Content uploaded by Shai Stern
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Shai Stern on Mar 07, 2021
Content may be subject to copyright.
Available via license: CC BY-NC-ND 4.0
Content may be subject to copyright.
Shai Stern is professor of law at Bar Ilan University, Israel.
© 2021 Russell Sage Foundation. Stern, Shai. 2021. “‘Separate, Therefore Equal’: American Spatial Segregation
from Jim Crow to Kiryas Joel.” RSF: The Russell Sage Foundation Journal of the Social Sciences 7(1): 67–90. DOI:
10.7758/RSF.2021.7.1.05. I am grateful for the substantial feedback I have received from numerous colleagues,
including Omri Ben Zvi, Lee Cahaner, Hanoch Dagan, Tsilly Dagan, Shahar Lifshitz, Avital Margalit, Miriam
Marcowitz- Bitton, Manal Totry- Jubran, Masua Sagiv, Samuel C. Heilman, and the participants of the colloquium
of public law at the Hebrew University in Jerusalem. All opinions expressed in this article represent those of the
author and all errors in this paper are solely the responsibility of the author. Direct correspondence to: Shai Stern
at shai.stern@biu.ac.il, Bar Ilan University, Ramat Gan, 5290002, Israel.
Open Access Policy: RSF: The Russell Sage Foundation Journal of the Social Sciences is an open access journal.
This article is published under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial- NoDerivs 3.0 Unported Li-
cense.
lic services, no one does not take up space.
Thus, although segregation in some areas may
affect sections of the population, spatial segre-
gation affects the entire population. Second,
given the physical characteristics of space, spa-
tial segregation can be more clearly identified,
diagnosed, and measured than in other spheres
(Massey and Denton ). Third, control of
space and its distribution is a prime source for
the development of segregation and discrimi-
nation on other levels (Massey ; powell
; Acevedo- Garcia and Lochner ; Klar-
“Separate, Therefore Equal”:
American Spatial Segregation
from Jim Crow to Kiryas Joel
In rejecting Plessy v. Ferguson’s “separate but equal” doctrine in Brown v. Board of Education, the U.S.
Supreme Court created a presumption that segregation equals discrimination. However, alongside this as-
sertion, American space has become increasingly separate. A socio- legal analysis identifies three generations
of spatial segregation in the United States and calls for recognizing the fourth generation—separate, there-
fore equal—in which minority communities require voluntary self- segregation to achieve equality. This
fourth generation of spatial separation requires the law to embrace a protective role, by which it will defend
the ability of minority communities to segregate spatially, the autonomy of individual community members,
and the welfare of the society at large.
Keywords: segregation, “separate but equal,” Kiryas Joel, ultra- Orthodox, First Amendment
“Separate,
Therefore Equal”
Spatial segregation involves the “separation of
socially defined groups in space, such that
members of one group are disproportionately
concentrated in a particular set of geographic
units compared with other groups in the popu-
lation” (Massey, Rothwell, and Domina ,
). Although the segregation of social groups
is present and expressed in a wide range of
fields and spheres, spatial segregation carries
with it the unique characteristic that every per-
son needs a living space in the first instance.
Unlike other spheres, such as education or pub-
rsf: the russell sage foundation journal of the social sciences
man ; Myers, Darity, and Marsh ;
Bischoff and Reardon ; Williams and Col-
lins ). Finally, spatial separation presents
unique difficulties related to the possible repa-
ration of historical distortions (Rothstein ).
Therefore, although spatial segregation is both
influenced by and affects the separation of so-
cial groups in other spheres, its unique charac-
teristics enable a distinct socio- legal investiga-
tion into the role of the law in establishing and
maintaining spatial separation. This analysis
enables the identification of three generations
of American spatial segregation; in each, the
law plays a different role in the construction of
space. The different roles the law plays in these
three generations enable the operation of dif-
ferent mechanisms and form a different per-
ception of spatial justice (Soja ). Several
caveats are important to recognize. First, this
article is socio- legal and thus does not pretend
to be absolute or ultimate. A socio- legal ap-
proach analyzes the law as directly linked to the
analysis of the social situation to which the law
applies and examines the role that the law plays
in creating, maintaining, and changing the so-
cial situation (Schiff ). Such analysis recog-
nizes other possible classifications and catego-
rizations of space construction and separation
in American space. Its aim is to contribute to
the understanding of separation in American
society in general and separation in space in
particular, a perspective that enables a discus-
sion on the various functions of law and its im-
pact on society and space. Second, although
analysis of American space cannot ignore the
powerful governmental and private economic
mechanisms used to preserve space separation
(Gotham a; Klarman ; Lamb ;
Massey ; Brooks and Rose ; Rothstein
; Taylor ), the goal here is to provide a
socio- legal examination of spatial processes.
Thus the article does not include in- depth anal-
ysis of the mechanisms and economic mea-
surements that have affected it. The analysis
instead offers a broad- brush characterization
of the role of law in each generation. In each
period, instances sometimes contradict the
main characteristics of the generation. These
instances are discussed as part of the bigger
picture.
The first generation of American spatial segre-
gation began with the founding of the United
States and lasted until the Court’s decision in
Plessy v. Ferguson.
Over this extended period,
American society underwent significant
changes and transformations, both politically
and economically. The decision to include this
period within a single generation is based on
the similarities in both the social groups in-
volved and the characteristics of spatial separa-
tion. Throughout the period, racial subordina-
tion was prevalent in most spheres of American
life (Smith ; Omi and Winant ). Rela-
tionships between social groups have been ex-
amined in a prism of slavery, its abolition, and
the social and economic processes that fol-
lowed abolition (Woodward and McFeely ,
; Van Cleve ; Guelzo ; Rael ). Ab-
olition did not end racial subordination in
American society; in fact, in a variety of areas,
subordination remained and even intensified
(Smith ). It is therefore surprising to find
that, in terms of space, separation was relatively
marginal (DuBois ; Weaver ; Bauman
; Woodward and McFeely ). The data
show that until the end of the nineteenth cen-
tury, separation in the American space was rel-
atively low, and separate neighborhoods in ur-
ban or rural environments were not the norm
(Weaver ; Kushner ; Cutler, Glaeser,
and Vigdor ). The literature suggests a
number of explanations for this, the most
prominent being that spatial segregation would
have been an inconvenience and an obstruc-
tion to slavery (Taeuber and Taeuber ;
Woodward and McFeely , ). Recognition
that space was integrated does not contradict
the systematic race- based discrimination and
subordination practiced throughout the first
generation; on the contrary, integration was
one of the constitutive components of the ra-
cial subordination system (Woodward and
1. Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.S. 537 (1896).
rsf: the russell sage foundation journal of the social sciences
,
McFeely , ). The role of law in the first
generation was therefore less concerned with
racial segregation and more with preserving
and legitimizing racial inequality and subordi-
nation. The spatial concept dominating Amer-
ican space during the first generation was thus
“unequal though integrated.” The abolition of
slavery, alongside the ratification of the Thir-
teenth, Fourteenth, and Fifteenth Amend-
ments to the Constitution between and
not only changed the formal legal status
of African Americans throughout the United
States, but also marked a substantive change
in the role the law played in the construction
of space.
This undermining of the racial subordina-
tion system led southern states and local gov-
ernments to create legislation that enforced
racial segregation (Kennedy ). Racial seg-
regation, therefore, enabled white suprema-
cists to preserve the discriminatory and sub-
ordinate racial system that had been lost with
the abolition of slavery and the enactment of
constitutional amendments (Emerson ;
Klarman ; Brown and Webb , –;
Brooks and Rose ). Jim Crow laws man-
dated racial segregation in all public facilities
in southern states from the s and s for-
ward (Brown and Webb ; Woodward and
McFeely , ). In , the Supreme Court
approved the discriminative concept underly-
ing these laws, rejecting constitutional chal-
lenges against the discrimination they would
generate. In Plessy v. Ferguson, the Court estab-
lished the “separate but equal” doctrine, which
suggested that as long as the facilities provided
to each race were equal, state and local govern-
ments could apply policies that separated dif-
ferent races (Klarman ). In this sense,
Plessy v. Ferguson is the mirror image of the
law’s role; whereas the aim in the first genera-
tion was to legitimize racial inequality rather
than to be concerned with spatial segregation,
in the second generation, the law, which was
bound to constitutional equality duties, not
only approved but also facilitated racial segre-
gation. Therefore, Plessy v. Ferguson marks the
beginning of the second generation in Ameri-
can spatial separation, in which allegedly
equally funded segregation had become legiti-
mate, if not worthy (Klarman ). Although
Plessy v. Ferguson did not deal with spatial sep-
aration per se, its impact on spatial and resi-
dential separation was significant. The reason
is that the ruling—although not directly deal-
ing with spatial separation—established the
principle that guided the Supreme Court
throughout the entire second generation, ac-
cording to which racial segregation, in itself, is
not legally ineligible. Implementing Plessy v.
Ferguson’s insight into the spatial dimension
was accomplished through two landmark
Supreme Court cases. In Village of Euclid v. Am-
bler Realty Co., the Court provided municipali-
ties with the right to zone land use. The Court
found that the government had a valid interest
in maintaining the character of a neighborhood
and in regulating where certain land uses
should occur. In Corrigan v. Buckley, the Court
ruled that a racially restrictive covenant was a
legally binding document.
These two cases in
-
corporated Plessy v. Ferguson’s insight regard-
ing the legality of segregation into the spatial
plane and affirmed discriminatory and separa-
tive spatial practices. Data show that American
cities in were not exceptionally segregated
(Weaver ; Cutler, Glaeser, and Vigdor ).
However, the rapid spread of the Jim Crow laws,
now constitutionally backed by the Supreme
Court, changed the American space, making it
more segregated than it ever had been (Cutler,
Glaeser, and Vigdor ; Massey, Rothwell, and
Domina ). In the South, the abolition of
slavery and the expansion of white supremacy
sentiments increased spatial separation in the
main cities (Taeuber and Taeuber ; Emer-
son ). In the North, where demand for labor
in industrial cities was strong, an influx of
southern African Americans escaping the Jim
Crow laws settled in separate areas within the
cities (Scott ; Cutler, Glaeser, and Vigdor
). The spatial separation in the North was
a result not only of prejudices on the part of
veteran residents, but also economic and social
2. Village of Euclid, Ohio v. Ambler Realty Co., 272 U.S. 365 (1926).
3. Corrigan v. Buckley, 271 U.S. 323 (1926).
rsf: the russell sage foundation journal of the social sciences
4. Buchanan v. Warley, 245 U.S. 60 (1917).
5. Brown v. Board of Education of Topeka, 347 U.S. 483 (1954).
6. Shelley v. Kraemer, 334 U.S. 1 (1948).
considerations on the part of the migrants
(Weaver ; Lieberson ; Klarman ).
The legal backing for spatial segregation
granted by the Supreme Court in Plessy v. Fer-
guson, Village of Euclid v. Ambler Realty Co., and
Corrigan v. Buckley found expression in a variety
of legal practices, which were designed to es-
tablish and maintain this separation. To pre-
vent racial spatial integration, local govern-
ments made use of racial zoning ordinance
(Aloi, Goldberg, and White ; Rabin ;
Silver ), as well as enforcing racially restric-
tive covenants (Dean ; Jones- Correa ;
Gotham b). Although racial zoning ordi-
nances were declared unconstitutional by the
Supreme Court in Buchanan v. Warley as early
as , courts constantly rejected challenges
to the enforcement of racially restrictive cove-
nants (Brooks and Rose ). These practices
were widespread by , and all the major in-
dustrial centers in the North had ghettos,
which kept African Americans segregated spa-
tially (Massey and Denton ; Cutler, Glaeser,
and Vigdor ). The Supreme Court’s support
for segregation, even if purportedly only with
equal funding, as well as its legitimization of
discriminatory and spatially segregating prac-
tices, made the law an active agent in the imple-
mentation of spatial segregation. In the second
generation, therefore, the law facilitated the
creation and maintenance of racial- based spa-
tial segregation (Klarman ).
The third generation of spatial segregation
began with the Supreme Court’s rejection of
the “separate but equal” doctrine in Brown v.
Board of Education. Aer more than half a cen-
tury of steady rise in the rate of spatial separa-
tion, the Court in Brown ruled that racially
based separation should be considered categor-
ically as discrimination and therefore as uncon-
stitutional. However, it can be argued that this
was only the symbolic beginning of the third
generation, for two reasons. First, although the
“separate but equal” doctrine was officially re-
jected in Brown, from a spatial perspective, this
ruling was preceded by another in Shelley v.
Kraemer. Here, the Supreme Court forbade ra-
cially restrictive housing covenants, denying
the ability of state authorities, including courts,
to enforce racial segregation, though it was pri-
vately initiated (Brooks and Rose ). As Rich-
ard Rothstein argues, Shelley v. Kraemer was to
spatial segregation what Brown was to educa-
tion (). Second, the first practical expres-
sion of the principled determination given in
Brown came only aer more than a decade, in
the enactment of civil rights laws that outlawed
housing discrimination based on race, color,
religion, sex, or national origin. But Brown’s
symbolism is important not only in the ques-
tion of the starting point of the third genera-
tion, but also in the role of the law in perpetu-
ating spatial separation in this generation. The
third generation of American spatial segrega-
tion is distinct from the previous two concern-
ing both the social groups involved and the role
that the law played in perpetuating separation
in space. Unlike the previous generations, the
third generation of American spatial separation
made the issue of separation more extensive in
all aspects related to the social groups involved.
Thus, whereas the first two generations focused
on race- and ethnicity- based segregation, the
third expanded the potential for spatial segre-
gation along economic lines (Abramson, Tobin,
and VanderGoot ; Jargowsky ; Massey
and Fischer ; Massey ). Shiing the ba-
sis for spatial separation from race and ethnic-
ity to income widens the circle of those involved
in spatial separation, although differences in
income level are oen proxies for racial and
ethnic affiliation (Reeves, Rodrigue, and Knee-
bone ). This ongoing change in the basis
for segregation, however, was a direct result of
the role the law played in the third generation.
The beginning of the third generation was
encouraging in terms of the role of law in the
construction of space. On a declarative, consti-
tutional level, the law denied the legitimacy of
segregation and established the legal presump-
tion that separation is categorically unequal.
Brown was followed by several important civil
rsf: the russell sage foundation journal of the social sciences
,
7. Pub.L. 88–352, 78 Stat. 241, enacted July 2, 1964.
8. Pub.L. 90–284, 82 Stat. 73, enacted April 11, 1968.
9. Jones v. Alfred H. Mayer Co., 392 U.S. 409 (1968).
rights laws, which had a significant impact on
American society. These laws, especially the
Civil Rights Act of and the Fair Housing
Act of , changed basic principles in Amer-
ican law and outlawed discrimination with re-
gard to residence or employment on grounds
of race, color, religion, gender, and national
origin. However, although in its constitutional
capacity the law rejected separation and advo-
cated equality, in its private capacity it legiti-
mized separation and arguably turned it into a
constitutive feature of the American space. In
this sense, the law created a gap between the
declarative dimension and the practical one.
The prohibitions on discrimination and segre-
gation, which the law established on a public-
constitutional level, disappeared when they
were implemented in private law. The public-
private distinction was introduced for the first
time at Shelley v. Kraemer, which allowed racial
restrictive covenants but forbade their state en-
forcement. However, even aer the enactment
of the Fair Housing Act, which prohibited dis-
crimination on a private level, various exemp-
tions were prescribed in the act itself that al-
lowed the preservation and perpetuation of
spatial separation (Schwemm ; Walsh ;
powell ). These exemptions continue to al-
low spatial separation despite the Supreme
Court ruling in Jones v. Alfred H. Mayer Co.
that
overturned Corrigan v. Buckley and upheld the
constitutionality of the Fair Housing Act. The
public- private distinction led to a number of
significant spatial processes, the effects of
which are still evident in the American space.
One of these processes is known as white flight,
the large- scale migration of white populations
from racially mixed urban areas to more racially
homogeneous suburban regions (Frey ;
Conley ; Woldoff ). Although the rea-
sons for the white migration are varied (Frey
), the legal possibility of limiting entry into
residential projects by private proprietary
mechanisms has enabled the preservation of
separation between the suburbs and urban
space (Rothstein ). Another interrelated
spatial process was the flourishing of home-
owners associations (HOAs); private associa-
tions formed for managing residential subdivi-
sion. HOAs were first established in the United
States in the mid- nineteenth century but flour-
ished in the third generation of spatial segrega-
tion (Reichman ; Ellickson ; Brooks
and Rose ). Along with the development in
infrastructure and transportation, the main
reason for the frequent use of HOAs since the
s was their identification as frameworks for
exclusion and spatial separation, which were
protected by private law (Ellickson ; Massey
and Denton , ; Ford ; Roithmayr
). Another process that has gained momen-
tum since the s is gentrification; the spatial
process of changing the character of neighbor-
hoods through the influx of more affluent resi-
dents and businesses (Smith ; Lees, Slater,
and Wyly ). Gentrification oen increases
the economic value of a neighborhood but
forces low- income residents out because of the
increased cost of rent and goods (Smith ;
Boyd ; Goetz ; Lees, Slater, and Wyly
). This involuntary residential displace-
ment of economically weak population groups
is a prominent expression of the third genera-
tion of American spatial segregation (powell
and Spencer ). It is the result of the aban-
donment of space for private law and the mar-
ket forces which, despite the declarations of
integration and equality, establish and perpet-
uate spatial segregation on the ground. The
third generation of American spatial separation
is ongoing; income- based separation is becom-
ing both rooted in the American space and an
integral part of social stratification in the
United States (Massey and Eggers ; Abram-
son, Tobin, and VanderGoot ; Fischer ;
Reardon and Bischoff ). The characteristics
of the three generations of American spatial
separation (table ) reveal significant differ-
ences in terms of the basis for separation and
the mechanisms used to implement it.
At the same time however, it seems that the
United States has recently entered the fourth
Table 1. Three Generations of American Spatial Segregation
Generation De Jure De Facto Segregation Bases
Legal Instruments
Applied
Milestone
Supreme Court
Rulings
Segregation
Mechanisms
First Unequal though
integrated
Low-level
segregation
Racial-based
subordination
Thirteenth, Fourteenth,
and Fifteenth
Amendments
Racial subordination
through slavery
Second Separate but equal High-level
segregation
Racial-based
segregation
Jim Crow laws Plessy v.
Ferguson
Separation in public
facilities
transportation,
schools, hotels, and
restaurants
Third Separate is inherently
unequal
High-level
segregation
Racial, ethnic, and
economic based
segregation
Civil Rights Act of
Civil Rights Act of
Shelley v. Kraemer
Brown v. Board of
Education
Private law
mechanisms HOA,
gated communities,
restrictive covenants
Suburbanization and
local policies white
flight
Federal policies
redlining mortgages
Source: Author’s tabulation.
rsf: the russell sage foundation journal of the social sciences
,
generation of spatial separation, a generation
characterized by the voluntary separation of
minority groups holding a distinct religious or
cultural conception of the good.
:
In a referendum held in November in the
upstate New York town of Monroe, the majority
of residents voted to separate from the village
of Kiryas Joel. This decision ended a long pe-
riod of clashes between the two groups of resi-
dents, which was mainly related to cultural dif-
ferences between the two populations. It also
marked the beginning of the fourth generation
of spatial separation in the United States.
To understand the depth of the differences
between the two social groups involved, we
need to look closely at the Kiryas Joel commu-
nity and its defining characteristics. Kiryas Joel
was founded in the early s as a semi- rural
outpost of the Satmar Hasidic sect based in
Brooklyn, and grew rapidly, creating the need
for multifamily housing and additional land for
it (Stolzenberg ; Grumet, Caher, and Kaye
). The Satmar are the largest, most devoted
Hasidic community in America (Mintz ; Ru-
bin ). Even among ultra- Orthodox sects, it
is considered one of the most zealous in its im
-
plementation of Jewish law and opposition to
reforms or innovation (Magid ; Wood and
Watt ). The Satmar brought their way of life
with them from Hungary to Brooklyn aer
World War II, where the separation of religion
and state, combined with Brooklyn’s housing
opportunities, enabled the expanding Satmar
community and other Central European Jewish
immigrants to establish isolated, illiberal com-
munities that functioned independently of
many state- regulated structures (Rubin ).
Satmar families, eschewing birth control, typi-
cally have eight to ten children (Mintz ;
Wood and Watt ; Stolzenberg ). They
speak Yiddish, dress in long clothes to avoid
revealing body parts in public, engage in full
gender separation outside the home, and gen-
erally refrain from consuming American media
or publications that do not come from within
the community (Minow ).
The Satmar community proliferated so rap-
idly that lack of housing acted as a catalyst for
the establishment of the second location
of the Satmar sect in the town of Monroe, New
York. This community was named Kiryas Joel
(Stolzenberg ; Minow ; Myers ).
The establishment of the village of Kiryas Joel
symbolized not only a split in the American Sat-
mar community but also a turning point in the
community’s struggle for spatial separation
(Stolzenberg ; Minow ; Myers ).
The village saw value in convergence within it-
self, providing for its needs autonomously, and
maintaining spatial and social separation from
external populations. These characteristics nat-
urally led to a distance between residents of the
village of Kiryas Joel and residents of the town
of Monroe, so that even before the referendum
on municipal separation, the residents of
Kiryas Joel were spatially and culturally sepa-
rated. At the same time, attempts to obtain le-
gal approval for this separation were repeatedly
rejected.
The most striking legal confrontation con-
cerned the Kiryas Joel residents’ aspirations to
establish a separate and independent board of
education. Although most of the village chil-
dren attended private schools that were gender
segregated in accordance with the religious
norms of the community, the children who had
disabilities were sent to a Monroe public
school. Because of Monroe’s refusal to gender
segregate its public school, the New York legis-
lature authorized Kiryas Joel to establish a pub-
lic school that would serve the village’s children
with disabilities. Citizen taxpayers and the New
York School Board Association sued, claiming
that the statute creating this special school dis-
trict was not neutral and violated the require-
ment to separate church and state as mandated
by the First Amendment. The case went to the
Supreme Court, which in Board of Ed. of Kiryas
Joel Village School Dist. v. Grumet ruled that the
special school district gave too much authority
over a secular function of society to a religious
group and unconstitutionally delegated a secu
-
lar function to a religious body. The New York
legislature responded by adopting new legisla-
tion that appeared to be more general and more
neutral, but the suit was also taken to the Su-
preme Court. The Grumet case is one promi-
nent example among many of the tension be-
rsf: the russell sage foundation journal of the social sciences
tween the two social groups, which arose from
fundamental differences in their worldviews
and ways of life. The case also attests to the fact
that spatial and cultural separation existed be-
tween the village of Kiryas Joel and the town of
Monroe even before the referendum. How-
ever, I argue that the municipal separation, to
which both the residents of Monroe and the
residents of Kiryas Joel agreed, marked a new
era of spatial separation in the United States.
The reason for seeing Kiryas Joel’s case as
the beginning of the fourth generation of
American spatial separation is not that the sep-
aration between the groups was allegedly vol-
untary. Consider another case of an alleged vol-
untary separation—St. George and East Baton
Rouge Parish, Louisiana. In October , aer
years of trying to create a separate school sys-
tem, residents of a white suburb of Baton
Rouge voted to become a new city called St.
George. Fiy- four percent of voters in the com-
munity approved the amendment, but other
Baton Rouge residents were not allowed to ex-
press their position (due to state laws). St.
George was accordingly incorporated as a sep-
arate city and gained control over its taxes and
schools (Wilson ). Although the case of St.
George is timely and occurs, expectedly or not,
in Louisiana, which has been the focus of
Plessy v. Ferguson, it is not a unique case. Ac-
cording to recent research, most of the cases
in which communities aim to self- segregate
themselves from their parish do so to control
their taxes and school systems (Wilson ;
EdBuild ; Taylor, Frankenberg, and Siegel-
Hawley ). Thus, states set different statu-
tory processes for school district secessions
that isolate students and resources (Shoked
; Wilson ; EdBuild ). Thirty states
have a policy defined in law. Some require ac-
tions by voters; others require the state’s ap-
proval and even constitutional amendment.
Since , no fewer than seventy- three U.S.
communities have attempted to secede from
schools in an effort to strengthen resources
(EdBuild ). Some, like St. George, aimed to
achieve school segregation by promoting mu-
nicipal secession.
The case of St. George and similar commu-
nities that struggle to segregate themselves
from their less affluent surrounding parishes
should not be considered as part of the fourth
generation because for the most part they have
maintained the characteristics of segregation
in previous generations. Thus, St. George, a
largely white and more affluent suburb of Baton
Rouge, seeks to separate spatially from the ma-
jority of nonwhite, less affluent residents of the
East Baton Rouge Parish (Runnels ). Spatial
separation is promoted by the powerful to
avoid integration with the less powerful on ra-
cial and economic grounds. These are precisely
the characteristics of the separation against
which the Brown Court came out, and the same
bases for separation in the post- Brown genera-
tion. Therefore, seeing such a separation, de-
spite being ostensibly voluntary, as one that
deserves any protection cannot be justified.
The case of Kiryas Joel, however, is quite dif-
ferent.
The reason to view the municipal separation
of Kiryas Joel and the town of Monroe as the
beginning of the fourth generation of American
spatial segregation is that it altered the roles of
the social groups involved as well as the legal
and social implications of this decision. The
official separation of the village from the town
created, in practice, the first town in the United
States exclusively for ultra- Orthodox Jews. Mov-
ing to the present day, the new town of Palm
Tree is expected to be run according to the rules
and the religious norms held by residents of
Kiryas Joel. These norms, as well as the charac-
teristics of the residents, are expected to affect
the town’s zoning laws—to emphasize apart-
ments for large families as well as the provision
of public institutions for study and ritual—and
the educational institutions and the norms ac-
cording to which they will operate (Minow
). Therefore, the establishment of Palm
Tree marks the emergence of a new generation
of segregation in the American space, one that
differs from the three generations that pre-
ceded it. This fourth generation is not based on
race, religion, ethnicity, or income. Instead, the
social groups involved are, respectively, a ma-
jority group in American society and a minority
community that seeks to live in accordance
with its unique, oen illiberal norms. In the
case of Kiryas Joel, the group is defined as a
minority because of its religious affiliation, but
future cases that rely on the Kiryas Joel prece-
rsf: the russell sage foundation journal of the social sciences
,
dent will not necessarily be limited to religious
minorities. Indeed, the fourth generation pro-
vides the opportunity for various minority com-
munities—religious, ethnic, cultural, and even
economic—to demand spatial separation from
the majority group. Focusing on the majority-
minority tension justifies viewing the Satmar
community’s struggle for spatial segregation as
manifesting a fourth generation of American
spatial separation and not just as another link
in the historical chain of religious communities
seeking to differentiate on a religious basis.
American history is replete with multiple strug-
gles on behalf of religious communities to
maintain their religious practices and to pre-
serve their religious freedom. Kiryas Joel’s sep-
aration illustrates a broader struggle for spatial
autonomy that does not settle for religious free-
dom but instead demands a spatial expression
of government.
Placing the majority- minority tension at the
core of the fourth generation of American spa-
tial segregation, however, requires us to recog-
nize that Kiryas Joel is not the first case where
this tension was the basis for a claim. African
American separatists opposed integration and
called for the concept of self- segregation of
blacks out of community empowerment (Ham-
ilton and Ture ; Hall ; Pettigrew ).
In the late nineteenth and early twentieth cen-
turies, African American activists established
several black- only towns, believing that blacks
would never find peace or prosperity living in
white- dominated areas. The assumption be-
hind such towns—such as Boley and Langston
in Oklahoma and Mound Bayou in Missis-
sippi—was that only by controlling the govern-
mental institutions would the empowerment
of the community be possible (Meier ; Tol-
son ; Stuckey ). Almost a century later,
minority communities in East Palo Alto, Cali-
fornia, and Boston, Massachusetts, made sev-
eral efforts to incorporate as independent mu-
nicipalities (Goel et al. ). These attempts,
though abandoned eventually, were symptom-
atic of the negative reaction to the implementa-
tion of integration that had been guaranteed
by law in the third generation of American spa-
tial segregation, as well as the desire to assert
political control over their community (Goel et
al. ). However, these separatist calls and
self- segregation attempts were rejected, either
because of the belief that segregation is un-
equal and inappropriate or a more practical un-
derstanding that granting such a possibility
would make it possible to preserve the discrim-
inatory situation in effect at the time. The fail-
ure of previous self- segregation attempts,
therefore, should be attributed to the message
conveyed by both Plessy v. Ferguson and Brown
v. Board of Education. Although these two judg-
ments did not deal directly with spatial separa-
tion, they did link separation and equality. In
that sense, the judgments made segregation
the ultimate cause for inequality in American
society. Although the place of racial- , religious-,
ethnic- , or income- based segregation in creat-
ing and preserving inequality in American so-
ciety is undisputable, labeling it as the ultimate
and perhaps even the only cause of inequality
is problematic for two reasons. First, it hides
other political, economic, and social causes of
inequality and therefore prevents those causes
from being identified and treated. Second, and
more important, it does not allow for a more
distinct observation of the circumstances of
each case (Bayer, Fang, and McMillan ). Set-
ting an irrefutable presumption that segrega-
tion is unequal denies claims for spatial separa-
tion that may not only not harm equality but
instead—as in self- segregation claims on behalf
of suppressed minority communities—en-
hance it.
The Kiryas Joel case changed this common
understanding by allowing minority communi-
ties to segregate themselves voluntarily from
general American society. In this sense, the
fourth generation opens anew the discussion
about the applicability of the Plessy v. Fergu-
son’s “separate but equal” doctrine in American
spatial policy. However, it not only reinforces
the debate but also suggests that the imple-
mentation of this doctrine may be legitimate
and even desired if a minority community re-
quests it. The fourth generation, therefore,
presents a different concept of spatial justice
in which a separate space may be required for
a minority community to gain equality. Spatial
separation, therefore, is no longer an obstacle
to equality but instead a condition for it—in
other words, “separate, therefore equal.” This
is, of course, a meaningful change in the Amer-
rsf: the russell sage foundation journal of the social sciences
10. United States v. Fordice, 505 U.S. 717 (1992).
ican spatial policy, one that has both legal and
social implications.
Kiryas Joel was the first town to be incorpo-
rated as an ultra- Orthodox- only settlement, but
many other towns face a similar threat. The ex-
perience of New York towns such as East Ra-
mapo and Bloomingburg and New Jersey towns
such as Riverdale, Mahwah, Jackson, Upper
Saddle River, and Montvale is much the same
as what led to Kiryas Joel’s municipal separa-
tion. In all these cases, the ultra- Orthodox com-
munity argues that segregation will reflect
justice and equality by serving the unique com-
munity’s needs. “Separate, therefore equal” is
slowly becoming a normative claim for spatial
justice for many communities (see table A).
The return to the forefront of the legitimate
connection between separation and equality in
space poses significant legal challenges and re-
quires investigation of its implications for so-
ciety as a whole, for the segregated community,
and for the individual members of the commu-
nity. This examination must be based on argu-
ments about the justifications of or objections
to the spatial separation of minority communi-
ties, as discussed in the following section.
-
Can the spatial segregation of minority com-
munities, especially those organized around il-
liberal norms, be socially and legally justified?
Should the liberal state allow such segregation,
or should it struggle to prevent it? Should the
fact that the segregation is voluntary affect the
answer to these questions?
Stronger Alone: Empowerment
Minorities have oen been the victims of spa-
tial and residential segregation (Nelson ;
Seitles ). As Douglas Massey, Jonathan
Rothwell, and Thurston Domina demonstrate,
minorities such as African Americans, Latinos,
and Asians were the most prominent victims of
spatial separation, based, at least until the
s, on race and ethnicity (; Jennings
). The change in the characteristics of
American spatial segregation, from that based
on race and ethnicity to that based on income,
did not significantly change the location of mi-
norities in this equation. Then, as today, mi-
norities in American society lived with spatial
exclusion (Yinger ; Seitles ; Trifun
) as well as repeated attempts by govern-
ment and private parties to create spatial sepa-
ration (Trifun ). The social and legal battle
to diminish racial and ethnic spatial segrega-
tion in the United States was primarily the bat-
tle of minorities seeking to be considered as
equals in society (Valocchi ). The rejection
of the “separate but equal” doctrine has been a
significant yet symbolic milestone in the strug-
gle for equality for minorities in the United
States, in effect declaring that a worthy society
cannot legitimize separation between people
because of their racial, ethnic, or religious dif-
ference. The Court’s legal declaration in Brown
celebrates equality and inclusiveness. It failed
to recognize, however, that sometimes spatial
separation empowers minorities instead of
marginalizing them.
Attempts to prevent racial and ethnic spatial
segregation over the years led both state and
local governments to adopt inclusive spatial
policies, such as subsidized housing, inclusion-
ary zoning, and restrictions on discrimination.
In response to these efforts, some scholars ar-
gue that in the quest for equality, the right of
minorities to not integrate was obscured. The
law, as expressed in the Supreme Court ruling
in United States v. Fordice—where Justice Clar-
ence Thomas’s concurring opinion suggesting
that historically black colleges should not be
destroyed or severed of their traditions and
histories was not adopted by the opinion of
the Court—showed little tolerance for these
claims. However, scholars as well as social ac-
tivists suggest that in some cases segregation
may be desirable (Jennings ). Take, for ex-
ample, a situation in which integration strips
the minority community of essential character-
istics, history, and values (Goel et al. ; Jen-
nings ). Another argument is that separa-
tion may in times empower minorities, whether
because they are able to preserve their history
and values, or because they may develop a
sense of belonging and social affiliation (Brooks
; Tomlins ; Kaplan and Woodhouse
rsf: the russell sage foundation journal of the social sciences
,
). The empowerment justification was at
the core of both the black separatism move-
ment of the s and the incorporation at-
tempts of black communities in the s.
These arguments still find expression in the re-
cent flourishing of Afrocentric schools in
Brooklyn, New York. Approximately six Afro-
centric schools in Brooklyn, in which about
, children are enrolled, decided to provide
African American children with an educa-
tional framework that would celebrate black
culture and history. As Rafiq Kalam Id- Din II,
the founder of the Ember Charter School, de-
scribed its mission, “Everything you do needs
to be focused on agency and empowerment”
(Shapiro ).
Segregation as empowerment justifies spa-
tial segregation when it contributes to a minor-
ity’s ability to flourish. This understanding
echoes some of the arguments on behalf of
multiculturalism, which support limited segre-
gation of minorities from general society. How-
ever, the empowerment justification depends
on the characteristics of the community and
the need, insofar as it exists, for spatial segrega-
tion to preserve those characteristics. Such a
demand must come from the minority commu-
nity and cannot be imposed by an external
party (Goel et al. ). The significance of these
qualifications is that the empowerment justifi-
cation for spatial segregation cannot and
should not be broadly exercised. It requires a
careful examination of the circumstances of
each case and the characteristics of each com-
munity.
Live and Let Live: Pluralism
Another justification for the spatial segregation
of minority communities is rooted in a funda-
mental pluralistic approach, which imposes a
duty on liberal states to allow all citizens to live
their lives in accordance with whatever concept
of good they deem appropriate (Anderson ;
Stern ). At the core of this approach is the
understanding that every person may hold dif-
ferent beliefs and values. Elizabeth Anderson
identifies this principle, saying that “people ex-
perience the world as infused with many differ-
ent values” (, ). She also explains that the
state should therefore be obligated to allow all
people to live by their values through the estab-
lishment of diverse social institutions, which
people can use to promote these values (Ander-
son ; Stern ). Anderson thus argues
that the state has an obligation “to expand the
range of significant opportunities open to its
citizens by supporting institutions that enable
them to govern themselves by the norms inter-
nal to the modes of valuation appropriate to
different kinds of goods” (, ).
Applying Anderson’s pluralistic approach to
the spatial discourse means that the liberal
state must be prepared to allow spatial segrega-
tion if it contributes to individuals’ actualiza-
tion of their values and norms (Stolzenberg
). It also requires the state to preserve the
ability of all individuals and communities to
realize their values and norms and therefore
should be done in a way that prevents external-
izing one group’s norms over another’s (Stern
). The case of Kiryas Joel is a good example
of the pluralistic justification. The ultra-
Orthodox community of Kiryas Joel maintains
strict adherence to halakhah (Jewish religious
law), which affects all aspects of their lives,
from spiritual concepts to everyday life (Mintz
; Norgren and Nanda ). To maintain
their religious worldview in accord with the
community, members of the community can-
not integrate with institutions in general soci-
ety (Rubin ). It was no accident that the
main legal event in which the Kiryas Joel com-
munity was involved had to do with the schools
to which the community sent its children (Ru-
bin ). A community that meticulously pre-
serves gender segregation in its schools cannot
exercise its religious worldview if the commu-
nity’s children enroll in mixed- gender institu-
tions (Mintz ). It should not be surprising,
therefore, that the tension related to the edu-
cational institutions between the residents of
Monroe and the residents of Kiryas Joel eventu-
ally led to a decision on separation. Thus the
community’s requirements for maintaining its
values and norms give rise to the pluralistic jus-
tification for spatial segregation.
The pluralistic justification and the empow-
erment justification have certain similarities.
Both seek to enable communities to preserve
their characteristics, values, and norms. Nei-
ther applies to forced spatial segregation, but
instead conditions separation on the commu-
rsf: the russell sage foundation journal of the social sciences
nity’s free will or demand. However, the two
justifications also differ. The most prominent
of these differences relates to the characteris-
tics of communities that may require spatial seg-
regation. The empowerment justification holds
that only minority communities that have his-
torically experienced oppression, discrimina-
tion, and exclusion by a majority population
should be permitted to implement spatial seg-
regation in the name of empowerment. The le-
gitimization of spatial segregation, a policy per-
ceived as discriminatory and socially harmful,
stems from a long history of discrimination
and exclusion. According to this justification,
minority communities can now correct past in-
justices by using tools to which they are accus-
tomed. It is different, however, if the pluralistic
justification is examined. The pluralistic justi-
fication holds that spatial segregation is not
unique to minority communities. Any commu-
nity whose unique characteristics and ability to
realize that its members’ worldview requires
spatial separation should be permitted to do
so. Whereas the empowerment justification is
based primarily on using the past to construct
the future, the pluralistic justification aims
mainly to foster the ability of communities to
function properly in the present.
Good Fences Make Good
Neighbors: Utilitarianism
Another way to justify spatial segregation both
in general and between particular communities
is utilitarian. This justification assumes that
the inability of two or more parties to reach an
agreement about the proper use or manage-
ment of shared resources requires division and
separation (Ostrom ). This assumption un
-
derlies Garrett Hardin’s “tragedy of the com-
mons” (), in which he advocates adopting
a private property regime rather than a com-
mon one (Demsetz ; Hardin ). To over-
come the collective action problem in regard to
shared resources, and to avoid inefficiency, it
would be better to divide ownership of the re-
source so that each owner is able to use and
manage their own plot efficiently (Ostrom
). This rationale, which calls for division
and separation to ensure efficiency, may also
justify spatial separation between different
communities. When communities holding dis-
tinctly different values and norms are required
to share resources, such as schools, they may
face ongoing conflicts that prevent any of them
from deriving the proper and desired benefit of
those institutions.
This argument also holds true for decision
making in the design of common space. Con-
sider the various needs of the Monroe and the
Kiryas Joel populations. Those of the Monroe
population were more or less identical to those
of any average American community, but those
of Kiryas Joel were quite different. The large
number of children per family, the gender seg-
regation in educational institutions and the
public sphere, and their need for various insti-
tutions of worship all led to ongoing conflicts
regarding local zoning and the characteristics
of public institutions. From the utilitarian
point of view, these confrontations and there-
fore this partnership were undesirable. Pro-
tracted confrontations between parties not
only caused significant delays in the satisfac-
tion of public needs but also resulted in the
failure to satisfy either side. Economic losses
related to litigation or constant threats of it
were a factor (Trubek et al. ; Ribstein ),
as was frustration on all sides with the inability
to implement programs and services (Michel-
man ) that, in a sense, paralyzed the shared
city. These costs, all embedded in the collective
action problem, militate for the separation of
communities that have been paralyzed and de-
pleted by costly sharing. In this sense, spatial
segregation may efficiently ease tensions and
confrontations among communities, or, as one
Kiryas Joel official said, “We can each have our
own town and be good neighbors.”
The empowerment and pluralistic justifica-
tions have numerous similarities, but the utili-
tarian justification involves a completely differ-
ent view. According to it, segregation should
also be implemented if one of the communities
using a common space does not wish to imple-
ment it. The reasoning here lies in the perspec-
tive that characterizes utilitarian perceptions,
which is the consideration of aggregate welfare,
regardless of the will of those who make up the
equation. This aspect of the utilitarian justifica-
tion has the potential to facilitate the imposi-
tion of spatial segregation on various commu-
nities, ignoring their characteristics and the
rsf: the russell sage foundation journal of the social sciences
,
implications of that separation on the conduct
of the community. In a sense, the utilitarian
justification’s disregard for the volitional
choice of spatial segregation is reminiscent of
the dark ages, when racial segregation was jus-
tified for utilitarian reasons, in service of per-
ceived aggregate welfare (Hayman ; Klar-
man ). These and other objections are the
focus of the next section, which explains the
reasons for opposing spatial separation.
-
Each of the three justifications for spatial seg-
regation, though differing in scope and scale of
application, holds that communities should be
allowed to segregate spatially in certain circum-
stances. Whether because segregation is re-
quired to empower long oppressed communi-
ties, because of its essential role in preserving
a community’s norms and values, or because it
contributes to the aggregate welfare, spatial
segregation may be legitimized despite its
moral flaws and its historic role in fostering dis-
crimination.
Influences on Society
One objection to legitimizing it, despite its po-
tential contribution to minority communities
or to society generally, is that it imposes costs
and inappropriate norms. This objection has
multiple layers. The first, oen referred to as
the slippery slope argument, suggests that le-
gitimizing spatial separation will not success-
fully be restricted within defined boundaries,
as in the case of a voluntary demand of a minor-
ity community. Instead, it will cross borders
and expanses, eventually spreading to the en-
tire American space (Kymlicka , ).
According to this view, even under the alleg-
edly egalitarian spatial policies of the third gen
-
eration of spatial segregation, racist and dis-
criminatory attitudes remain, if dormant.
Widening the prohibitions on segregation in
public law has led to discriminatory and racist
views being expressed mainly through market
forces and private law. Reinstating the possibil-
ity of spatial separation could, on a public level,
therefore incite racist and discriminatory be-
haviors, and drive spatial segregation even in
situations for which no justification is possible.
In a sense, the slippery slope argument seeks
to prevent the return of America to the second
generation, in which spatial separation was le-
gitimate and justified in various ways by a large
portion of the population (Edmonds ). Spa-
tial separation should therefore be prohibited
now just as it has been.
A second aspect of the influence objection
concerns the possibility that community
norms, for the sake of which the community
has separated from society, will bleed into the
common space outside the community. Com-
munal norms will cross the boundaries of the
community and affect the external space. For
example, it is possible that different religious
or cultural norms, some of which could conflict
with liberal norms such as gender segregation
and gender discrimination, would affect the lib-
eral space outside the community. The com-
munity that differentiates itself spatially in or-
der to continue and even intensify its practices
of nonliberal norms within its discrete com-
munal space will, somewhat paradoxically, ex-
ert greater influence on the general space from
which it withdrew (Stolzenberg ). Although
it is possible to argue that communities such
as Kiryas Joel exercised nonliberal norms even
before separating from the town of Monroe,
separation increases its ability to do so, both in
terms of enforcement and scope, because seg-
regation facilitates the practice of nonliberal
norms in the public sphere. The influence ob-
jection, then, calls for the prohibition of spatial
separation in the fourth generation out of con-
cern that such separation would impose im-
proper costs and norms in the space around
the community.
Harm to Community Members’ Autonomy
A different objection to legitimizing spatial
segregation stems from a concern for the in-
dividual autonomy of members of the segre-
gated community (Buchanan ; Pildes ;
Dagan and Heller ). According to this argu-
ment, the three justifications for spatial segre-
gation ignore both the interests of individual
members of the community and their auton-
omy. The objection to spatial segregation out
of concern for the individual autonomy of com-
munity members recognizes that communi-
ties, although important to their members,
rsf: the russell sage foundation journal of the social sciences
may violate their autonomy to the point of
claiming that individuals will sacrifice them-
selves for the sake of the community. In such
cases, communities, however important they
may be, can effectively become prisons for in-
dividuals.
Spatial segregation does not create commu-
nities or shape their characteristics. The vari-
ous justifications discussed earlier refer to ex-
isting communities that seek to differentiate
themselves spatially. However, spatial separa-
tion of the community from other communi-
ties intensifies, or is likely to intensify, the vio-
lation of the autonomy of individual members
of the community, for two reasons (Stern ).
First, spatial segregation empowers the com-
munity as a whole and its leaders in particular
(Phillips ). Empowering community lead-
ers creates the potential for further reduction
of individual autonomy, subordinating the in-
dividual’s discretion to the directives of lead-
ership. Second, and equally important, spatial
segregation creates a barrier between those
who belong to the community and those who
do not. This barrier, although it may have ex-
isted socially or covertly when the communi-
ties intertwined, prevents individual members
of the community from being exposed to other
norms and to those who believe in them (Stern
). Exposure to alternatives generally devel-
ops the ability to think autonomously. As
noted, this barrier also reduces the ability of
individual members of the community to
create social, economic, and cultural affilia-
tions with those who do not belong to the com-
munity, and thus has a chilling effect on their
ability to exit the community as they choose
(Simmel ; Bolt, Burgers, and Van Kempen
).
The Utilitarian Objection
Another objection to the spatial segregation of
minority communities involves society as a
whole. This utilitarian objection has many as-
pects, the common denominator of which is
the conclusion that granting legitimacy for spa-
tial segregation may harm aggregate welfare
(Glyn and Miliband ; Carr and Kutty ).
One suggests that segregation involves an in-
herent reduction in the ability of isolated com-
munities to maximize their economic activity.
Another is that spatial segregation creates en-
claves that, over time, will become completely
disconnected from general society, so that so-
ciety loses significant forces that might other-
wise contribute to aggregate welfare. The first
objection focuses on the segregated communi-
ties and the implications of spatial separation
on their economic situation. Most of the re-
search regarding the economic implications
suggests that segregation leads to severe con-
sequences for the separatist community and its
members (Massey, Gross, and Eggers ;
Massey and Fischer ; Wilson ). These
consequences are the result of poor education,
poor health, and lack of training and mobility,
but also stem from the lack of economic ties
with nonmembers (Massey, Gross, and Eggers
; Massey and Denton ; Massey and
Fischer ). Segregation impairs the eco-
nomic strength of the community because it
radically restricts the opportunities available
to its members. An examination of the ultra-
Orthodox communities in the New York area
reveals that their economic conditions are sig-
nificantly worse than those of the national and
state average. According to the – Amer-
ican Community Survey, all- ultra- Orthodox
communities, such as Kaser, New Square, and
Palm Tree, have per capita incomes one-
quarter to one- third of the state average and
poverty rates three to four times that of the
state. The childhood poverty in these commu-
nities is almost three times that of the state
(U.S. Census Bureau , annex ). From a util-
itarian point of view, the economic weakness
of the community is not expected to remain
an intracommunal problem. Communities
that collapse impose a heavy economic burden
on the state to subsidize and support them
through various educational, health, and reha-
bilitation programs (Massey and Denton ).
The concern for economic damage, then, justi-
fies its prevention from a utilitarian point of
view. However, the utilitarian objection has a
second aspect, which is related to the disen-
gagement of those segments of the population
from general society. According to this argu-
ment, the state’s labor capacity and productiv-
ity are impaired when segments of the labor
force disengage. The spatial segregation of mi-
nority communities may lead to enclaves be-
rsf: the russell sage foundation journal of the social sciences
,
coming completely detached from the general
economic activity in the country as a whole.
Whereas earlier this concern was the motive
for increasing mobility and improvements in
the ways in which minority groups were inte-
grated into the economy, complete separation
implemented voluntarily by the community to-
day can lead to the loss of significant parts of
the labor force, thus harming aggregate wel-
fare.
, :
As discussed, in each of the three previous gen-
erations, the law played a different role regard-
ing separation in space. In the first generation,
it functioned as the guardian of racial subordi-
nation through the institution of slavery and
was therefore indifferent to spatial separation.
In the second generation, aer the abolition of
slavery, it preserved white supremacy, legitimiz-
ing and even facilitating spatial segregation. In
the third generation, it became a constituent
component of spatial separation, because de-
spite its declarations regarding the prohibition
on separation, it supported and expanded its
existence through private law and market
forces. The fourth- generation characteristics
no longer allow the law to continue playing a
dual role in the same way. Incorporation as a
municipality prevents minority communities
from continuing to use private law as a method
of segregation and discrimination. The choice
to incorporate as a municipality changes the
status of those communities, shiing them
from private to public law. The meaning of in-
corporation as municipalities goes beyond at-
tempts of individuals and private developers to
exclude others and forces the law to consider
the implications of such segregation on the
community, its individual members, and soci-
ety at large. The justifications and objections
for spatial separation in the fourth generation
require that the law intervene in the construc-
tion of space and play a major, protective role
in maintaining the boundaries of separation
and its consequences.
Three constitutional challenges require a re-
thinking of the role of the law in establishing
the separate, therefore equal policy. The first
lies in the connection that fourth- generation
spatial segregation creates between commu-
nity authority and government authority. Such
a connection expands the authority given to
community leaders, therefore extending the
threat posed to the autonomy of individual
community members, as well as their constitu-
tional rights. The second challenge is the role
of the law in ensuring the ability of a minority
community to maintain its activities and char-
acteristics. This challenge sharpens when the
community that seeks to segregate spatially is
a religious community, a reality that evokes the
Establishment Clause of the First Amendment
and concerns state contribution to the estab-
lishment of religion. The third challenge relates
to the protection that the law should provide to
those who are not community members. In this
context, the law should accommodate the con-
cern that spatial segregation of minority com-
munities will establish discriminatory norms
between those who are members of the com-
munity and those who are not; for example, in
the fields of housing, employment, and educa-
tion. Protecting the community, the individual
community members and society at large,
therefore becomes a significant part of defining
the role of the law in the fourth generation of
spatial separation.
The Role of Law in Protecting
Community Members
The first challenge the fourth generation of spa-
tial segregation poses before the law is the ex-
tension of the authority and power of the com-
munity and its leaders. If before incorporating
as a municipality the community benefited
mostly from community forces, which were
based on internal community norms main-
tained primarily by social sanctions, its incor-
poration as a municipality adds a governmen-
tal layer to the variety of methods available to
the community and its leaders when seeking to
impose their judgment on community mem-
bers. In this sense, empowering a minority
community to be incorporated as a municipal-
ity connects community authority and govern-
ing authority, a connection that raises concern
about the preservation of the autonomy and
constitutional rights of the community mem-
bers. One example of such a challenge may be
the design of public space in accordance with
rsf: the russell sage foundation journal of the social sciences
11. Board of Ed. of Kiryas Joel Village School Dist. v. Grumet, 512 U.S. 687 (1994).
12. Kiryas Joel Village School Dist., 512 U.S. 687 (Scalia, A., dissenting).
community norms. In , the New York Civil
Liberties Union and the American Civil Liber-
ties Union sued the village of Kiryas Joel aer
press reports documented a public park in
which women and girls were confined to an
area with red benches and playground equip-
ment, with boys and men to a blue area. The
lawsuit was settled aer the town of Monroe
government agreed not to endorse segregation
of the sexes in the public sphere. However, the
separation of Kiryas Joel from Monroe raised
concerns that providing governing powers to
the Satmar community would reawaken its
leaders’ desire to shape the public sphere to
align with community norms. Another chal-
lenge concerns the enforcement of community
norms through governing powers. In this
sense, the concern is that establishing the con-
nection between community authority and gov-
ernment authority would extend the violation
of the autonomy of individual community
members, especially when it comes to their
right to oppose the leadership, to protest
against it, and to suggest alternatives to a path
chosen by the community leadership. These
concerns become more acute because the sanc-
tions held by the municipal government are no
longer informal, social sanctions, but instead
governmental and legal ones.
The concerns reinforce the notion that the
law should play a protective role that would
protect individual members of the community
from extending the infringement to their au-
tonomy, as well as from the loss of their consti-
tutional rights. To fulfill its protective role, the
law should address these concerns primarily
through strict adherence to the constitutional
rights of the community members, emphasiz-
ing the rights enumerated in the First Amend-
ment: freedom of expression, freedom of
speech, and freedom of association. Thus any
attempt by the municipal government to re-
strict or limit the exercise of individual mem-
bers’ constitutional rights should be under
strict scrutiny and under the assumption that
the restrictions on these rights should be re-
duced as far as possible. When illiberal minor-
ity communities incorporate as municipalities,
they bind together both communal and gov-
erning authorities. This consolidation of pow-
ers diminishes the ability of individuals, as
community members, to exercise their auton-
omy. If community members who violated
community codes were primarily subject to
community and social sanctions until the com-
munity’s incorporation as a municipality, they
would be subject to government sanctions aer
incorporation. The unification of powers,
therefore, sharpens the importance of the role
of law as the protector of community members’
rights.
-
The Establishment Clause is a limitation
placed on governments to prevent actions that
may contribute to the establishment of reli-
gion, making it illegal for the government to
promote theocracy or a specific religion. Gov-
ernment support for spatially segregated reli-
gious minority communities could trigger Es-
tablishment Clause concerns because the
segregation could be seen as a way of realizing
religious community norms. This question was
at the core of the Grumet case, in which the New
York legislature’s special state statute estab-
lished a separate board of education along the
village boundaries of Kiryas Joel to serve this
distinctive religious population. Justice David
Souter reached the conclusion that the legisla-
tors’ decision, one counter to regular state
practice, was undermining the state’s constitu-
tional obligation to act in neutrality, therefore
violating the Establishment Clause. Although
the ruling in Grumet was widely criticized (Mi-
now ; Greene ),
it seems that the chal-
lenge that the Establishment Clause poses to
fourth generation spatial segregation claims
should be examined differently. As noted, the
fourth- generation of spatial separation does
not necessarily concern religious communities
exclusively, though it is reasonable to assume
that these may play a major role in community
quests for segregation. Instead, the main char-
acteristic of the community that seeks to seg-
rsf: the russell sage foundation journal of the social sciences
,
13. Employment Division, Department of Human Resources of Oregon v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872 (1990).
14. 42 U.S.C. § 2000bb.
regate itself voluntarily is that it is a minority
community. An examination of the justifica-
tions for spatial separation also reveals that
none are unique to religious communities. All
three justifications may apply to religious com-
munities but do not depend on religious affili-
ation, only concerns relating to minority status.
A decision on whether the state should permit,
support, or regulate self- segregated communi-
ties should thus be based on nonreligious jus-
tifications as specified. In the context of spatial
segregation, the state should accommodate re-
ligion as long as segregation is justified accord-
ing to secular (social) justifications. Such rec
-
ognition should also be accompanied by the
verification that the social costs highlighted in
the objections specified do not impose too
heavy a burden on society. When the state acts
according to this principle, it does so out of a
secular respect for the needs of religious com-
munities or any other minority community. It
does not violate the Establishment Clause be-
cause it is motivated by secular and social con-
cerns rather than religious ones.
American law established antidiscrimination
duties through several antidiscrimination laws,
among them the Civil Rights Act of , the
Fair Housing Act of , and the Americans
with Disabilities Act of . These laws pro-
vide protection for race, color, religion, sex, and
national origin in the areas of voting, educa-
tion, employment, public accommodation,
and housing. In addition to federal legislation,
numerous state and local laws address discrim-
ination that is not covered by these laws (Hunt
). This set of rules challenges a minority
community that seeks to segregate spatially be-
cause it reinforces its commitment to equality,
even to those who are not members of the com-
munity or who do not share the conception of
good that it holds. Consider, for example, a sit-
uation in which a minority community seeks
to segregate spatially because of its unique cul-
tural characteristics. Antidiscrimination laws
require the community to refrain from discrim-
inating against those who are not members of
the community in regard to housing, employ-
ment, and education, but allowing such a pos-
sibility could thwart the purpose of segregation
in the first place. In the case of Kiryas Joel, the
main motive for segregation was the reluctance
of members of the community to compromise
their religious worldview on gender segrega-
tion in schools and public spaces. Applying an-
tidiscrimination laws in the new town of Palm
Tree, therefore, would frustrate the entire pur-
pose of segregation. Spatial segregation in the
fourth generation thus poses a significant chal-
lenge to the law because it is forced to examine
the boundaries of segregation as well as its im-
plications for the community, its members,
and those who are not members of the com-
munity.
As a result, the law in the fourth generation
of spatial segregation needs to take a protective
role. On the one hand, it should protect the
ability of minority communities to exercise
their right to spatial segregation, whether for
empowerment, pluralism, or utilitarian pur-
poses. On the other hand, it should protect in-
dividual members of the community, as well as
those who are not members of the community,
from the discriminatory consequences that this
separation may have. This tension sharpens
when the community that seeks to self-
segregate is a religious one. When it comes to
a religious minority community, the attempt to
compel it to comply with antidiscrimination
laws provokes an additional constitutional
challenge—the Free Exercise Clause, which
aims to limit the state’s actions to restrict
religion- related activities. Over the last few
years, the extent of exemption from antidis-
crimination laws granted for religious reasons
has expanded. Aer the Supreme Court’s ruling
in Oregon v. Smith, which held that judicially
mandated religious exemptions from generally
applicable legislation are normally inappropri-
ate, the Congress offered a swi counterre-
sponse, enacting the Religious Freedom Resto-
ration Act of . This was followed by the
rsf: the russell sage foundation journal of the social sciences
15. 42 U.S.C. § 2000cc.
16. Burwell v. Hobby Lobby Stores, Inc., 573 U.S. ___ (2014).
17. Masterpiece Cakeshop v. Colorado Civil Rights Commission, 584 U.S. ___ (2018).
Religious Land Use and Institutionalized Per-
sons Act of . These acts elevate the Free
Exercise Clause over antidiscrimination laws
and provide additional exemptions for reli-
gious reasons. Additional expansion of the
religion- based exemptions from antidiscrimi-
nation laws come in two recent Supreme Court
rulings: Burwell v. Hobby Lobby Stores
and Mas-
terpiece Cakeshop. v. Colo. Civil Rights Commis-
sion. It seems, therefore, that the Court’s ten-
dency is to extend the application of exemptions
by virtue of the Free Exercise Clause, meaning
that in more and more cases, individuals or
companies arguing that a regulation or a legis-
lation violates their religious faith may be ex-
empted from compliance (Luchenister ;
Sepper ). In other words, religious people
can use their beliefs to evade the application of
antidiscrimination laws. The legal tendency to
expand the scope of religious exemptions may
also be significant in the fourth generation of
spatial segregation, especially as far as religious
communities are concerned.
In regard to the Free Exercise Clause, it can
also be argued that to determine the appropri-
ate role of the law, it is necessary to consider
the justifications for and objections to spatial
segregation in general, and in regard to minor-
ity communities in particular. However, this
question is different from the one discussed
earlier, which focuses on state support or fund-
ing of such communities. This question relates
to the ability of the community to exclude oth-
ers or to discriminate against them by prevent-
ing them from purchasing housing within the
segregated town, or from employing them in
its institutions. Although such actions may
contribute to fulfilling the justifications for seg-
regation, they nevertheless pose threats to in-
dividual insiders, outsiders, and society as a
whole, thus requiring a strict examination of
their circumvention of the inherent objections
to segregation. In other words, although the
question of state funding should be examined
primarily for its contribution to the fulfillment
of the justifications, the question of the com-
munity’s exemption from antidiscrimination
laws should depend on its ability to answer the
objections described in regard to spatial sepa-
ration, especially those that impose costs on
outsiders.
The separation of Kiryas Joel from the town of
Monroe and the establishment of the new town
of Palm Tree as an exclusive ultra- Orthodox
town have spawned a new generation in the
American spatial segregation chronicle. This
generation is characterized by minority com-
munities that demand self- segregation from
their surroundings as part of their quest for
spatial justice. Although fourth- generation
claims might be justified for various reasons,
they are also objected to for various reasons.
This article outlines both the justifications and
objections to examine the role of the law in the
fourth generation of spatial segregation.
Voluntary segregation on behalf of minor-
ity communities requires the law to play a pro-
tective role, to protect the communities’ abil-
ity to exercise their aspiration to segregate
spatially, the individual members of the com-
munity, and those who are not members of the
community from the consequences that this
separation may have. A hard look at the justi-
fications for and objections to spatial segrega-
tion forces a rethink of how to address the le-
gal challenges facing spatial segregation,
which have fourth- generation characteristics.
The proliferation of minority communities
seeking to segregate spatially, as well as the
various challenges these actions pose, re-
quired the law to address the challenges and
to become a dominant player in the field. In
this sense, the challenges that the fourth gen-
eration of American spatial segregation poses
allow the law to ensure that the renewed le-
gitimacy for spatial segregation will not re-
store the application of the “separate but
equal” doctrine, but instead serve as a basis
for separation only in those instances in which
separate, therefore equal is in play.
Table A1. Ultra-Orthodox Towns and Villages in New York and New Jersey
Municipal Status Population
Ultra-Orthodox
Population
Steps Taken
Toward Separation Major Friction Points
Palm Tree Kiryas Joel, N.Y. Tow n October , incorporation
as a new town
Control over Board of Education,
territorial annexation
Lakewood, N.J. Township — —
Mahwah, N.J. Township — Calls to avoid selling apartments to
the ultra-Orthodox, struggle for
prevention of gender segregation in
the public sphere
Bloomingburg, N.Y. Village in town of
Mamakating
— Territorial annexation, public
institutions
New Square, N.Y. Village in town of
Ramapo
, incorporation as
a village
Struggles around planning laws and
building large houses suitable for
ultra-Orthodox families, legal
clashes over incorporation as a
village
Kaser, N.Y. Village in town of
Ramapo
, incorporation as
a village
Incorporation as a village approved
without conflict
Spring Valley, N.Y. Village in towns of
Ramapo and
Clarkstown in
Rockland County
Control over Board of Education,
territorial annexation
Ramapo, N.Y. To wn Control over Board of Education,
financing school transportation to
private schools, territorial
annexation
Source: Author’s tabulation from U.S. Census data.
Note: The data are taken from the 2018 census. Estimated population data for Bloomingburg, N.Y., are from “Population and Housing Unit Estimates.”
rsf: the russell sage foundation journal of the social sciences
Abramson, Alan, Mitchell S. Tobin, and Matthew R.
VanderGoot. 1995. “The Changing Geography of
Metropolitan Opportunity: The Segregation of
the Poor in U.S. Metropolitan Areas, 1970 to
1990.” Housing Policy Debate 6(1): 45–72.
Acevedo- Garcia, Dolores, and Kimberly A. Lochner.
2003. “Residential Segregation and Health.” In
Neighborhoods and Health, edited by Ichiro
Kawachi and Lisa F. Berkman. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Aloi, Frank A., Arthur Abba Goldberg, and James M.
White. 1969. “Racial and Economic Segregation
by Zoning: Death Knell for Home Rule.” Univer-
sity of Toledo Law Review 1(1): 65–108.
Anderson, Elizabeth. 1995. Value in Ethics and Eco-
nomics. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press.
Bauman, John F. 1974. “Black Slums/Black Projects:
The New Deal and Negro Housing in Philadel-
phia.” Pennsylvania History 41(3): 311–38.
Bayer, Patrick, Hanming Fang, and Robert McMillan.
2014. “Separate When Equal? Racial Inequality
and Residential Segregation.” Journal of Urban
Economics 82(1): 32–48.
Bell, Derrick. 2004. Silent Covenants: Brown v. Board
of Education and the Unfulfilled Hopes for Racial
Reform. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bischo, Kendra, and Sean F. Reardon. 2014. “Resi-
dential Segregation by Income, 1970–2009.” In
Diversity and Disparities: America Enters a New
Century, edited by John R. Logan. New York:
Russell Sage Foundation.
Bolt, Gideon, Jack Burgers, and Ronald van Kempen.
1998. “On the Social Significance of Spatial Lo-
cation; Spatial Segregation and Social Inclusion.”
Netherlands Journal of Housing and the Built En-
vironment 13(1): 83–95.
Boyd, Michelle. 2008. “Defensive Development: The
Role of Racial Conflict in Gentrification.” Urban
Aairs Review 43(6): 751–76.
Brooks, Richard R. W., and Carol M. Rose. 2013. Sav-
ing the Neighborhood: Racially Restrictive Cove-
nants: Law, and Social Norms. Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press.
Brooks, Roy L. 1996. Integration or Separation? Cam-
bridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Brown, David, and Clive Webb. 2007. Race in the
American South: From Slavery to Civil Rights. Ed-
inburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Buchanan, Allen E. 1989. “Assessing the Communi-
tarian Critique of Liberalism.” Ethics 99(4): 852–
61.
Carr, James H., and Nandinee K. Kutty. 2008. “The
New Imperative for Equality.” In Segregation, ed-
ited by James Carr and Nandinee Kutty. New
York: Routledge.
Conley, Dalton. 2010. Being Black, Living in the Red:
Race, Wealth, and Social Policy in America.
Berkeley: University of California Press.
Cutler, David M., Edward L. Glaeser, and Jacob L.
Vigdor. 1999. “The Rise and Decline of the Amer-
ican Ghetto.” Journal of Political Economy 107(3):
455–506.
Dagan, Hanoch, and Michael Heller. 2001. “The Lib-
eral Commons.” Yale Law Journal 110(4): 549–52.
Dean, John P. 1947. “Only Caucasian: A Study of
Race Covenants.” Journal of Land and Public Util-
ity Economics 23(4): 428–32.
Demsetz, Harold. 1967. “Toward a Theory of Property
Rights.” American Economic Review 57(2), Papers
and Proceedings of the Seventy- ninth Annual
Meeting of the American Economic Association
(May): 347–59.
DuBois, W.E.B. 1899. The Philadelphia Negro. Phila-
delphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
EdBuild. 2017. “Fractured: The Breakdown of Ameri-
ca’s School Districts.” Accessed September 12,
2010. https://edbuild.org/content/fractured.
Edmonds, Richard W. 1957. Segregation, Is It Justi-
fied? Muscogee: University of Michigan Press.
Ellickson, Robert C. 1982. “Cities and Homeowners
Associations.” University of Pennsylvania Law Re-
view 130(6): 1519–80.
Emerson, Michael O. 1994. “Is It Dierent in Dixie?
Percent Black and Residential Segregation in the
South and Non- South.” Sociological Quarterly
35(4): 571–80.
Fischer, Mary J. 2003. “The Relative Importance of
Income and Race in Determining Residential
Outcomes in US Urban Areas, 1970–2000.” Ur-
ban Aairs Review 38(5): 669–96.
Ford, Richard Thompson. 1993. “Boundaries of Race:
Political Geography in Legal Analysis.” Harvard
Law Review 107(8): 1841–921.
Frey, William H. 1979. “Central City White Flight:
Racial and Nonracial Causes.” American Socio-
logical Review 44(3): 425–48.
Glyn, Andrew, and David Miliband. 1994. Paying for
Inequality: The Economic Cost of Social Injustice.
London: Institute for Public Policy Research/Riv-
ers Oram Press.
rsf: the russell sage foundation journal of the social sciences
,
Goel, Ankur J., Willie J. Lovett Jr., Robert Patten, and
Robert L. Wilkins. 1988. “Black Neighborhoods
Becoming Black Cities: Group Empowerment,
Local Control and the Implications of Being
Darker than Brown.” Harvard Civil Rights–Civil
Liberties Law Review 23(2): 415.
Goetz, Edward. 2011. “Gentrification in Black and
White: The Racial Impact of Public Housing De-
molition in American Cities.” Urban Studies
48(8): 1581–604.
Gotham, Kevin Fox. 2000a. “Racialization and the
State: The Housing Act of 1934 and the Creation
of the Federal Housing Administration.” Socio-
logical Perspectives 43(2): 291–317.
——
—. 2000b. “Urban Space, Restrictive Covenants
and the Origins of Racial Residential Segregation
in a US City, 1900–50.” International Journal of
Urban and Regional Research 24(3): 616–33.
Greene, Abner S. 1996. “Kiryas Joel and Two Mis-
takes About Equality.” Columbia Law Review
96(1): 1–86.
Grumet, Louis, John Caher, and Judith Kaye. 2016.
Curious Case of Kiryas Joel: The Rise of a Village
Theocracy and the Battle to Defend the Separa-
tion of Church and State. Chicago: Chicago Re-
view Press.
Guelzo, Allen C. 2012. Fateful Lightning: A New His-
tory of the Civil War and Reconstruction. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Hall, Raymond L. 1977. “Introduction.” In Black Sepa-
ratism and Social Reality: Rhetoric and Reason, ed-
ited by Raymond L. Hall. Elmsford, N.Y.: Per-
gamon Press.
Hamilton, Charles V., and Kwame Ture. 1967. Black
Power: Politics of Liberation in America. New
York: Vintage Books.
Hardin, Garrett. 1968. “The Tragedy of the Com-
mons.” Science 162(1243)(December 13): 1243–48.
Hayman, Robert L., Jr. 2002. “Neutral Principles and
the Resegregation Decisions.” Widener Law Sym-
posium Journal 9(1): 129–64.
Hunt, Jerome. 2012. “A State- by- State Examination
of Nondiscrimination Laws and Policies: State
Nondiscrimination Policies Fill the Void but Fed-
eral Protections Are Still Needed.” Washington,
D.C.: Center for American Progress.
Jargowsky, Paul A. 1996. “Take the Money and Run:
Economic Segregation in U.S. Metropolitan Ar-
eas.” American Sociological Review 61(6): 984–
98.
Jennings, James. 2000. The Politics of Black Empow-
erment: The Transformation of Black Activism in
Urban America. Detroit: Wayne State University
Press.
Jones- Correa, Michael. 2000. “The Origins and Dif-
fusion of Racial Restrictive Covenants.” Political
Science Quarterly 115(4): 541–68.
Kaplan, David H., and Kathleen Woodhouse. 2004.
“Research in Ethnic Segregation I: Causal Fac-
tors.” Urban Geography 25(6): 579–85.
Kennedy, Stetson. 2011. Jim Crow Guide to the
U.S.A.: The Laws, Customs and Etiquette Govern-
ing the Conduct of Nonwhites and Other Minori-
ties as Second- Class Citizens. Tuscaloosa. Uni-
versity of Alabama Press.
Klarman, Michael J. 2004. From Jim Crow to Civil
Rights: The Supreme Court and the Struggle for
Racial Equality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kushner, James A. 1979. “Apartheid in America: An
Historical and Legal Analysis of Contemporary
Racial Residential Segregation in the United
States.” Howard Law Journal 22(2): 547–60.
Kymlicka, Will. 1997. “Do We Need a Liberal Theory
of Minority Rights? Reply to Carens, Young,
Parekh and Forst.” Constellations 4(1): 72–87.
Lamb, Charles M. 2005. Housing Segregation in
Suburban America Since 1960 : Presidential and
Judicial Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press.
Lees, Loretta, Tom Slater, and Elvin Wyly. 2013. Gen-
trification. New York: Routledge.
Lieberson, Stanley. 1980. A Piece of the Pie: Blacks
and White Immigrants Since 1880. Berkeley: Uni-
versity of California Press.
Luchenister, Alex J. 2015. “A New Era of Inequality:
Hobby Lobby and Religious Exemptions from
Anti- Discrimination Laws.” Harvard Law and
Policy Review 9(1): 63–88. Accessed September
12, 2020. https://harvardlpr.com/wp-content
/uploa ds/sites/20/2015/04/9-1_Luchenitser.pdf.
Magid, Shaul. 2014. “‘America Is No Dierent,’
‘America Is Dierent’—Is There an American
Jewish Fundamentalism?” In Fundamentalism:
Perspectives on a Contested History, edited by
Simon A. Wood and David H. Watt. Columbia:
University of South Carolina Press.
Massey, Douglas S. 1990. “American Apartheid: Seg-
regation and the Making of the Underclass.”
American Journal of Sociology 96(2): 329–57.
——
—. 2008. Origins of Economic Disparities: The
Historical Role of Housing Segregation. New York:
Routledge.
rsf: the russell sage foundation journal of the social sciences
Massey, Douglas S., and Nancy A. Denton. 1988.
“The Dimensions of Residential Segregation.”
Social Forces 67(2): 281–315.
——
—. 1993. American Apartheid: Segregation and
the Making of the Underclass. Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press.
Massey, Douglas S., and Mitchell L. Eggers. 1993.
“The Spatial Concentration of Aluence and Pov-
erty During the 1970s.” Urban Aairs Quarterly
29(2): 299–315.
Massey, Douglas S., and Mary J. Fischer. 2000. “How
Segregation Concentrates Poverty.” Ethnic and
Racial Studies 23(4): 670–91.
——
—. 2003. “The Geography of Inequality in the
United States, 1950–2000.” Brookings- Wharton
Papers on Urban Aairs 1:1–40.
Massey, Douglas S., Andrew B. Gross, and Mitchell
L. Eggers. 1991. “Segregation, the Concentration
of Poverty, and the Life Chances of Individuals.”
Social Science Research 20(4): 397–420.
Massey, Douglas S., Jonathan Rothwell, and Thur-
ston Domina. 2009. “The Changing Bases of
Segregation in the United States.” Annals of the
American Academy of Political and Social Science
626(1): 74–90.
Meier, August. 1954. “Booker T. Washington and the
Town of Mound Bayou.” Phylon (1940–1956)
15(4): 396–401.
Michelman, Frank I. 1967. “Property, Utility, and Fair-
ness: Comments on the Ethical Foundations of
Just Compensation Law.” Harvard Law Review
80(6): 1165–258.
Minow, Martha. 1995. “The Constitution and the
Subgroup Question.” Indiana Law Journal 71(1):
9–10.
Mintz, Jerome R. 1992. Hasidic People: A Place in the
New World. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univer-
sity Press.
Myers, David N. 2013. “‘Commanded War’: Three
Chapters in the ‘Military’ History of Satmar Ha-
sidim.” Journal of the American Academy of Reli-
gion 81(2): 311–56.
Myers, Samuel L., Jr., William A. Darity Jr., and Kris
Marsh. 2009. “The Eects of Housing Market
Discrimination on Earnings Inequality.” In The In-
tegration Debate: Competing Futures for Ameri-
can Cities, edited by Gregory D. Squires and
Chester W. Hartman. New York: Routledge.
Nelson, Jania S. 1996. “Residential Zoning Regula-
tions and the Perpetuation of Apartheid.” UCLA
Law Review 43: 1689–730.
Norgren, Jill, and Serena Nanda. 2006. American
Cultural Pluralism and Law. Westport, Conn.:
Greenwood Publishing.
Omi, Michael, and Howard Winant. 2014. Racial For-
mation in the United States. New York: Rout-
ledge.
Ostrom, Elinor. 1990. Governing the Commons: The
Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Pettigrew, Thomas F. 1977. “Racially Separate or To-
gether.” In Black Separatism and Social Reality:
Rhetoric and Reason, edited by Raymond L. Hall.
Elmsford, N.Y.: Pergamon Press.
Phillips, Anne. 2005. “Dilemmas of Gender and Cul-
ture: The Judge, the Democrat and the Political
Activist.” In Minorities Within Minorities: Equality,
Rights and Diversity, edited by Avigail Eisenberg
and Je Spinner- Halev. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Pildes, Richard H. 1998. “Why Rights Are Not
Trumps: Social Meanings, Expressive Harms, and
Constitutionalism.” Journal of Legal Studies
27(S2): 725–63.
powell, john a. 2002. “Opportunity- Based Housing.”
Journal of Aordable Housing and Community
Development 12(2): 188–228.
——
—. 2008. “Reflections on the Past, Looking to the
Future: The Fair Housing Act at 40.” Indiana Law
Review 41(3): 605–27. Accessed September 10,
2020. http://journals.iupui.edu/index.php/inlaw
rev/article/view/3949/3911.
powell, john a., and Marguerite L. Spencer. 2002.
“Giving Them the Old One- Two: Gentrification
and the KO of Impoverished Urban Dwellers of
Color.” Howard Law Journal 46(3): 433–90.
Rabin, Yale. 1989. “Expulsive Zoning: The Inequita-
ble Legacy of Euclid.” In Zoning and the Ameri-
can Dream: Promises Still to Keep, edited by
Charles Haar. New York: Routledge.
Rael, Patrick. 2015. Eighty- Eight Years: The Long
Death of Slavery in the United States, 1777–1865.
Race in the Atlantic World, 1700–1900. Athens:
University of Georgia Press.
Reardon, Sean F., and Kendra Bischo. 2011. “In-
come Inequality and Income Segregation.” Amer-
ican Journal of Sociology 116(4): 1092–153.
Reeves, Richard, Edward Rodrigue, and Elizabeth
Kneebone. 2016. “Five Evils: Multidimensional
Poverty and Race in America.” Washington, D.C.:
Brookings Institution. Accessed September 10,
2020.
rsf: the russell sage foundation journal of the social sciences
,
https://www.brookings.edu/wp-content/uploads
/2016/06/reeveskneebonerodrigue_multidimen
sionalpoverty_fullpaper.pdf.
Reichman, Uriel. 1976. “Residential Private Govern-
ments: An Introductory Survey.” University of
Chicago Law Review 43(2): 253–306.
Ribstein, Larry E. 2001. “Law v. Trust.” Boston Uni-
versity Law Review 81(2): 553–90.
Roithmayr, Daria. 2010. “Racial Cartels.” Michigan
Journal of Race and Law 16(1): 45–80.
Rothstein, Richard. 2017. The Color of Law: A Forgot-
ten History of How Our Government Segregated
America. New York: Liveright Publishing.
Rubin, Israel. 1997. Satmar: Two Generations of an
Urban Island, 2nd ed. Bern: Peter Lang.
Runnels, Gabriella. 2016. “Breaking Apart: Confront-
ing Race in East Baton Rouge Parish.” Women
Leading Change: Case Studies on Women, Gen-
der, and Feminism 1(2): 59–78.
Schi, David N. 1976. “Socio- Legal Theory: Social
Structure and Law.” The Modern Law Review
39(3): 287–310.
Schwemm, Robert G. 1978. “Discriminatory Eect
and the Fair Housing Act.” Notre Dame Lawyer
54 (December): 199–262.
Scott, A. J. 1986. “Industrialization and Urbanization:
A Geographical Agenda.” Annals of the Associa-
tion of American Geographers 76(1): 25–37.
Seitles, Marc. 1998. “The Perpetuation of Residential
Racial Segregation in America: Historical Dis-
crimination, Modern Forms of Exclusion, and In-
clusionary Remedies.” Journal of Land Use and
Environmental Law 14(1): 89–124.
Sepper, Elizabeth. 2015. “Free Exercise Lochnerism.”
Columbia Law Review 115(6): 1453–519.
Shapiro, Eliza. 2019. “‘I Love My Skin!’ Why Black
Parents Are Turning to Afrocentric Schools.” New
York Times, January 8. Accessed October 8,
2020. https://www.nytimes.com/2019/01/08/ny
region /afrocentric-schools-segregation-brooklyn
.html.
Shoked, Nadav. 2013. “Quasi- Cities.” Boston Univer-
sity Law Review 93(6): 1971–2032.
Silver, Christopher. 1997. “ The Racial Origins of Zon-
ing in American Cities.” In Urban Planning and
the African American Community: In the Shad-
ows, edited by Thomas Manning and Marsha
Ritzdorf. Thousand Oaks, Calif.: Sage Publica-
tions.
Simmel, Georg. 1955.Conflict and the Web of
Group-Ailiations.New York: Free Press.
Smith, Mark M. 2006. How Race Is Made: Slavery,
Segregation, and the Senses. Chapel Hill: Univer-
sity of North Carolina Press.
Smith, Neil. 2005. The New Urban Frontier: Gentrifi-
cation and the Revanchist City. New York: Rout-
ledge.
Soja, Edward W. 2010. Seeking Spatial Justice. Min-
neapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Stern, Shai. 2014. “Takings, Community, and Value:
Reforming Takings Law to Fairly Compensate
Common Interest Communities.” Journal of Law
and Policy 23(1): 141–202.
——
—. 2015. “When One’s Right to Marry Makes
Others Unmerry.” Albany Law Review 79(2): 627.
Stolzenberg, Nomi Maya. 1993. “‘He Drew a Circle
That Shut Me Out’: Assimilation, Indoctrination,
and the Paradox of a Liberal Education.” Harvard
Law Review 106(3): 581–667
——
—. 2002. “The Return of the Repressed: Illiberal
Groups in a Liberal State.” Journal of Contempo-
rary Legal Issues 12(1): 897.
——
—. 2011. “Board of Education of Kiryas Joel Vil-
lage School District v. Grumet: A Religious
Group’s Quest for its Own Public School.” In Law
and Religion, edited by Leslie C. Griin. New
York: Aspen Publishers.
——
—. 2015. “Is There Such a Thing as Non- State
Law? Lessons from Kiryas Joel.” In Negotiating
State and Non- State Law: The Challenge of
Global and Legal Pluralism, edited by Michael
Helfand. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Stuckey, Melissa Nicole. 2009. All Men Up: Race,
Rights, and Power in the All- Black Town of Boley,
Oklahoma, 1903–1939. New Haven, Conn.: Yale
University Press.
Taeuber, Karl E., and Alma F. Taeuber. 1965. Negroes
in Cities: Residential Segregation and Neighbor-
hood Change. Chicago: Aldine Publishing.
Taylor, Keeanga- Yamahtta. 2019. Race for Profit:
How Banks and the Real Estate Industry Under-
mined Black Homeownership. Chapel Hill: Uni-
versity of North Carolina Press.
Taylor, Kendra, Erica Frankenberg, and Genevieve
Siegel- Hawley. 2019. “Racial Segregation in the
Southern Schools, School Districts, and Counties
Where Districts Have Seceded.” AERA Open
5(3). Published online September 3. DOI: 10.1177
/2332858419860152.
Tolson, Arthur l. 1970. “Black Towns of Oklahoma.”
The Black Scholar 1(6): 18–22.
rsf: the russell sage foundation journal of the social sciences
Tomlins, Richard. 2000. “Addressing the Housing
Needs of Minority Ethnic Communities: Towards
a Pluralistic Ethnic Housing Policy.” In Ethnicity
and Housing: Accommodating Dierences, edited
by Frederick W. Boal. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate
Publishing.
Trifun, Natasha M. 2009. “Residential Segregation
After the Fair Housing Act.” Human Rights 36(4):
14–19.
Trubek, David M., Austin Sarat, William L. F. Fel-
stiner, Herbert M. Kritzer, and Joel B. Grossman.
1983. “The Costs of Ordinary Litigation.” UCLA
Law Review 31(1): 72–127.
U.S. Census Bureau. 2019. “2014–2018 American
Community Survey 5- Year Estimates.” Washing-
ton: Government Printing Oice. Accessed Sep-
tember 10, 2020. https://www.census.gov
/data /developers/data-sets/acs-5year.html.
Valocchi, Steve. 1996. “The Emergence of the Inte-
grationist Ideology in the Civil Rights Move-
ment.” Social Problems 43(1): 116–30.
Van Cleve, George. 2010. A Slaveholders’ Union :
Slavery, Politics, and the Constitution in the Early
American Republic. Chicago: University of Chi-
cago Press.
Walsh, James D. 1999. “Reaching Mrs. Murphy: A
Call for Repeal of the Mrs. Murphy Exemption to
the Fair Housing Act.” Harvard Civil Rights–Civil
Liberties Law Review 34(2): 605–34.
Weaver, Robert Clifton. 1948. The Negro Ghetto.
New York: Russell & Russell.
Williams, David R., and Chiquita Collins. 2001. “Ra-
cial Residential Segregation: A Fundamental
Cause of Racial Disparities in Health.” Public
Health Reports 116(5): 404–16.
Wilson, Erika K. 2016. “The New School Segrega-
tion.” Cornell Law Review 102(3): 139–210.
Wilson, William Julius. 1990. The Truly Disadvan-
taged: The Inner City, the Underclass, and Public
Policy, repr. ed. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Woldo, Rachael A. 2011. White Flight/Black Flight:
The Dynamics of Racial Change in an American
Neighborhood. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University
Press.
Wood, Simon A., and David Harrington Watt. 2014.
Fundamentalism: Perspectives on a Contested His-
tory. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press.
Woodward, Comer Vann, and William S. McFeely.
2002. The Strange Career of Jim Crow. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Yinger, John. 1995. Closed Doors, Opportunities Lost:
The Continuing Costs of Housing Discrimination.
New York: Russell Sage Foundation.