embodied decision-making, and the narrative richness of a situation.
Accordingly, researchers can design interactive virtual scenarios in which participants’ choices
influence how the story unfolds (effectively, a high-tech “choose your own adventure”). The
prospect of incorporating these methods into the toolbox of empirical bioethics is exciting, and will
undoubtedly raise new questions, both empirical and normative.
In recent work with colleagues, we have similarly proposed a new framework for the use
of empirical methods in bioethics, what we call experimental philosophical bioethics or bioxphi
(Earp et al. 2020; Earp et al. 2021), modeled on the ‘parent’ discipline of experimental philosophy
or x-phi (Knobe et al. 2012). In this commentary, we explore some ways in which insights from
bioxphi, combined with the use of immersive digital technologies, may yield an even clearer
picture of the concepts, intuitions, reasoning, and empirical assumptions commonly implicated in
bioethics debates.
In a nutshell, bioxphi is a form of experimental moral philosophy as applied to topics in
bioethics. It uses controlled experiments rather than descriptive studies to understand morally
charged phenomena of interest to bioethicists, with the aim of contributing to associated
normative debates (Earp et al. 2020). When policymakers draw on public attitudes to decide about
the permissibility of using certain biomedical or neuroscientific technologies, for example, what
actually shapes the public’s moral attitudes toward these technologies (Mihailov et al. 2021)? How
do medical professionals distinguish between ‘ending’ a patient’s life and ‘allowing’ it to end, and
what factors influence attributions of the cause of death (Rodríguez-Arias et al. 2020)? By asking
questions such as these, bioxphi seeks not merely to document stakeholder judgments or
behavior in circumstances of bioethical relevance, but also to uncover the precise contextual
factors and proximate psychological mechanisms that explain why people judge and act as they
do (Earp et al. 2020). The immersive tools of design bioethics, with their emphasis on ecological
3
validity, could help identify additional factors and processes that shape moral intuitions, decisions,
and other outcomes of interest in bioethical contexts. For instance, controlled experiments using
virtual and augmented reality methods could systematically manipulate well-defined elements of
the experienced environment to study the influence of these factors on moral judgments and
behavior. This methodological design would be analogous to -- but going beyond what is possible
with -- the so-called contrastive vignette technique (Reimer 2019).
Bioethical judgment versus behavior: to each domain its own method
A principal concern in Pavarini and colleagues’ article (2021, p. 9) is that contrastive
vignette studies rely on static hypothetical scenarios, typically presented through short written
descriptions; and for this reason, they lack the emotional and contextual grounding of everyday
sensory experience. Without such grounding, participants’ responses may be unrepresentative of
their actual responses when engaging in the (virtually) real world. But are the situations or
judgments of interest to bioethicists invariably vivid and dependent on features of the physical
environment? Perhaps not. For instance, the experience of voting on a bioethical policy or forming
an abstract judgment about a range of policy-relevant issues might in fact be reasonably well-
captured by static, text-based stimuli. On the other hand, simulating a real-life emergency room
to understand the urgent judgment calls of physicians may demand richer and more realistic,
sensory-based research methods.
In other words, whether a particular research objective is best pursued through sensorially
rich, immersive methods, or through traditional, text-based methods, depends on the question at
hand. One way to answer this question is by considering the target behavior or judgment of
interest, and determining whether what is most (bioethically) relevant about it is people’s
embodied responses (i.e., how they actually react in vivid circumstances) or their declarative
judgments (i.e., what people decide when reasoning more abstractly). By taking advantage of
4
both immersive and conventional text-based stimuli, we might develop a more complete
understanding of people’s behavioral tendencies and declarative attitudes toward bioethical
questions. Thus, while we share Pavarini and colleagues’ enthusiasm about ongoing
developments in digital technology, we wish to call attention to the contingency or variability in
whether behavioral or vignette methods are better suited to a particular research objective. A
flexible use of these complementary research methods may furnish the most detailed
understanding of the bioethical mind.
Bioxphi and normative inference
What are some ways in which the bioxphi approach may offer distinct advantages? As we
see it, bioxphi is especially well-suited to identifying the factors that influence moral judgment,
allowing us to probe the epistemic or normative value of these factors. Consider the following
schema of a bioethical argument:
1. The moral condemnation M of biomedical technology X is mainly influenced by
factor/process F/P. [empirical premise]
2. F/P is a normatively unreliable factor/process. [normative premise]
3. So, moral condemnation M of biomedical technology X is unjustified.
The normative premise may require a sophisticated argument to show that a factor F is
morally unreliable or irrelevant. But either way, the empirical premise will be crucial to determining
whether the moral condemnation M of biomedical technology X is unjustified. Without the
knowledge that factor F underpins moral condemnation M, we would not be in a position to
question the epistemic or normative merit of M.
5
Let us illustrate. In a recent experimental study, we investigated potential factors that
undergird moral attitudes toward cognitive enhancement (Mihailov et al. 2021). We described a
series of agents who took ‘smart pills’ during a competition, and asked participants whether the
agents’ subsequent achievements were the result of their abilities or of the pills’ effects.
Participants who were especially concerned with fairness tended to diminish the role of the
agents’ skill and dedication, concluding instead that the ‘smart pills’ were ultimately responsible
for bringing about success. Importantly, this pattern arose only when cognitive enhancement was
described as abnormal. Describing smart pill use as commonplace eliminated such fairness-
based disapproval.
This raises a complex ethical question: Normatively speaking, does mere normalization
constitute reliable or unreliable grounds for one’s moral approval of cognitive enhancement?
Depending on one’s normative or epistemic commitments about what makes a moral judgment
reliable or unreliable, these empirical findings might help us decide whether, and to what extent,
such judgments should play a role in guiding associated policy debates.
In another study, Earp and colleagues used a mix of digital and text-based materials to
test whether the perceived gender of a child influences the amount of pain the child is judged to
be feeling. Earp et al. showed participants a video of a young child dressed in gender-neutral
clothing getting a finger-stick to draw blood and asked how much pain the child experienced (Earp
et al. 2019). Earp et al. found that when the child was called “Samuel” participants rated the child
as experiencing more pain than when the child was called “Samantha,” holding everything else
equal. Thus, perceived gender alone appeared to bias observer interpretations of felt pain in this
relatively context-rich study (i.e., due to the use of a video of an actual clinical encounter). These
results might then cast doubt upon the reliability of a moral judgment that, say, children of different
genders should receive different levels of pain control for a comparable injury.
6
These studies show how normative inferences in bioethics might draw on empirical
findings from bioxphi studies, an important enterprise given that empirical research in bioethics is
still predominantly descriptively oriented (Wangmo and Provoost 2017).
The role of situated behaviors in moral inference
Suppose that certain situational factors or psychological processes have been identified,
in bioxphi research, as likely to play a role in people’s moral judgments or behaviors. Design
bioethics offers a valuable opportunity to show how these factors or processes actually play out
in the (virtually) real world. In other words, the results of bioxphi studies may inspire thinking within
design bioethics as to what kinds of phenomena to simulate; and then potential differences
between abstract judgments and context-specific behaviors may be explored. There is some
precedent for this sort of comparison. Within moral psychology, researchers have simulated
sacrificial dilemma scenarios developed by armchair philosophers (Francis et al. 2016; Patil et al.
2014). The emotionally arousing nature of virtual reality generated different behavioral responses
from choices made using text-based methods.
1
Given the discrepancy between moral thought
and moral action, simulation technologies are well suited to serve the implementation purpose of
bioethics. Design bioethics, with its capacity to impose time constraints, mimic real-world
uncertainty, and include visual and tactile interaction, can help us evaluate the feasibility of certain
ethical recommendations.
At the same time, the implementation aspect of design bioethics can provide a feedback
loop to bioxphi. Realistic simulations of moral scenarios elicit high-fidelity cognitive and emotional
responses. The contextual richness of virtual reality might reveal details not seen by conventional
(e.g., text-based) analysis. Sometimes, it will only be possible to determine which stimuli are
1
Surprisingly, as emotional arousal had been expected to reduce utilitarian choices, the virtual
simulation of the so-called footbridge moral dilemma actually increased such choices (Francis et
al. 2016; Patil et al. 2014).
7
relevant for understanding moral judgments or behavior after these have actually occurred in a
realistic setting.
Conclusion
Ultimately, we see bioxphi and design bioethics as complementary, rather than competing,
approaches. Indeed, insofar as design bioethics employs an experimental design to examine how
particular variables influence moral judgments or behavior (for example, by manipulating key
features of the environment across virtual reality sessions), it could be seen as an instance or
extension of the bioxphi approach we have advocated in recent work: a kind of "high-tech bioxphi.”
We look forward to exploring the interface between these emerging methodological frameworks
for empirical studies within bioethics, and reflecting on potential normative implications for
bioethical theory, practice, and policy.
Acknowledgments
This work was supported by a grant of the Romanian Ministery of Education and Research,
CNCS UEFISCDI, project number PN-III-P4-ID-PCE-2020-0521, within PNCDI III.
References:
1. Davies, R., Ives, J., & Dunn, M. (2015). A systematic review of empirical bioethics
methodologies. BMC Medical Ethics, 16(1), 1-13.
2. Earp, B. D., Monrad, J. T., LaFrance, M., Bargh, J. A., Cohen, L. L., & Richeson, J. A.
(2019). Gender bias in pediatric pain assessment. Journal of Pediatric Psychology,
44(4), 403-414.
8
3. Earp, B. D., Demaree-Cotton, J., Dunn, M., Dranseika, V., Everett, J. A., Feltz, A., ... &
Tobia, K. (2020). Experimental philosophical bioethics. AJOB Empirical bioethics, 11(1),
30-33.
4. Earp, B. D., Lewis, J., Dranseika, V., & Hannikainen, I. (2021). Experimental
philosophical bioethics and normative inference. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics,
forthcoming.
5. Francis, K. B., Howard, C., Howard, I. S., Gummerum, M., Ganis, G., Anderson, G., &
Terbeck, S. (2016). Virtual morality: Transitioning from moral judgment to moral action?.
PLOS ONE, 11(10), e0164374.
6. Knobe, J., Buckwalter, W., Nichols, S., Robbins, P., Sarkissian, H., & Sommers, T.
(2012). Experimental philosophy. Annual Review of Psychology, 63, 81-99.
7. Mihailov, E., López, B. R., Cova, F., & Hannikainen, I. R. (2021). How pills undermine
skills: Moralization of cognitive enhancement and causal selection. Consciousness and
Cognition, 91, 103120.
8. Patil, I., Cogoni, C., Zangrando, N., Chittaro, L., & Silani, G. (2014). Affective basis of
judgment-behavior discrepancy in virtual experiences of moral dilemmas. Social
Neuroscience, 9(1), 94-107.
9. Pavarini, G., McMillan, R., Robinson, A., & Singh, I. (2021). Design bioethics: a
theoretical framework and argument for innovation in bioethics research. The American
Journal of Bioethics, 1-21.
10. Reiner, P. B. (2019). Experimental neuroethics. In Shaping Children (pp. 75-83).
Springer, Cham.
11. Rodríguez-Arias, D., Rodríguez López, B., Monasterio-Astobiza, A., & Hannikainen, I. R.
(2020). How do people use ‘killing’, ‘letting die’ and related bioethical concepts?
Contrasting descriptive and normative hypotheses. Bioethics, 34(5), 509-518.
9
12. Wangmo, T., & Provoost, V. (2017). The use of empirical research in bioethics: a survey
of researchers in twelve European countries. BMC Medical Ethics, 18(1), 1-11.
... For instance, descriptive ethics studies explore stakeholders' responses to bioethical questions and try explain how people arrive at certain moral opinions Open Access *Correspondence: emilian.mihailov@filosofie.unibuc.ro and reasoning patterns [13][14][15][16][17][18][19][20][21][22]. Empirical research can investigate whether people and healthcare professionals comply with ethical guidelines and how ethical solutions are translated into practice [13-15, 18, 23-29]. ...
... All participants accepted the lowest ambitious objective: identification of ethical issues in practice. It was not viewed as an important objective mainly because empirical research was assumed to be hypothesis driven, in line with experimental strands of empirical bioethics [16,19,21]. Therefore, this objective was not considered a driving force of empirical research. ...
... However, other scholars have argued previously that social sciences should have a more important role in bioethical inquiry which goes beyond the production of empirical results [39,40,42,43,51]. As bioethics becomes more interdisciplinary, many questions about how to carry out such integration as well as quality standards of such an integration remain disputed [21,[52][53][54][55][56]. ...
Article
Full-text available
Background: This is the first qualitative study to investigate how researchers, who do empirical work in bioethics, relate to objectives of empirical research in bioethics (ERiB). We explore reasons that make some objectives more acceptable, while others are deemed less acceptable. Methods: Using qualitative exploratory study design, we interviewed bioethics researchers, who were selected to represent different types of scholars working in the field. The interview data of 25 participants were analyzed in this paper using thematic analysis. Results: From the eight objectives presented to the study participants, understanding the context of a bioethical issue and identifying ethical issues in practice received unanimous agreement. Participants also supported other objectives of ERiB but with varying degrees of agreement. The most contested objectives were striving to draw normative recommendations and developing and justifying moral principles. The is-ought gap was not considered an obstacle to ERiB, but rather a warning sign to critically reflect on the normative implications of empirical results. Conclusions: Our results show that the most contested objectives are also the more ambitious ones, whereas the least contested ones focus on producing empirical results. The potential of empirical research to be useful for bioethics was mostly based on the reasoning pattern that empirical data can provide a testing ground for elements of normative theory. Even though empirical research can inform many parts of bioethical inquiry, normative expertise is recommended to guide ERiB. The acceptability of ambitious objectives for ERiB boils down to finding firm ground for the integration of empirical facts in normative inquiry.
... This chapter summarizes an emerging sub-discipline of both empirical bioethics and experimental philosophy ("x-phi") which has variously been referred to as experimental philosophical bioethics, experimental bioethics, or simply "bioxphi" Lewis, 2020;Mihailov, Hannikainen and Earp, 2021). Like empirical bioethics, bioxphi uses data-driven research methods to capture what various stakeholders think (feel, judge, etc.) about moral issues of relevance to bioethics. ...
... In principle, bioxphi studies could employ the full range of experimental methods used in the cognitive and psychosocial sciences, including, for example, the use of transcranial magnetic or direct-current brain stimulation devices to influence the cognitive processes involved in making moral judgments (e.g., Kuehne et al., 2015), or the administration of psychoactive substances to influence moral motivations (see Earp, 2018). Indeed, as some have argued (O'Neill and Machery, 2014;Mihailov, Hannikainen and Earp, 2021;Nado, 2021;Alfano, Loeb and Plakias, 2022), experimental methods could also usefully be employed in combination with other empirical methods, such as interviews, qualitative surveys, linguistic corpus data analyses, anthropological work, and virtual reality simulations. ...
Chapter
Full-text available
This chapter summarizes an emerging sub-discipline of both empirical bioethics and experimental philosophy (“x-phi”) which has variously been referred to as experimental philosophical bioethics, experimental bioethics, or simply “bioxphi” (Earp, Latham and Tobia, 2020; Earp et al., 2020; Lewis, 2020; Mihailov, Hannikainen and Earp, 2021). Like empirical bioethics, bioxphi uses data-driven research methods to capture what various stakeholders think (feel, judge, etc.) about moral issues of relevance to bioethics. However, like its other parent discipline of x-phi, bioxphi tends to favor experiment-based designs drawn from the cognitive sciences (Knobe, 2016)—including psychology, neuroscience, and behavioral economics—to tease out why and how stakeholders think as they do.
... In 2015, Davies and colleagues summarized thirtytwo empirical bioethics integrative methodologies that combine normative analysis and empirical data obtained using social-science research. Following this, scholars have discussed the integration of the normative and life sciences research (Mertz and Schildmann 2018), using critical realism in empirical bioethics (McKeown 2017), and integrating experimental philosophical bioethics and normative ethics (Earp, et al. 2020;Mihailov, et al. 2021). In line with the systematic review of empirical bioethics methodologies' two broad categories of dialogical and consultative processes of integration (Davies, et al. 2015), our participants indicated two familiar approaches. ...
Article
Full-text available
The integration of normative analysis with empirical data often remains unclear despite the availability of many empirical bioethics methodologies. This paper sought bioethics scholars’ experiences and reflections of doing empirical bioethics research to feed these practical insights into the debate on methods. We interviewed twenty-six participants who revealed their process of integrating the normative and the empirical. From the analysis of the data, we first used the themes to identify the methodological content. That is, we show participants’ use of familiar methods explained as “back-and-forth” methods (reflective equilibrium), followed by dialogical methods where collaboration was seen as a better way of doing integration. Thereafter, we highlight methods that were deemed as inherent integration approaches, where the normative and the empirical were intertwined from the start of the research project. Second, we used the themes to express not only how we interpreted what was said but also how things were said. In this, we describe an air of uncertainty and overall vagueness that surrounded the above methods. We conclude that the indeterminacy of integration methods is a double-edged sword. It allows for flexibility but also risks obscuring a lack of understanding of the theoretical-methodological underpinnings of empirical bioethics research methods.
... Experimental bioethics has also established itself as a specific approach within bioethics (see Rodríguez, this volume; Earp et al., 2020). Beyond employing empirical evidence as a general constraint for philosophical theorising (Borry et al., 2005), experimental bioethics has recently highlighted the importance of getting precise evidence (relying primarily on controlled experiments) to test well-defined hypotheses, mostly about the shape of folk intuitions in institutional settings and the psychological and cultural factors underlying such intuitions (Mihailov et al., 2021). Several classical topics are being reinvigorated using experimental bioethics approaches such as the question of personal identity in complex medical contexts (Strohminger & Nichols, 2015;Earp et al., 2022). ...
... Experimental bioethics has also established itself as a specific approach within bioethics (see Rodríguez, this volume; Earp et al., 2020). Beyond employing empirical evidence as a general constraint for philosophical theorising (Borry et al., 2005), experimental bioethics has recently highlighted the importance of getting precise evidence (relying primarily on controlled experiments) to test well-defined hypotheses, mostly about the shape of folk intuitions in institutional settings and the psychological and cultural factors underlying such intuitions (Mihailov et al., 2021). Several classical topics are being reinvigorated using experimental bioethics approaches such as the question of personal identity in complex medical contexts (Strohminger & Nichols, 2015;Earp et al., 2022). ...
... The ways in which psychological factors affect our moral intuitions has attracted the interest of experimental moral philosophers (Earp et al., 2020Lewis, 2020;Königs, 2022;Mihailov et al., 2021;Pölzler & Paulo, 2021). In a recent estimation (Cova et al., 2021), found that x-phi studies were successfully replicated about 70% of the time, as compared with less than 50% in social psychology (Open Science Collaboration, 2015). ...
Article
In this paper we develop test cases to adjudicate between dual-process and the causal mapping explanations of order effects. Using dilemmas with minimized emotional force, we explore new conditions for order effects to occur. Overall, the results support causal model theory. We produced novel evidence that order effects extend not only to cases with low emotional engagement, but also to specialized judgments about whether an action violates a rule. However, when objects are sacrificed instead of persons the order effect either disappears or becomes symmetrical, contrary to previous theorizing that it is an asymmetrical transfer effect. Causal model theory needs to be developed to include interplays between the moral status of sacrificed entities and computational models of causal mapping. Symmetric order effects remain a puzzle, motivating future research. Though we do not know how to explain them yet, we discuss how symmetric order effects can influence policy decision making.
... Drawing on past research in cognitive science and bioethics, the present work-an instance of socalled experimental philosophical bioethics [48,[55][56][57]-advanced an explanation of the treatment-enhancement distinction and the conditions in which it arises: In short, we found that providing access to health-related interventions shapes their perceived normality, and normalization dampens people's selective disapproval of enhancement. As a result, people strongly differentiate between treatment and enhancement when the medical interventions in question are inaccessible, but this distinction weakens as interventions become more accessibleand, in turn, more widespread among their potential beneficiaries. ...
Preprint
Full-text available
There is little debate regarding the acceptability of providing medical care to restore physical or mental health that has deteriorated below what is considered typical due to disease or disorder (i.e., providing “treatment”—for example, administering psychostimulant medication to sustain attention in the case of attention deficit disorder). When asked whether a healthy individual may undergo the same intervention for the purpose of enhancing their capacities (i.e., “enhancement”— for example, use of a psychostimulant as a “study drug”), people often express greater hesitation. Building on prior research in moral philosophy and cognitive science, in this work, we ask why people draw a moral distinction between treatment and enhancement. In two experiments, we provide evidence that the accessibility of health-related interventions determines their perceived descriptive or statistical normality (Experiment 1), and that gains in descriptive normality for such interventions weaken the moral distinction between treatment and enhancement (Experiment 2). In short, our findings suggest that the tendency to draw a moral distinction between treatment and enhancement is driven, in part, by assumptions about descriptive abnormality; and raise the possibility that normalizing novel biomedical interventions by promoting access could undermine people’s selective opposition toward enhancement, rendering it morally comparable to treatment.
Article
Full-text available
We propose to expand the conversation around moral enhancement from direct brain-altering methods to include technological means of modifying the environments and media through which agents can achieve moral improvement. Virtual Reality (VR) based enhancement would not bypass a person’s agency, much less their capacity for reasoned reflection. It would allow agents to critically engage with moral insights occasioned by a technologically mediated intervention. Users would gain access to a vivid ‘experience machine’ that allows for embodied presence and immersion in a virtual world that meaningfully replicates relevant aspects of real life. We explore how VR can train empathy and foster moral growth in complex ways that would be inaccessible even for traditional moral education. Virtual Reality Perspective Taking is a unique medium for making empathy more reflective.
Article
Full-text available
There is little debate regarding the acceptability of providing medical care to restore physical or mental health that has deteriorated below what is considered typical due to disease or disorder (i.e., providing “treatment”—for example, administering psychostimulant medication to sustain attention in the case of attention deficit disorder). When asked whether a healthy individual may undergo the same intervention for the purpose of enhancing their capacities (i.e., “enhancement”—for example, use of a psychostimulant as a “study drug”), people often express greater hesitation. Building on prior research in moral philosophy and cognitive science, in this work, we ask why people draw a moral distinction between treatment and enhancement. In two experiments, we provide evidence that the accessibility of health-related interventions determines their perceived descriptive or statistical normality (Experiment 1), and that gains in descriptive normality for such interventions weaken the moral distinction between treatment and enhancement (Experiment 2). In short, our findings suggest that the tendency to draw a moral distinction between treatment and enhancement is driven, in part, by assumptions about descriptive abnormality; and raise the possibility that normalizing novel biomedical interventions by promoting access could undermine people’s selective opposition toward enhancement, rendering it morally comparable to treatment.
Preprint
Full-text available
In this paper we develop test cases to adjudicate between dual-process and the causal mapping explanations of order effects. Using dilemmas with minimized emotional force, we explore new conditions for order effects to occur. Overall, the results support causal model theory. We produced novel evidence that order effects extend not only to cases with low emotional engagement, but also to specialized judgements about whether an action violates a rule. However, when objects are sacrificed instead of persons the order effect either disappears or becomes symmetrical, contrary to previous theorizing that it is an asymmetrical transfer effect. Causal model theory needs to be developed to include interplays between the moral status of sacrificed entities and computational models of causal mapping. Symmetric order effects remain a puzzle, motivating future research. Though we do not know how to explain them yet, we discuss how symmetric order effects can influence policy decision making.
Article
Full-text available
Despite the promise to boost human potential and wellbeing, enhancement drugs face recurring ethical scrutiny. The present studies examined attitudes toward cognitive enhancement in order to learn more about these ethical concerns, who has them, and the circumstances in which they arise. Fairness-based concerns underlay opposition to competitive use—even though enhancement drugs were described as legal, accessible and affordable. Moral values also influenced how subsequent rewards were causally explained: Opposition to competitive use reduced the causal contribution of the enhanced winner’s skill, particularly among fairness-minded individuals. In a follow-up study, we asked: Would the normalization of enhancement practices alleviate concerns about their unfairness? Indeed, proliferation of competitive cognitive enhancement eradicated fairness-based concerns, and boosted the perceived causal role of the winner’s skill. In contrast, purity-based concerns emerged in both recreational and competitive contexts, and were not assuaged by normalization.
Article
Full-text available
Empirical research in bioethics has developed rapidly over the past decade, but has largely eschewed the use of technology-driven methodologies. We propose “design bioethics” as an area of conjoined theoretical and methodological innovation in the field, working across bioethics, health sciences and human-centred technological design. We demonstrate the potential of digital tools, particularly purpose-built digital games, to align with theoretical frameworks in bioethics for empirical research, integrating context, narrative and embodiment in moral decision-making. Purpose-built digital tools can engender situated engagement with bioethical questions; can achieve such engagement at scale; and can access groups traditionally under-represented in bioethics research and theory. If developed and used with appropriate rigor, tools motivated by “design bioethics” could offer unique insights into new and familiar normative and empirical issues in the field.
Article
Full-text available
This paper explores an emerging sub-field of both empirical bioethics and experimental philosophy (“x-phi”), which has been called “experimental philosophical bioethics” (“bioxphi”). As an empirical discipline, bioxphi adopts the methods of experimental moral psychology and cognitive science; it does so to make sense of the eliciting factors and underlying cognitive processes that shape people’s normative judgments, particularly about real-world matters of bioethical concern. Yet, as a normative discipline situated within the broader field of bioethics, it also aims to contribute to substantive ethical questions about what should be done in a given context. What are some of the ways in which this aim has been pursued? In this paper, we employ a case study approach to examine and critically evaluate four strategies from the recent literature by which scholars in bioxphi have leveraged empirical data in the service of normative arguments.
Preprint
Full-text available
Bioethicists involved in end-of-life debates routinely distinguish between ‘killing’ and ‘letting die’. Meanwhile, previous work in cognitive science has revealed that when people characterize behavior as either actively ‘doing’ or passively ‘allowing’, they do so not purely on descriptive grounds, but also as a function of the behavior’s perceived morality. In the present report, we extend this line of research by examining how medical students and professionals (N = 184) and laypeople (N = 122) describe physicians’ behavior in end-of-life scenarios. We show that the distinction between ‘ending’ a patient’s life and ‘allowing’ it to end arises from morally-motivated causal selection: Namely, when a patient wishes to die, her illness is treated as the cause of death and the doctor is seen as merely allowing her life to end. In contrast, when a patient does not wish to die, the doctor’s behavior is treated as the cause of death and, consequently, the doctor is described as ending the patient’s life. This effect emerged regardless of whether the doctor’s behavior was omissive (as in withholding treatment) or commissive (as in applying a lethal injection). In other words, patient consent shapes causal selection in end-of-life situations, and in turn determines whether physicians are seen as ‘killing’ patients, or merely as ‘enabling’ their death.
Article
Full-text available
There is a rich tradition in bioethics of gathering empirical data to inform, supplement, or test the implications of normative ethical analysis. To this end, bioethicists have drawn on diverse methods, including qualitative interviews, focus groups, ethnographic studies, and opinion surveys to advance understanding of key issues in bioethics. In so doing, they have developed strong ties with neighboring disciplines such as anthropology, history, law, and sociology. Collectively, these lines of research have flourished in the broader field of “empirical bioethics” for more than 30 years (Sugarman & Sulmasy 2010). More recently, philosophers from outside the field of bioethics have similarly employed empirical methods—drawn primarily from psychology, the cognitive sciences, economics, and related disciplines—to advance theoretical debates. This approach, which has come to be called experimental philosophy (or x-phi), relies primarily on controlled experiments to interrogate the concepts, intuitions, reasoning, implicit mental processes, and empirical assumptions about the mind that play a role in traditional philosophical arguments (Knobe et al. 2012). Within the moral domain, for example, experimental philosophy has begun to contribute to long-standing debates about the nature of moral judgment and reasoning; the sources of our moral emotions and biases; the qualities of a good person or a good life; and the psychological basis of moral theory itself (Alfano, Loeb, & Plakias 2018). We believe that experimental philosophical bioethics—or “bioxphi”—can similarly contribute to bioethical scholarship and debate. Here, we introduce this emerging discipline, explain how it is distinct from empirical bioethics more broadly construed, and attempt to characterize how it might advance theory and practice in this area.
Article
Full-text available
Objective: Accurate assessment of pain is central to diagnosis and treatment in healthcare, especially in pediatrics. However, few studies have examined potential biases in adult observer ratings of children’s pain. Cohen et al. (2014) reported that adult participants rated a child undergoing a medical procedure as feeling more pain when the child was described as a boy as compared to a girl, suggesting a possible gender bias. To confirm, clarify, and extend this finding, we conducted a replication experiment and follow-up study examining the role of explicit gender stereotypes in shaping such asymmetric judgments. Method: In an independent, pre-registered, direct replication and extension study with open data and materials (https://osf.io/t73c4/), we showed participants the same video from Cohen et al. (2014), with the child described as a boy or a girl depending on condition. We then asked adults to rate how much pain the child experienced and displayed, how typical the child was in these respects, and how much they agreed with explicit gender stereotypes concerning pain response in boys versus girls. Results: Similar to Cohen et al. (2014), but with a larger and more demographically diverse sample, we found that the ‘boy’ was rated as experiencing more pain than the ‘girl’ despite identical clinical circumstances and identical pain behavior cross conditions. Controlling for explicit gender stereotypes eliminated the effect. Conclusions: Explicit gender stereotypes—e.g., that boys are more stoic or girls are more emotive—may bias adult assessment of children’s pain.
Article
Full-text available
Background: The use of empirical research methods in bioethics has been increasing in the last decades. It has resulted in discussions about the 'empirical turn of bioethics' and raised questions related to the value of empirical work for this field, methodological questions about its quality and rigor, and how this integration of the normative and the empirical can be achieved. The aim of this paper is to describe the attitudes of bioethics researchers in this field towards the use of empirical research, and examine their actual conduct: whether they use empirical research methods (and if so, what methods), and whether (and how) they have made attempts at integrating the empirical and the normative. Methods: An anonymous online survey was conducted to reach scholars working in bioethics/biomedical ethics/ethics institutes or centers in 12 European countries. A total of 225 bioethics researchers participated in the study. Of those, 200 questionnaires were fully completed, representing a response rate of 42.6%. The results were analysed using descriptive statistics. Results: Most respondents (n = 175; 87.5%) indicated that they use or have used empirical methods in their work. A similar proportion of respondents (61.0% and 59.0%) reported having had at least some training in qualitative or quantitative methods, respectively. Among the 'empirical researchers', more than a fifth (22.9%) had not received any methodological training. It appears that only 6% or less of the 'empirical researchers' considered themselves experts in the methods (qualitative or quantitative) that they have used. Only 35% of the scholars who have used empirical methods reported having integrated empirical data with normative analysis, whereas for their current projects, 59.8% plan to do so. Conclusions: There is a need to evaluate the current educational programs in bioethics and to implement rigorous training in empirical research methods to ensure that 'empirical researchers' have the necessary skills to conduct their empirical research in bioethics. Also imperative is clear guidance on the integration of the normative and the empirical so that researchers who plan to do so have necessary tools and competences to fulfil their goals.
Article
Full-text available
The nature of moral action versus moral judgment has been extensively debated in numerous disciplines. We introduce Virtual Reality (VR) moral paradigms examining the action individuals take in a high emotionally arousing, direct action-focused, moral scenario. In two studies involving qualitatively different populations, we found a greater endorsement of utilitarian responses–killing one in order to save many others–when action was required in moral virtual dilemmas compared to their judgment counterparts. Heart rate in virtual moral dilemmas was significantly increased when compared to both judgment counterparts and control virtual tasks. Our research suggests that moral action may be viewed as an independent construct to moral judgment, with VR methods delivering new prospects for investigating and assessing moral behaviour.
Article
Full-text available
Background Despite the increased prevalence of bioethics research that seeks to use empirical data to answer normative research questions, there is no consensus as to what an appropriate methodology for this would be. This review aims to search the literature, present and critically discuss published Empirical Bioethics methodologies. Methods MedLine, Web of Science and Google Scholar were searched between 15/02/12 and 16/06/13 to find relevant papers. These were abstract reviewed independently by two reviewers with papers meeting the inclusion criteria subjected to data extraction. Results 33 publications (32 papers and one book chapter) were included which contained 32 distinct methodologies. The majority of these methodologies (n = 22) can be classed as either dialogical or consultative, and these represent two extreme ‘poles’ of methodological orientation. Consideration of these results provoked three central questions that are central to the planning of an empirical bioethics study, and revolve around how a normative conclusion can be justified, the analytic process through which that conclusion is reached, and the kind of conclusion that is sought. Conclusion When considering which methodology or research methods to adopt in any particular study, researchers need to think carefully about the nature of the claims they wish to generate through their analyses, and how these claims align with the aims of the research. Whilst there are superficial similarities in the ways that identical research methods are made use of, the different meta-ethical and epistemological commitments that undergird the range of methodological approaches adopted rehearse many of the central foundational disagreements that play out within moral philosophy and bioethical analysis more broadly. There is little common ground that transcends these disagreements, and we argue that this is likely to present a challenge for the legitimacy of the bioethical enterprise. We conclude, however, that this heterogeneity ought to be welcomed, but urge those involved in the field to engage meaningfully and explicitly with questions concerning what kinds of moral claim they want to be able to make, about normative justification and the methodological process, and about the coherence of these components within their work.
Chapter
Ethical discourse draws upon information from various disciplines to promote normative conclusions. In this chapter, we review one particular method—the contrastive vignette technique (CVT)—that has been fruitfully used as a quantitative means of exploring public attitudes towards ethically challenging issues. The chapter serves as a practical guide to the design and use of CVT in neuroethical inquiry, a technique we term experimental neuroethics.