ArticlePDF Available

The End of a Classical Ontology for Quantum Mechanics?

MDPI
Entropy
Authors:

Abstract

In this paper, I argue that the Shrapnel–Costa no-go theorem undermines the last remaining viability of the view that the fundamental ontology of quantum mechanics is essentially classical: that is, the view that physical reality is underpinned by objectively real, counterfactually definite, uniquely spatiotemporally defined, local, dynamical entities with determinate valued properties, and where typically ‘quantum’ behaviour emerges as a function of our own in-principle ignorance of such entities. Call this view Einstein–Bell realism. One can show that the causally symmetric local hidden variable approach to interpreting quantum theory is the most natural interpretation that follows from Einstein–Bell realism, where causal symmetry plays a significant role in circumventing the nonclassical consequences of the traditional no-go theorems. However, Shrapnel and Costa argue that exotic causal structures, such as causal symmetry, are incapable of explaining quantum behaviour as arising as a result of noncontextual ontological properties of the world. This is particularly worrying for Einstein–Bell realism and classical ontology. In the first instance, the obvious consequence of the theorem is a straightforward rejection of Einstein–Bell realism. However, more than this, I argue that, even where there looks to be a possibility of accounting for contextual ontic variables within a causally symmetric framework, the cost of such an account undermines a key advantage of causal symmetry: that accepting causal symmetry is more economical than rejecting a classical ontology. Either way, it looks like we should give up on classical ontology.
entropy
Article
The End of a Classical Ontology for Quantum Mechanics?
Peter W. Evans


Citation: Evans, P.W. The End of a
Classical Ontology for Quantum Me-
chanics? Entropy 2021,23, 12. https://
dx.doi.org/10.3390/e1010000
Received: 18 November 2020
Accepted: 21 December 2020
Published: 24 December 2020
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neu-
tral with regard to jurisdictional claims
in published maps and institutional
affiliations.
Copyright: © 2020 by the author. Li-
censeeMDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This
articleis an open accessarticle distributed
under the terms and conditions of the
Creative CommonsAttribution (CCBY)
license(https://creativecommons.org/
licenses/by/4.0/).
School of Historical and Philosophical Inquiry, University of Queensland, St Lucia, QLD 4072, Australia;
p.evans@uq.edu.au
Abstract:
In this paper, I argue that the Shrapnel–Costa no-go theorem undermines the last remaining
viability of the view that the fundamental ontology of quantum mechanics is essentially classical:
that is, the view that physical reality is underpinned by objectively real, counterfactually definite,
uniquely spatiotemporally defined, local, dynamical entities with determinate valued properties,
and where typically ‘quantum’ behaviour emerges as a function of our own in-principle ignorance
of such entities. Call this view Einstein–Bell realism. One can show that the causally symmetric
local hidden variable approach to interpreting quantum theory is the most natural interpretation that
follows from Einstein–Bell realism, where causal symmetry plays a significant role in circumventing
the nonclassical consequences of the traditional no-go theorems. However, Shrapnel and Costa
argue that exotic causal structures, such as causal symmetry, are incapable of explaining quantum
behaviour as arising as a result of noncontextual ontological properties of the world. This is partic-
ularly worrying for Einstein–Bell realism and classical ontology. In the first instance, the obvious
consequence of the theorem is a straightforward rejection of Einstein–Bell realism. However, more
than this, I argue that, even where there looks to be a possibility of accounting for contextual ontic
variables within a causally symmetric framework, the cost of such an account undermines a key
advantage of causal symmetry: that accepting causal symmetry is more economical than rejecting a
classical ontology. Either way, it looks like we should give up on classical ontology.
Keywords:
causal symmetry; classical ontology; quantum foundations; contextuality; ontological
models framework
1. Introduction
It should come as no surprise that many, perhaps even a good majority, of physicists
after 1927 gave up on the view that the fundamental ontology of quantum mechanics is
essentially classical: that is, the view that physical reality is underpinned by objectively
real, counterfactually definite, uniquely spatiotemporally defined, local, dynamical entities
with determinate valued properties, and where typically ‘quantum’ behaviour emerges
as a function of our own in-principle ignorance of such entities. Let us call this position
on the ontology of quantum theory Einstein–Bell realism. Despite the gloomy forecast for
Einstein–Bell realists, it is well known that a class of responses to the canon of quantum
no-go theorems, so-called causally symmetric local hidden variable approaches, plausibly
rescues a large part of this classical picture of quantum theory. (I shall not be providing an
argument for or against any particular causally symmetric local hidden variable approach
here. See [
1
,
2
] for good reviews of such approaches. See also [
3
], in which we argue in
favour of what we call the Price–Wharton approach). Indeed, causally symmetric local
hidden variable approaches arguably comprise the last refuge for Einstein–Bell realism,
positioned as they are to navigate a classical ontology through Bell’s theorem, the Kochen–
Specker theorem, and the PBR theorem.
Part of the appeal of causal symmetry in this context is that it circumvents one of
the integral assumptions of these three no-go theorems—that the properties of some
quantum system have definite values independently of the measurement context to which
the system is to be subject. With respect to Bell’s theorem, this admits local hidden
Entropy 2021,23, 12. https://dx.doi.org/10.3390/e23010012 https://www.mdpi.com/journal/entropy
Entropy 2021,23, 12 2 of 18
variables—or local beables, as Bell called them—and with respect to the Kochen–Specker
theorem, this not only admits noncontextual hidden variables, but also provides a natural
explanation for why quantum systems appear to be contextual (as contextuality arises from
the specific epistemic constraints of causal symmetry). A more recent no-go theorem, due to
Shrapnel and Costa [
4
], undermines this case for noncontextual hidden variables. In short,
the Shrapnel–Costa theorem removes the loophole open to ‘exotic causal structure’, and so
implies that no ontological model, now including causally symmetric models, that satisfy
the noncontextuality assumptions of the theorem can reproduce the statistical predictions
of quantum mechanics. So in order to be a feasible model of such predictions, any causally
symmetric ontology underpinning quantum behaviour must necessarily be contextual,
along with the rest of the ontological models. Making matters worse is that the resulting
form of the contextuality renders a natural explanation for this feature, as in the case of the
Kochen–Specker theorem, much less plausible. In so far as causally symmetric local hidden
variable approaches comprise the last refuge for Einstein–Bell realism, this contextuality
is a concerning predicament for classical ontology. Indeed, I argue that this concerning
predicament is as good as the end of a classical ontology for quantum mechanics.
The argument will proceed as follows. I begin in Section 2by introducing the broad
outline of causally symmetric local hidden variable approaches to the traditional no-go
theorems, and I define Einstein–Bell realism. I focus in this section on contextuality,
so introduce the ontological models framework and the operational formulation of the
contextuality problem. In Section 3, I provide a brief outline of the history and development
of the process matrix formalism and then go on to detail the Shrapnel–Costa theorem.
I consider the three assumptions of the theorem that constrain ontological models that
reproduce the statistical predictions of quantum mechanics—
ω
-mediation, instrument
noncontextuality, and process noncontextuality—and briefly examine what a violation of
each these assumptions implies. I consider in Section 4what this means for Einstein–Bell
realism and a classical ontology. I argue that, as a result of the Shrapnel–Costa theorem,
the outlook is particularly worrying for Einstein–Bell realism and classical ontology. In the
first instance, the obvious consequence of the theorem is a straightforward rejection of
Einstein–Bell realism. However, more than this, I argue that, even where there looks to
be a possibility of accounting for contextual ontic variables within a causally symmetric
framework, the cost of such an account undermines a key advantage of causal symmetry:
that accepting causal symmetry is more economical than rejecting a classical ontology.
Either way, it looks like we should give up on classical ontology.
2. Causal Symmetry and Classical Ontology
2.1. The No-Go Theorems
Following the revolution of statistical mechanics in the late nineteenth century, one
could surely be forgiven for expecting that the puzzles of quantum mechanics that emerged
over the first few decades of the twentieth century would ultimately be explained by an
underlying theory, comprised of hidden variables. This was a position for which Einstein,
de Broglie, and others argued. It was not long before a no-go theorem jeopardising this
position was proposed by von Neumann
[5]
, who purported to show that the probabilistic
nature of quantum theory could not be a function of an underlying theory of hidden vari-
ables. Bohm
[6]
showed by way of counterexample that there must have been something
wrong with von Neumann’s theorem by proving that the predictions of his own hidden
variable model were equivalent to the predictions of quantum theory. As a consequence of
Bohm’s counterexample to von Neumann’s theorem, Bell developed a more precise no-go
theorem—Bell’s theorem [
7
]—which clarifies that there can be no local hidden variable
model that can match the predictions of quantum theory (and that satisfy the further
reasonable assumptions of Bell’s theorem).
Bell’s comments on locality have attracted considerable attention (for instance, by [
8
,
9
],
to name just two), but this detail should not concern us here. The basis of Bell’s assumption
is that the specification of local beables at spacelike separation must be independent condi-
Entropy 2021,23, 12 3 of 18
tioned on their causal pasts. There is, however, another assumption in Bell’s theorem that
is significant for our current purposes. This further assumption is known as measurement
independence, and it requires that any hidden variables underlying a quantum system must
remain statistically independent of the choice of measurement settings to which that system
is subject as part of the experimental procedure [
1
]. If one were to reject the assumption
of measurement independence, one could maintain Bell’s assumption of locality by per-
mitting beables to be correlated explicitly with the choice of measurement setting, even if
that choice occurs in the future of the quantum system. (Another, metaphysically distinct,
way to reject the assumption of measurement independence is to remove the freedom
of agents to choose measurement settings arbitrarily, leading to superdeterministic local
hidden variables approaches [
8
,
10
,
11
]. Causal symmetry is generally more favourable than
superdeterminism on account of the fact that one can explicitly preserve the free choice of
agents by rejecting the assumption of strictly forwards-in-time causality.) Such a correla-
tion can then be accounted for by giving up the conventional assumption that causation
must occur only in the forward temporal direction, such that the choice of measurement
setting might causally influence the hidden variables underlying the quantum state in
the backward temporal direction. Thus, the resulting causal symmetry denies one of the
assumptions underpinning Bell’s theorem, measurement independence, without violating
the assumption of locality. This move rescues the possibility of local hidden variables,
so long as one admits symmetric causal influences, both forwards and backwards in time.
Very shortly after Bell’s theorem followed the Kochen–Specker theorem [
12
], which will
be particularly relevant for our discussion below. This theorem states that any hidden
variable model that reproduces the predictions of quantum theory must be contextual.
A model or theory is said to be contextual when the properties attributed to some system
described by the theory are dependent upon the means of realising some value for that
property, or context of measurement or observation of those properties, beyond the actual
observation itself. Thus, we can think of a noncontextual ontological property as one that
can be unambiguously distinguished experimentally. A relevant example of a context of
measurement beyond the measurement itself would be the set of further properties, if any,
that are measured in conjunction with the measurement. Since in classical mechanics there
is no such dependence on measurement context for properties attributed to systems as
a result of some measurement, classical mechanics is noncontextual. According to the
Kochen–Specker theorem, any model of a quantum system that assumes that measurements
deterministically uncover the values of pre-existing dynamical variables—such as beables—
must be contextual. So, just as Bell’s theorem shows that there can be no local hidden
variable model satisfying his assumptions that can match the predictions of quantum the-
ory, the Kochen–Specker theorem shows that there can be no noncontextual deterministic
local hidden variable model that can match the predictions of quantum theory.
However, just as we saw above that rejecting Bell’s assumption of measurement
independence, and so permitting correlations that arise as a result of symmetric causal
influences, rescues local hidden variables from Bell’s theorem, hypothesising such causal
symmetry allows a similar rejection of the assumption of measurement independence
for the Kochen–Specker theorem. Under the assumption that the correlation between
the value of any pre-measurement hidden variables and the context of measurement
can be explained by a causal influence directed from the latter to the former, we can
take the measurement process to be bringing about the determinate valued properties that
constitute the hidden variables, rather than uncovering independently existing variables [
1
].
This account has the added bonus of providing a ‘natural’ explanation for why quantum
theory is contextual: the dependence of any measured values on the eventual context of
measurement should be expected in a regime that admits symmetric causal influences.
This is because the natural epistemic constraints that arise when describing a physical
system whose complete description depends upon a future boundary condition result in
an impoverished, statistical description of the system conditioned only upon the initial
Entropy 2021,23, 12 4 of 18
boundary condition (see, for instance, [
13
]). Indeed, Wharton [
14
] (p. 203) suggests that
contextuality just is the failure of measurement independence.
So far this brief historical narrative is straightforward. However, since contextuality
is at the heart of the Shrapnel–Costa theorem, we need to develop further layers to this
narrative. The particular way of understanding contextuality adopted by Shrapnel and
Costa has its origin in the work of Spekkens
[15]
. To get to grips with this treatment of
contextuality, we need to say a few words about the ontological models framework.
2.2. Ontological Models
The ontological models framework was first introduced in [
15
], and developed further
in [
16
] (see also [
17
,
18
] for good reviews), and provides a formalisation of our notion of
classical ontology in an operational model of quantum processes [
1
]. As an operational
model, the framework specifies a set of possible preparations, transformations, and mea-
surements, and associated outcome probabilities, to describe the observed statistics over
the possible outcomes. In addition, the framework also specifies an ontological model to
account for the observed statistics in the following way.
The quantum state,
ψ
, is the description we give to the quantum system after the
preparation procedure. We assume, however, that we can completely specify the proper-
ties of the quantum system as a result of preparation in terms of its actual ontic state,
λ
,
which arises via a classical probability density,
µψ(λ)
, over the set of possible ontic states,
Λ
. We can then specify the outcome probabilities for each measurement procedure,
M
,
conditional on
λ
, such that the outcomes,
{m}
, are independent of the preparation proce-
dure. We say that
λ
screens-off the preparation from the measurement so that measurement
outcomes only depend on the ontic state. Leifer and Pusey
[19]
call this feature
λ
-mediation,
as the ontic state completely mediates any correlations between preparation procedures
and measurement outcomes. Importantly for our narrative here is that, explicitly according
to the ontological models framework,
λ
does not causally depend on the future choice of
measurement procedure, M,
P(λ|M) = P(λ), (1)
otherwise
λ
could not screen off the
{m}
from
ψ
. Finally, as a result of this setup, the even-
tual operational statistics given by the conditional outcome probabilities need to reproduce
the quantum statistics.
Let us add to this a useful distinction from the ontological models framework be-
tween what Harrigan and Spekkens
[16]
call
ψ
-ontic and
ψ
-epistemic interpretations of
the wavefunction. In a
ψ
-ontic interpretation, each ontic state is consistent with a single
quantum state. In a
ψ
-epistemic interpretation, multiple distinct quantum states can be
consistent with a single ontic state. A further orthogonal distinction can be overlaid across
this. A
ψ
-complete interpretation takes the quantum state to provide a complete descrip-
tion of objective reality (that is, there is a one-to-one correspondence between quantum
states and ontic states), while a
ψ
-incomplete interpretation requires that the quantum
state be supplemented with additional ontic degrees of freedom (such as, for instance,
in typical
ψ
-ontic pilot-wave interpretations). Given this latter distinction,
ψ
-epistemic
interpretations are naturally
ψ
-incomplete, and render the wavefunction a representation
of the knowledge of the user of the formalism rather than a representation of objective
reality. For
ψ
-epistemic interpretations in the ontological models framework, there exists
an ontic state underlying the wavefunction. (Beyond the ontological models framework,
a
ψ
-epistemic wavefunction can be given an anti-realist or operationalist interpretation
that makes no such claim for a deeper underlying objective reality.)
We can apply this framework to our analysis of Bell’s theorem above. The ontolog-
ical models framework is explicit that
λ
does not causally depend on the measurement
procedure (1), which is, of course, simply Bell’s assumption of measurement indepen-
dence. As we saw above, by denying this assumption and accounting for the correlation
between hidden variables, or the ontic state
λ
, and the measurement procedure by way
of causal symmetry, we can rescue the assumption that any beables are local. As a result
Entropy 2021,23, 12 5 of 18
of this move, then, we can see that the admission of causal symmetry is a ready made
violation of the assumption of a strict temporal and causal order for the ontological models
framework [18] (p. 94).
As a very brief aside, and before we continue with our explication of contextuality
in quantum theory, we now have the tools to summarily deal with the causal symmetry
response to the PBR theorem [
20
]. The PBR theorem states, in short, that the ontic states of
any interpretation of quantum mechanics that fits within the Bell framework and repro-
duces the Born rule must be in one-to-one correspondence with the quantum states. This,
of course, is simply the definition of a
ψ
-ontic interpretation of the wavefunction. Thus,
the PBR theorem appears to be ruling out
ψ
-epistemic approaches to the wavefunction.
However, since the PBR theorem is framed in the ontological models framework, it is
straightforward to note as before that it does not apply to causally symmetric approaches.
Just as with Bell’s theorem, admitting causal symmetry rescues the possibility of an inter-
pretation of the wavefunction as an epistemic representation of an underlying reality of
local beables.
Let us return then to contextuality. Spekkens
[15]
pioneered a new way of thinking
of contextuality beyond the formulation of [
12
]. According to Spekkens’ characterisa-
tion, an ontological model of an operational theory is noncontextual when operationally
equivalent experimental procedures have equivalent representations in the ontological
model [
15
] (p. 1). Thus, contextuality on this account implies that operationally equivalent
experimental preparation procedures may correspond to inequivalent ontic state represen-
tations (and where the state additionally depends on the context of measurement). Defining
contextuality in this way, rather than in terms of the deterministic uncovering of the values
of pre-existing dynamical variables, renders the assumption of noncontextuality as a princi-
ple of parsimony: no ontological difference without operational difference. (Spekkens
[21]
argues that this generalised noncontextuality is an embodiment of Leibniz’ Principle of the
Identity of Indiscernibles, and labels this principle the Leibnizian methodological principle.
Schmid et al. [
22
] formalise this principle under the term Leibnizianity. We consider this
principle again in Section 4.) Despite this difference in flavour, Spekkens’ diagnosis of
hidden variable approaches concludes with the same result. Assuming that there are ontic
properties underlying the observed statistical behaviour of quantum systems, and that the
associated ontic states are distinct just when there are corresponding operational differ-
ences, cannot account for the statistical behaviour entailed by quantum theory. The result
is then that there is no noncontextual ontological model that can reproduce the observed
statistics of quantum theory.
Just as we saw above with respect to Bell’s theorem and the PBR theorem, however,
in so far as the no-go theorems can be characterised in the ontological models framework,
the no-go theorems are undermined by the assumption of causal symmetry. Thus Spekkens’
more general understanding of contextuality in terms of the ontological models framework
suffers the same response: causal symmetry is a categorical rejection of the assumption of a
strict temporal and causal order that underpins the ontological models framework. Noting
this is the main result of this section of the paper: in so far as there is a motivation to avoid
the consequences of the above no-go theorems, particularly to maintain some semblance
of a classical ontology, hypothesising causal symmetry is a strategy that is well placed to
achieve this.
The no-go theorems are ordinarily taken to demonstrate that the underlying con-
ceptual and ontological framework of quantum theory cannot be completely classical,
and cannot be about local, noncontextual hidden variables. Any hope one might have
for hanging on to such a classical ontology rests with causally symmetric local hidden
variable approaches, as per our story here. Whilst such approaches are admittedly unortho-
dox, and even perhaps in a sense ‘nonclassical’ on account of causal symmetry, what is
significant about such approaches is that they have the potential to rescue an objectively
real, counterfactually definite, uniquely spatiotemporally defined, local, noncontextual
(or where any contextuality is underpinned by noncontextual epistemic constraints), deter-
Entropy 2021,23, 12 6 of 18
minate valued ontology, where typically ‘quantum’ behaviour emerges as a function of our
own in-principle ignorance of such entities [1].
As I propose in [
23
] (and also in [
1
]), the distinction that Quine
[24]
draws between
the ‘ontology’ and the ‘ideology’ of a theory is an apt distinction to understand the value of
the above argument. According to Quine, the ideology of a theory is comprised of the set
of ideas that can be expressed by a theory, and thus ideological economy is then a measure
of the economy of primitive undefined statements employed to reproduce this ideology.
Put in these terms, one of the consequences of the above narrative is that the ideology of
causal symmetry is more economical than a rejection of classical ontology. The main goal
of the current work is to make clear how the Shrapnel–Costa no-go theorem significantly
jeopardises this position. In short, motivated by the ‘get out of jail free’ card that causal
symmetry is able to play with respect to the no-go theorems, Shrapnel and Costa develop a
no-go theorem that closes off the ‘measurement independence’ loophole to any approach
that assumes an ‘exotic’ form of causality.
Before we consider the Shrapnel–Costa theorem in Section 3, let us once more explicitly
state our characterisation of classical ontology by adopting the framework which my
collaborators and I have elsewhere called Einstein–Bell realism [
3
], bringing together the
above analysis of the no-go theorems.
2.3. Einstein–Bell Realism
Consider the following conditions from [
3
], called the Einstein–Bell conditions, adapted
here to nonrelativistic quantum theory:
1. Quantum mechanical probabilities are epistemic;
2. Quantum mechanics is local;
3. Quantum mechanics is consistent with the no-go theorems.
We can think of Einstein–Bell realism as the conjunction of these conditions with the
assumption that there is an objective reality.
There is good reason for calling this view Einstein–Bell realism. It should be clear
to see that the first condition epitomises the sentiment that Einstein expressed to Born
in 1926 that “God does not play dice” (to be clear, I take this as a statement of determi-
nacy rather than determinism). This also has implications for any ensuing interpretation
of the wavefunction. Consider the distinction above between
ψ
-ontic and
ψ
-epistemic
interpretations of the wavefunction. Harrigan and Spekkens
[16]
argue that Einstein, in
his more sophisticated arguments for the incompleteness of quantum mechanics, advo-
cated for a realist
ψ
-epistemic interpretation. Despite the fact that there are some
ψ
-ontic,
ψ-incomplete
interpretations—like pilot-wave interpretations—in which probabilities arise
as a function of our ignorance over the full ontic degrees of freedom, and so are epistemic,
the basic probabilistic concepts that occur in all
ψ
-epistemic interpretations are clearly
also themselves epistemic. Thus,
ψ
-epistemic interpretations are natural bedfellows for
epistemic notions of probability [3] (p. 6).
The second assumption epitomises not only Einstein’s implicit appeal to consistency
between quantum theory and relativity (as in, for instance, [25]), but also the exclusion of
spacelike separated influences formalised in Bell’s own theorem (as in, for instance, [
26
]).
For clarity, and following [
3
] (p. 5), we can take the assumption here to mean that physical
bodies and influences can only follow timelike or null spacetime trajectories, and so these
trajectories must obey Lorentz covariance. The third assumption reflects that a plausible
interpretation of quantum theory must obey the constraints established by the above no-go
results, that is, from Bell’s theorem, the Kochen–Specker theorem, and the PBR theorem.
Employing the Einstein–Bell conditions, we argue in [
3
] that causally symmetric lo-
cal hidden variable approaches constitute a unique realist interpretation satisfying these
constraints. Our logic there is straightforward. The first condition requires a
ψ
-incomplete
interpretation, as epistemic probabilities cannot be accommodated by
ψ
-complete interpre-
tations. The second and third conditions together exclude
ψ
-ontic interpretations, as such
interpretations cannot be local according to the no-go theorems, implying that only
ψ
-
Entropy 2021,23, 12 7 of 18
epistemic interpretations can meet the Einstein–Bell conditions. Furthermore, a causally
symmetric approach circumvents the results of Bell’s theorem, and so can be a local hidden
variable theory, also circumvents the PBR theorem, and so permits a
ψ
-epistemic wave-
function, and also contains an explicit contextuality of the ontic state on the experimental
procedure, so fits within the bounds given by the Kochen–Specker theorem. So we can
see that the commitments of Einstein–Bell realism capture what we mean by local beables,
or by noncontextual local hidden variables: a commitment to a local-realist ontology un-
derlying a
ψ
-epistemic wavefunction. Causally symmetric hidden variable approaches are,
according to the arguments in [
3
], the only approaches that fit these constraints. As we will
now see, however, these constraints have just gotten prohibitively tighter.
3. The Shrapnel–Costa No-Go Theorem
Shrapnel and Costa
[4]
argue that exotic causal structures—such as causal symmetry—
are incapable of explaining quantum behaviour arising as a result of noncontextual ontolog-
ical properties of the world. As we have just seen, one of the key underlying assumptions
of the Kochen–Specker theorem is that quantum phenomena arise on a fixed background
forwards-in-time causal structure, and so do not preclude the possibility of more ex-
otic causal structures providing an ontologically classical (noncontextual) explanation.
This leaves open the possibility of symmetric causal structure allowing noncontextual
ontological properties to underpin quantum behaviour, and also providing a natural expla-
nation for why typically quantum behaviour can arise from such a noncontextual ontology.
The Shrapnel–Costa theorem is stronger than the Kochen–Specker theorem, as it
closes off the possibility of exotic causal structure providing just such a noncontextual
explanation of quantum behaviour. In fact, it shows that any ontology underpinning
quantum behaviour must be contextual; moreover, “what is contextual is not just the
traditional notion of “state”, but any supposedly objective feature of the theory, such as a
dynamical law or boundary condition, which is responsible for the experimentally observed
statistics” [
4
] (p. 2). In order to take account of the possibility of exotic causal structure,
the Shrapnel–Costa theorem first generalises the ontological models framework, and then
employs the process matrix formalism, which is suited to describing processes with indefinite
causal structure. To get to the heart of the Shrapnel–Costa theorem, then, let us begin by
reviewing the process matrix formalism.
3.1. Process Matrix Formalism
The development of the process matrix formalism is punctuated by a number of
independent redevelopments. The roots of the formalism stretch back to [
27
,
28
] on the dy-
namics of open quantum systems and quantum stochastic processes in the 1970s. This early
work is framed in the language of algebraic quantum field theory. The development of
quantum information theory at the beginning of this century allowed for some of the ideas
corresponding to those from the dynamics of open quantum systems to be recast into a
modern form, whereby, for instance, ‘non-Markovian quantum stochastic processes’ has be-
come ‘quantum channels with memory’. In the field of experimental quantum information,
process matrices began to be popularised in the analysis of quantum process tomogra-
phy of quantum optical systems (see, for instance, [
29
33
])—whereby processes matrices
were usually obtained experimentally from quantum state tomography [
29
]. However,
much of the contemporary discussion regarding the process matrix formalism can be traced
back to the seminal work [
34
], couched in the language of quantum information theory,
and developed largely independently of the earlier work on open quantum systems.
In short, a process matrix—to be defined below—is a way of representing the state
transformation denoted by the completely positive map,
MA(ρ)
, generated by the evolu-
tion of a quantum state,
ρ
, from an input state space,
HA1
, to an output state space,
HA2
,
by some quantum operation,
MA:L(HA1) L(HA2)
. A key step to developing the pro-
cess matrix formalism is the realisation that the Choi–Jamiołkowski isomorphism [
35
,
36
],
which establishes a correspondence between linear maps and linear operators, allows the
Entropy 2021,23, 12 8 of 18
linear map
MA:L(HA1) L(HA2)
to be conveniently rewritten as a linear operator
MA1A2 L(HA1 HA2)
(see [
37
] in this issue for more on the interpretation of the Choi–
Jamiołkowski isomorphism). Following on from [
34
], the ‘Pavia group’ employed this
Choi–Jamiołkowski representation to describe transformations on a network of quantum
gates, and developed a methodology for optimising such quantum circuits using what
they call a quantum comb: a temporally ordered physical process with a quantum memory
[
38
,
39
]. (Incidentally, the quantum comb has been independently redeveloped no less than
two more times [
40
,
41
].) They further demonstrated that simple quantum circuits can be
physical implementations of what they call quantum supermaps, mapping an input quantum
operation to an output quantum operation [42].
At about the same time, and independently, Gutoski and Watrous
[43]
also employed
the Choi–Jamiołkowski representation to represent what they call quantum strategies: a spec-
ification of the exchange and processing of quantum information in a quantum process.
This development is largely equivalent to the quantum comb (along with the operator
tensor formulation of quantum theory [
44
], which contains close similarities). The Pavia
group, however, went on in the ensuing years to develop and analyse the quantum control
of temporal order in the quantum switch, where two operations are enacted in a quantum
superposition of the two possible temporal orders [
45
47
]. The significance of the quantum
switch here is that the process matrix formalism developed as the ideal formal system for
describing such indefinite causal order.
Hardy
[48]
introduces the notion of indefinite causal structure in the context of quan-
tum gravity, and Oeckl
[49]
, also motivated by quantum gravity, considers a “general
boundary” formulation of quantum mechanics that does not assume an a priori causal
structure (and which overlaps significantly in the quantum context with the two-state vec-
tor formalism [
50
]). However, it is
Oreshkov et al. [51]
who analyse indefinite causal order
in the context of quantum processes: they employ the Choi–Jamiołkowski representation,
and a local causal direction, to derive a causal inequality violated by timelike and spacelike
correlations with a global causal direction. It is this work on process matrices and indefinite
causal order that has in part led to the development of quantum causal modelling [
52
55
],
the framework within which Shrapnel and Costa build their no-go theorem.
The utility of the process matrix formalism is that it provides a framework to describe
communication tasks between parties that lack a definite causal order. Given a set of parties
each residing in their own laboratory,
A
,
B
,
. . .
, one assumes that each party is able to act
locally on some system that passes once through their laboratory, where local operations
are described by ordinary quantum mechanics. No assumption is made concerning the
relative spatiotemporal arrangement of the laboratories, nor that there is ultimately some
causal structure within which the laboratories are positioned.
Following [
51
], the operations that any such party can perform are delineated by
aquantum instrument,
MA
, which induces—by way of a unitary transformation and
projective measurement—a transformation from input to output,
MA
i
, indexed by the
outcome,
i=
1,
. . .
,
n
.
MA
i
is a completely positive (CP) trace-non-increasing map. The set
of all CP maps for some instrument—which when taken together,
{MA
i}n
i=1 MA
,
exemplify the fact that with probability one there must be some outcome of the application
of the instrument—is a CP and trace-preserving (CPTP) map.
For a set of parties, the set of all outcomes across the laboratories corresponds to a
set of CP maps,
MA
i
,
MB
j
,
. . .
, and the complete list of probabilities
P(MA
i
,
MB
j
,
. . .)
for
all
i
,
j
,
. . .
is what
Oreshkov et al. [51] (p. 3)
call a process. The process thus exemplifies all
the operational correlations between local laboratories. An important assumption that
Oreshkov et al. make at this point is that each such joint probability is noncontextual, in the
sense that the joint probability for any set of CP maps is not dependent on the local detail of
any particular instrument
MA
. It is most obvious here in this characterisation of ‘process’
the way in which it can be seen as a generalisation of ‘state’: both can be seen as encoding
a list of probabilities over a set of measurement scenarios.
Entropy 2021,23, 12 9 of 18
Since, as above, the linear maps
MA
i
and
MB
j
can be represented, using the Choi–
Jamiołkowski isomorphism, by the linear operators
MA1A2
i
and
MB1B2
j
, respectively, the joint
probability for two measurement outcomes (
i
at
A
and
j
at
B
) can be expressed as a function
of the corresponding Choi–Jamiołkowski operators [51] (p. 4)]:
P(MA
i,MB
j) = TrhWA1A2B1B2(MA1A2
iMB1B2
j)i. (2)
Here,
WA1A2B1B2
is known as the process matrix, under the condition that it is positive
semi-definite (
WA1A2B1B2
0)—which embodies the constraint that the instruments
MA
and MBare CPTP maps—and its trace is one [56].
The process matrix is readily understood as a generalisation of a density matrix—and
so can be seen as a generalisation and extension of the notion of state—and the trace
rule (2) as a generalisation of the Born rule [
51
]. Further, more restrictive assumptions
allow one to reduce the process matrix to the quantum state (when the output systems are
one-dimensional), to reflect the characterisation of a quantum comb or network (when a
definite causal order is fixed), or to represent quantum channels with memory (when only
unidirectional signalling is possible).
With this brief survey of the process matrix formalism, let us turn our attention to the
Shrapnel–Costa no-go theorem.
3.2. Causation Does Not Explain Contextuality
Shrapnel and Costa begin by outlining a generalised operational framework to reflect
the ontological models framework of [
15
]. However, they are interested in replacing the
operational notions of preparation, transformation, and measurement procedures with
more temporally and causally neutral concepts. They replace these operations with the
general notion of local controllables,
˜
IA
, where each local controllable is indexed to a local
region,
A
,
B
,
. . .
, and each choice of local controllable is labelled by an outcome,
a
,
b
,
. . .
.
Furthermore, the physical features of the world external to the system, and independent of
the choice of local controllables, including “any global properties, initial states, connecting
mechanisms, causal influence, or global dynamics”, responsible for correlating outcomes
between local regions they call the environment,
˜
W
. Importantly, any variable correlated
with the choice of local controllable is necessarily considered an outcome and cannot be
part of the environment [4] (p. 5).
They define an event,
MA
: =
[(a
,
˜
IA)]
, as an operational equivalence class of pairs
of outcome and local controllable, such that the joint probabilities over outcomes are
equivalent for all possible outcomes and local controllables in all the other regions and for
all environments [
4
] (p. 7). In the process matrix framework (that is, in the quantum context)
this is analogous to the role played by the CP maps
MA
i
, which we can call here quantum
events. They define an instrument,
IA
, similarly as an operational equivalence class of lists
of possible (that is, with non-zero probability) events,
MA
; that is,
IA
: =
{MA
i}
. This is
analogous to the role played by the CPTP maps
MA
in the process matrix formulation,
which recall are labelled quantum instruments.
Moreover, just as we noted above that the joint probability
P(MA
i
,
MB
j
,
. . .)
is noncon-
textual, in the sense that it is not dependent on the local detail of any particular instrument
MA
, the probability of some event
MA
, so long as
IA
renders
MA
possible, is independent
of the particular instrument
I
. Thus, as above, correlations between events across different
regions are not a function the details of the instrument, which itself specifies events that
do not happen, and so events screen-off instruments. Shrapnel and Costa call this opera-
tional instrument equivalence and note that it is equivalent to noncontextuality in the former
sense [4] (p. 13).
Finally, they define a process,
W
: =
[˜
W]
, as an operational equivalence class of en-
vironments, such that the joint probabilities over outcomes given local controllables are
equivalent across the equivalence class of environments. In the quantum context,
W
is the
process matrix. This generalisation of outcomes, local controllables, and the environment
Entropy 2021,23, 12 10 of 18
into events, instruments, and the process serves to operationalise any joint probability
distribution to allow the creation of an ontological model—along the lines of the ontolog-
ical models framework—that underlies the distributions that we take to account for the
observed statistics.
The major shift enacted by Shrapnel and Costa from the ontological models framework
of [
15
,
16
] to ontological models in the process matrix framework is to move away from
the idea that the ‘state’ encodes the ontology of some system towards the idea that more
general properties of the environment are responsible for mediating correlations between
the regions. As such, they replace the ontic state λwith the ontic process ω:
our ontic process captures the physical properties of the world that remain
invariant under our local operations. That is, although we allow local properties
to change under specific operations, we wish our ontic process to capture those
aspects of reality that are independent of this probing. [4] (p. 8)
Those aspects of reality that the ontic process captures are those parts of the environ-
ment that are not within the control of the experimenters, like initial conditions, causal
influences, and global dynamics.
Shrapnel and Costa then make three natural assumptions that they take an ontological
model in their framework to obey. Firstly, they replace the notion of
λ
-mediation (as per [
19
]
above) with the notion of
ω
-mediation, in which the ontic process
ω
completely specifies
the properties of the environment that mediate correlations between regions, and screens
off outcomes produced by local controllables from the rest of the environment [4] (p. 8):
P(a,b, . . . |˜
IA,˜
IB, . . . ˜
W) = ZdωP(a,b, . . . |˜
IA,˜
IB, . . .)P(ω|˜
W). (3)
Secondly, they define the notion of instrument noncontextuality as a law of parsimony
(much like [
15
]): operationally indistinguishable pairs
(a
,
˜
IA)
,
(a0
,
˜
I0A)
should remain
ontologically indistinguishable. That is, b,c, . . . ˜
IB,˜
IC, . . . , ω[4] (p. 9):
P(a,b, . . . |ω,˜
IA,˜
IB, . . .) = P(a0,b, . . . |ω,˜
I0A,˜
IB, . . .). (4)
This allows them to define a probability distribution on the space of events, condi-
tional on instruments and the ontic process,
P(MA
,
MB
,
. . . |ω
,
IA
,
IB
,
. . .)
, in terms of a
function that maps events to probabilities. As Shrapnel and Costa point out, instrument
noncontextuality is formally identical to operational instrument equivalence, except for the
fact that instrument noncontextuality includes the ontic process.
Thirdly, they define the notion of process noncontextuality: operationally indistinguish-
able ˜
W,˜
W0should remain ontologically indistinguishable [4] (p. 9).
P(ω|˜
W) = P(ω|˜
W0). (5)
Again, this allows them to define a probability distribution on the space of ontic
processes, in terms of a function that maps ontic processes to probabilities.
The Shrapnel–Costa no-go theorem is then that there can be no ontological model that
satisfies
ω
-mediation, instrument noncontextuality, and process noncontextuality. They ar-
gue as follows. As we have just noted, each of instrument and process noncontextuality
defines a function that maps from the space of events,
{MA
,
MB
,
. . .}
, and ontic processes,
ω
, respectively, to probabilities. However, the two noncontextuality assumptions force
these functions to be ordinary positive probability distributions. Since quantum expec-
tation values cannot be expressed in this way, no instrument and process noncontextual
ontological model can reproduce the quantum statistical predictions.
3.3. Interpreting the Result
So what does this result mean, exactly? Well, to begin with, beyond pointing out the
intended consequence of their theorem, Shrapnel and Costa do not speculate on further
Entropy 2021,23, 12 11 of 18
consequences in any great detail. The intended consequence is that, since preparations,
transformations, and measurements have been replaced by local controllables, there is no
further assumption in the no-go theorem that
ω
is correlated with some controllables but
independent of others. Recall that this is the form of the ‘loophole’ in the orthodox onto-
logical models framework through which we are able to thread causally symmetric local
hidden variable approaches to defeat the nonclassical consequences of the no-go theorems
from Section 2. The part of the theorem doing most of the heavy lifting on this point is
ω
-mediation. By replacing
λ
-mediation with
ω
-mediation, the relevant correlations are not
simply a function of the quantum state, but the agent-independent rules or laws that we
take the environment to contribute to the dynamical behaviour of a system, and the connec-
tion between local action and observed events. Where causal symmetry is ideally placed
to circumvent
λ
-mediation, no such causal assumption can do so for
ω
-mediation. Thus,
this loophole is closed off in the Shrapnel–Costa theorem, rendering causally symmetric
approaches just as contextual as the rest of the models captured by the ontological models
framework [
1
]. So causally symmetric local hidden variable approaches, on account of be-
ing ontological models, must violate one of the assumptions of the Shrapnel–Costa theorem
to hope to match the statistical predictions of quantum mechanics (and superdeterministic
hidden variable models, also on account of being ontological models, fare no better at
meeting this challenge). In so far as this sets a challenge to causally symmetric approaches,
the discussion in the next section explores the possibility of meeting this challenge. To this
end, while Shrapnel and Costa note only briefly the consequences of violating each of their
assumptions, let us consider precisely what such violations entail.
The consequences of violations of the assumption of
ω
-mediation are not limited
to transgressions against a realist attitude towards the ontology of quantum systems.
As we noted just above, the assumption of
ω
-mediation insinuates that there are observer-
independent aspects of the world, such as boundary conditions and global dynamics,
that are ‘there’ to be discovered by the experimental procedure. Violations of this assump-
tion do not just offend realist attitudes towards the state, then, but would require a radical
rethink of the nature of scientific inquiry and our role as observers in that process.
Shrapnel and Costa have notable things to say about the assumption of instrument
contextuality. Firstly, it is interesting to note the possibilities that they consider in which
ontological models that satisfy instrument noncontextuality could be interpreted, from
an ordinarily time-oriented perspective, as contextual [
4
] (pp. 11–13). This is the same
phenomenon at play as the one employed by causally symmetric approaches with respect
to measurement noncontextuality. As we saw above in Section 2.1, the ‘added bonus’ of
causally symmetric approaches to contextuality in the Kochen–Specker theorem was that it
provided a natural explanation for this contextuality in terms of epistemic constraints that
arise from the ordinary temporal orientation of observers. However, the nonextendibility
result in the case of measurement noncontextuality—that no noncontextual extension of
quantum theory can provide more accurate predictions of outcomes [
57
]—holds in the case
of instrument noncontextuality, too. That is, no instrument noncontextual hidden variable
can provide more information than is contained in the process matrix [
4
] (p. 17). This result
rules out nontrivial hidden variable extensions such that obtaining greater predictive power
for quantum theory can only be achieved by the addition of contextual variables.
Violations of the assumption of instrument noncontextuality would imply that corre-
lations between events across different regions depend upon the details of the quantum
instrument—in particular, on the CP maps that are not employed as part of the choice of
local controllable—and so on events that do not in fact happen. Interestingly, this would
imply that events do not screen-off instruments, and so lends weight to the idea that
contextuality is a species of fine-tuning [
58
]. This flavour of noncontextuality has strong
similarities to preparation and measurement noncontextuality, and thus the ontological
consequences of violations of these have received considerable attention already (see,
for instance, [
17
,
59
]). Since these do not represent a particularly novel type of consequence
for the Shrapnel–Costa theorem, I will not labour these consequences here.
Entropy 2021,23, 12 12 of 18
The consequences of violations of the assumption of process noncontextuality are
certainly novel. Process contextuality implies that operationally equivalent arrangements
of an experiment do not necessarily lead to equivalent ontic descriptions of that experiment.
What is significant about this is that included in this ontic description are
all aspects of a physical scenario other than the choices of settings and the
observed outcomes. . .Such aspects include what kind of systems are involved,
the laws describing such systems, boundary conditions, etc. [4] (p. 18)
Thus, it seems that process contextuality would have a devastating effect on our ability
to conduct orthodox scientific inquiry. The implication here is that operationally equivalent
experimental arrangements may be realised by inequivalent ontic states, global properties,
causal mechanisms, laws, or boundary conditions—indeed, any part of the environment
that is not within the control of the experimenters. It is difficult to imagine exactly what this
means, ontologically speaking. However, I speculate in the next section that one solution
to a previously identified problem with a particular causally symmetric approach may
provide a suggestion as to what process contextuality could amount.
4. The End of a Classical Ontology?
We are now in a position to assess the prospects for causally symmetric local hidden
variable approaches to quantum theory in the face of the Shrapnel–Costa theorem and, in
so far as such approaches are the only approaches that fit the constraints of Einstein–Bell
realism, with them the prospects for Einstein–Bell realism and a classical ontology. To some,
the loss of the possibility of a classical ontology is surely no news at all; as I noted in the
opening sentence to this work, many physicists gave up on the view that the fundamental
ontology of quantum mechanics is essentially classical after 1927, and certainly after the
Bohr-Einstein debates ran their course beyond 1935 [25,60].
Thus the first obvious option in response to the Shrapnel–Costa theorem is to accept
that any rescue effort for Einstein–Bell realism is now determinately impossible. If one
wanted, one could still maintain that the wavefunction be interpreted as
ψ
-epistemic,
so long as there were no classical ontology underlying the wavefunction description (as in
some versions of QBism [
61
]). Alternatively, one could maintain a realist attitude towards
the quantum formalism by adopting a
ψ
-ontic interpretation, with or without additional
ontic degrees of freedom. Perhaps the clearest avenue here is a
ψ
-ontic wavefunction
without additional ontic structure (such as the many-worlds interpretation [
62
]), as one
must keep in mind that any additional ontic degrees of freedom would need to be nonlocal
and/or contextual.
However, is there a way to rescue Einstein–Bell realism? I see only two remaining
options. The first is to undermine the Shrapnel–Costa theorem, possibly by rejecting one
or more underlying assumptions. It is a difficult task to identify the most appropriate
foundations to challenge, but perhaps rethinking the nature of causality, inference, and/or
probability might be a fruitful place to begin searching. (Hofer-Szabó
[63]
considers the
possibility of giving up on Spekkens’ definition of generalised noncontextuality, which also
underpins the Shrapnel–Costa theorem, and simply permitting unproblematically the pos-
sibility of a quantum system responding differently to different measurements represented
by the same operator.)
Schmid et al. [
22
] propose a generalisation of causality and inference—what they call a
causal-inferential theory—with the express intention of avoiding the consequences of the tra-
ditional no-go theorems that rule out local or noncontextual realist approaches. They make
the suggestion that previous such generalisations that can be employed to provide di-
agnoses of the true consequences of the no-go theorems “scramble” the ontological and
epistemological aspects of this problem. The previous generalisations they mention include
the ontological models framework from above [
15
], quantum generalisations of proposi-
tional logic (‘quantum logic’ [
64
66
]), operational probability theories (which originate
from the Pavia group [
67
]), generalised probability theories (beyond quantum logic [
68
]),
and a nonclassical generalisation of Bayesian inference [
52
]. What is significant about this
Entropy 2021,23, 12 13 of 18
proposal is the way that Schmid et al. are explicitly attempting to “salvage” the notions of
locality and noncontextuality, and so salvage, at least in part, a classical ontology. A rough
outline of their main conjecture is as follows.
Recall that in Section 2.2 we were introduced to the term Leibnizianity that Schmid et al.
employ to characterise generalised noncontextuality. Their formalisation simply captures
the proclamation that there should be no ontological difference without operational differ-
ence. They claim that the traditional noncontextuality no-go theorems constrain logical
space, as we noted above in Section 2.1, to either contextual realist approaches—and so to
violations of Leibnizianity—or to approaches that forego some aspect of realism about the
quantum state. The key claim of Schmid et al. is that they identify that it is indeed possible
to have a Leibnizian realist interpretation of quantum theory, but only so long as the causal
and inferential components are inherently nonclassical. While they do not provide any great
amount of detail, they note that quantum causal modelling [
52
55
] is likely to play a signif-
icant role in the development of any such realist interpretation, as well as more abstract
characterisations of probability theory [
69
]. While the sentiment of this project is laudable,
I make merely two cautionary comments in passing. As a rejoinder to the involvement of
quantum causal modelling, it seems as though the Shrapnel–Costa theorem, which itself
is built on the principles of quantum causal modelling, will make it difficult for any such
generalisation on its own to salvage noncontextuality. On the involvement of abstract char-
acterisations of probability theory, any generalisation of probability theory that salvages
noncontextuality that is non-Kolmogorovian faces the contention—brought by Feintzeig
and Fletcher
[70]
—that it simply does not offer any clear advantage, in terms of, say, guid-
ing rational action, over contextual theories with ordinary Kolmogorovian probability.
The second remaining option for rescuing Einstein–Bell realism is arguably the more
interesting for proponents of causal symmetry. This option would entail biting the bullet on
contextuality, and either (i) considering the contextuality merely apparent and finding some
natural explanation for it in terms of noncontextual ontic structure and some epistemic con-
straint, or (ii) accepting that quantum theory is underpinned by contextual ontic structure
and then accounting for how the world might conspire to render this contextuality opera-
tionally undetectable in a classical setting (or, perhaps even both (i) and (ii)). The former,
of course, is the method by which causally symmetric approaches meet the challenge of the
Kochen–Specker theorem and the ontological models framework. The natural explanation
there is that an observer’s ordinary temporal orientation constrains epistemic access to
the future causes that influence the properties of some quantum system’s beables, and so
make these ultimately noncontextual hidden variables seem contextual from the observer’s
perspective. The ideal response for proponents of causal symmetry in the current scenario
would be to identify a corresponding epistemic, or otherwise, constraint that shows how
apparent contextuality can arise from actual noncontextuality. While I do not have a defini-
tive argument to demonstrate the plausibility of such an account, I would like to make
a speculative suggestion for the sort of constraint and corresponding consequences that
might be required for this task.
However, before I do, it is worth pushing the dialectic of this work towards the
following inconvenient conclusion. If the primary motivation for adopting a causally
symmetric framework is to rescue Einstein–Bell realism, then we have just seen that the
Shrapnel–Costa theorem renders this task either impossible, or at best beholden to the
possibility of some further account explaining how, say, apparent contextuality arises
from some noncontextual footing. However, and importantly, even if such an account
could be found, it still may not be enough to rescue Einstein–Bell realism. Whether it
does or not hangs on how ‘natural’ the account is. As we saw in Section 2.2, one of the
strengths of causally symmetric approaches that rescue Einstein–Bell realism from the
traditional no-go theorems is that the ideology of causal symmetry is more economical
than a rejection of classical ontology. However, it is difficult to see how any account
that introduces potentially artificial constraints or complex mechanisms can be proposed
Entropy 2021,23, 12 14 of 18
without significantly reducing the ideological economy of causal symmetry, jeopardising
the very grounds upon which one might consider the approach more virtuous [1].
Thus, in response to the Shrapnel–Costa theorem, the outlook is particularly worrying
for Einstein–Bell realism and classical ontology. Not only is the obvious consequence of
the theorem is a straightforward rejection of Einstein–Bell realism, but even where there
looks to be a possibility of accounting for contextual ontic variables within a causally
symmetric framework, the cost of such an account could result in a dramatic decrease
in the ideological economy of causal symmetry, and so render the rejection of classical
ontology favourable on grounds of scientific virtue. Either way, it looks very difficult to
maintain a classical ontology for quantum theory.
Despite this pessimistic prognosis, I will finish this part of the dialectic with a specula-
tive suggestion of where I see the most promising kind of possibilities for Einstein–Bell
realism in the face the Shrapnel–Costa theorem. In [
3
] we considered some peculiar prob-
lems faced by what we call the Price–Wharton approach to causally symmetric local hidden
variables in the context of a universal
ψ
-epistemic wavefunction (which we refer to as
Ψ
-epistemic quantum cosmology). The problem is the following. The Price–Wharton ap-
proach poses a two-time boundary value problem for the kinematics of the underlying
hidden variables. Additionally, as a result of the traditional no-go theorems, initial data on
a Cauchy surface forming a well-posed Cauchy problem and comprised of local, noncontex-
tual classical variables cannot possibly recover the statistical predictions of quantum theory.
This is despite the fact that the initial data about the quantum state on the same Cauchy
surface perfectly well comprise a well-posed Cauchy problem, due to the parabolicity of
the Schrödinger equation. That the ontic state variables on the initial Cauchy surface do
not comprise a well-posed Cauchy problem should be expected, though, as a two-time
boundary problem requires additional information from the final boundary to obtain a
complete determination between the boundaries. So sufficient initial data on a Cauchy
surface to form a well-posed Cauchy problem would lead to an overdetermination of the
ontic state at the final boundary. One way around this that we consider is that the laws
governing the ontic state variables cannot be parabolic or hyperbolic PDEs.
However, there is an alternative, more speculative possibility that we briefly consider
in this context, albeit one that is set to one side in [
3
]. The ontic state variables do solve
a Cauchy problem, but are also determined as a two-time boundary problem (so as to
circumvent the no-go theorems). The tension generated by this overdetermination is
addressed by a constraint on the free action of an agent controlling the nature of the data
on the initial and final boundary. We put it as follows:
the tension that would need to be resolved is between: (i) the solution of a Cauchy
problem from freely, arbitrarily and (ideally) completely specifiable initial data;
and (ii) the symmetric expectation that the final boundary be equally freely,
arbitrarily and completely specifiable. One way to escape this tension would be
to remove the freedom to completely specify data on the final boundary: an agent
controlling the final boundary would just happen to ‘choose’ a measurement
that concords with the deterministic evolution of the ontic state. However,
this would break the symmetry between the final and initial boundaries and
would also remove the element of control that renders the Price–Wharton picture
causally symmetric. To retain the symmetry would thus require some as-yet-
unspecified principled constraint that limits an agent’s ability to freely, arbitrarily
and completely specify both initial and final boundary data. This constraint must
be such that the aspects of the ontic state on the initial Cauchy surface that are a
consequence of the choices specified at the final boundary are not epistemically
accessible before the final boundary is specified—and vice versa. [3] (p. 7)
The significance of this possibility for the dialectic around the Shrapnel–Costa theorem
is the following. Consider the nature of this proposed constraint on an agent’s ability to
control the boundary data. One way for this constraint to work would be to limit agential
control over the complete specifiability of data on both the initial and final boundary (in the
Entropy 2021,23, 12 15 of 18
same way as one can perform quantum measurements, but cannot control the precise
outcome). Another way for this constraint to work would be to limit, say, the time intervals
at which an agent can specify data on initial and final boundaries. Without such a temporal
constraint, we should expect the data on the initial and final boundaries in a two-time
boundary value account to be generally related by elliptic PDEs. However, one could
imagine, albeit in a highly speculative fashion, that if the distance between the bound-
aries were constrained to certain discrete time intervals—perhaps frequent enough to be
practically undetectable to the agent—the initial and final ontic state variables could be re-
lated consistently by some hyperbolic PDE. (One could think of this as roughly analogous
to turning a ‘thick’ sandwich problem into a ‘thin’ sandwich problem in geometrody-
namics [
71
73
]. This problem in geometrodynamics is motivated by the corresponding
problem in electrodynamics, where the free specification of data on two boundaries with
periodic boundary conditions can be made consistent by stipulating that the interval of
time between the two boundaries is an integer multiple of a half period of the harmonic
oscillation of the field [
72
] (p. 355)). This would apparently resemble a well-posed Cauchy
problem over the ontic state variables on the initial boundary, but those variables would
be at least partly determined by the ontic state on the final boundary. There would be
overdetermination in such a case, but the overdetermination would be fine-tuned so as not
to create a contradiction. An agent would then be similarly constrained to intervene on a
system at specific times on pain of generating a contradiction in the hidden variables that
describe the kinematical properties of some quantum system between the boundaries.
This speculative example is interesting because of its potential realisation of process
contextuality. According to process contextuality, the parts of the physical system that are
contextual could include ontic states, global properties, causal mechanisms, dynamical
laws, and boundary conditions. This implies that these features of the ontic process might
depend upon the context of measurement. This seems to be a feature of the above example:
the ontic state variables on the boundaries, and whether they are modelled by, say, elliptical
or hyperbolic dynamical laws depends upon, say, the precise time intervals across which
the agent is able to intervene on the system. In addition, this account looks highly fine-
tuned, which also appears to be a feature of process contextuality. Could this then be a case
of process contextuality?
Moreover, the imagined (and admittedly unspecified) constraint on the agent that
limits the agent’s capability “to freely, arbitrarily, and completely specify both initial and
final boundary data” to specific time intervals should ultimately, with the right detail,
render such a causally symmetric local hidden variable approach process noncontextual, as
the constraint removes the above-mentioned contextuality (but admittedly for the price of
fine-tuning). This, by my lights, appears to qualify as biting the bullet on contextuality as
per the Shrapnel–Costa theorem, but also as having such process contextuality be merely
apparent. This is because the apparent contextuality would simply be a feature of our
continuous-time model of the causally symmetric hidden variables, which themselves are
determined on a discrete-time basis due to the constraint. Provided that the imagined
constraint could be given a ‘natural’ explanation (which I have certainly not attempted
here), the process contextuality could be accounted for in terms of noncontextual ontic
structure and some agent-centred constraint. However, there must be considerable doubt
concerning whether such a constraint could provide a natural explanation, at the very
least because it explicitly introduces fine-tuning into the explanation of how apparent
contextuality arises from a noncontextual ontic state. So long as one thinks that a Leibnizian
principle of parsimony is a good guide to scientific methodology, fine-tuning of this sort is
not a virtue of a theory—and it is moreover worth noting that, due to the nonextendibility
result above, the addition of noncontextual ontic structure cannot provide more information
than is contained in the quantum description.
I do not mention this speculative example here to argue in its favour, by any means.
My purpose here is to provide a demonstration of the sort of argumentation that would be
required as part of what is arguably the only reasonable path forward for the Einstein–Bell
Entropy 2021,23, 12 16 of 18
realist. What is required is an account of, say, apparent process contextuality that has these
sorts of features. This moreover demonstrates the interrelation between the naturalness
of the constraint and the ideological economy of the model: unless the constraint makes
use of uncontroversial features of time, space, agency, and so on, it will face a hard task
keeping the ideology economical.
5. Final Thoughts
Is this the end of a classical ontology for quantum mechanics? Yes, I think this has to
be the end. Perhaps there is hope that locality and noncontextuality can be salvaged by
an appropriate generalisation of probability theory and the characterisation of inference.
However, the path ahead for the causal symmetry program looks less hopeful. While there
is an open logical possibility that a causally symmetric hidden variable approach might be
able to provide a natural explanation of how a noncontextual ontic state might appear to
be contextual on account of some low-cost constraint, this seems at the present moment
highly unlikely. What is more, the nonextendibility result implies that any noncontextual
ontic state cannot contribute to the predictive power of quantum mechanics—any such
contribution can only be made by additional instrument-contextual variables. So any such
logical possibility is unlikely to render accepting causal symmetry more economical than
rejecting a classical ontology, and will necessarily fail to contribute to increased predictive
power for quantum mechanics. In so far as this unlikely logical possibility is the last refuge
for Einstein–Bell realism, it looks like we should give up on Einstein–Bell realism and,
with it, classical ontology.
Funding:
This research was funded by the University of Queensland and the Australian Government
through the Australian Research Council (DE170100808).
Acknowledgments:
This work is based on a talk I gave at the BSPS conference in 2018. Some of this
talk, including parts of the logical structure and the broad recommendation, is dispersed amongst
the detail of [
1
]. For useful discussion and comments I would like to thank Fabio Costa, Simon
Friederich, Sean Gryb, Sally Shrapnel, Karim Thébault, Ken Wharton, and the audience at the BSPS
2018 conference held at the University of Oxford.
Conflicts of Interest: The author declares no conflict of interest.
References
1.
Friederich, S.; Evans, P.W. Retrocausality in Quantum Mechanics. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Zalta, E.N., Ed.;
Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2019.
2.
Wharton, K.B.; Argaman, N. Colloquium: Bell’s theorem and locally mediated reformulations of quantum mechanics. Rev. Mod.
Phys. 2020,92, 21002, [CrossRef]
3. Evans, P.W.; Gryb, S.; Thébault, K.P. Ψ-epistemic quantum cosmology? Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 2016,56, 1–12, [CrossRef]
4. Shrapnel, S.; Costa, F. Causation does not explain contextuality. Quantum 2018,2, 63, [CrossRef]
5. von Neumann, J. Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik; Springer: Berlin, Germany, 1932.
6.
Bohm, D. A Suggested Interpretation of the Quantum Theory in Terms of “Hidden” Variables. I. Phys. Rev.
1952
,85, 166–179,
[CrossRef]
7. Bell, J.S. On the Problem of Hidden Variables in Quantum Mechanics. Rev. Mod. Phys. 1966,38, 447–452,
[CrossRef]
8. Norsen, T. John S. Bell’s concept of local causality. Am. J. Phys. 2011,79, 1261–1275, [CrossRef]
9.
Wiseman, H.M.; Cavalcanti, E.G. Causarum Investigatio and the Two Bell’s Theorems of John Bell. In Quantum [Un]Speakables II:
Half a Century of Bell’s Theorem; Bertlmann, R., Zeilinger, A., Eds.; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Switzerland, 2017;
pp. 119–142, [CrossRef]
10. Bell, J.S. Bertlemann’s socks and the nature of reality. J. Phys. Colloq. 1981,42, 41–62, [CrossRef]
11.
Bell, J.S. La nouvelle cuisine. In Between Science and Technology; Sarlemijn, A.; Kroes, P., Eds.; Elsevier: Amsterdam,
The Netherlands, 1990; pp. 97–115, [CrossRef]
12. Kochen, S.; Specker, E.P. The Problem of Hidden Variables in Quantum Mechanics. J. Math. Mech. 1967,17, 59–87. [CrossRef]
13. Wharton, K.B. Time-Symmetric Boundary Conditions and Quantum Foundations. Symmetry 2010,2, 272–283,
[CrossRef]
14. Wharton, K.B. Quantum states as ordinary information. Information 2014,5, 190–208, [CrossRef]
Entropy 2021,23, 12 17 of 18
15.
Spekkens, R.W. Contextuality for preparations, transformations, and unsharp measurements. Phys. Rev. A
2005
,71, 52108,
[CrossRef]
16.
Harrigan, N.; Spekkens, R.W. Einstein, Incompleteness, and the Epistemic View of Quantum States. Found. Phys.
2010
,
40, 125–157, [CrossRef]
17. Leifer, M.S. Is the Quantum State Real? An Extended Review of Ψ-ontology Theorems. Quanta 2014,3, 67–155, [CrossRef]
18.
Ringbauer, M. Exploring Quantum Foundations with Single Photons; Springer Theses, Springer International Publishing: Cham,
Switzerland, 2017.
19.
Leifer, M.S.; Pusey, M.F. Is a time symmetric interpretation of quantum theory possible without retrocausality? Proc. R. Soc. Lond.
A2017,473, [CrossRef]
20. Pusey, M.F.; Barrett, J.; Rudolph, T. On the reality of the quantum state. Nat. Phys. 2012,8, 475–478, [CrossRef]
21.
Spekkens, R.W. The ontological identity of empirical indiscernibles: Leibniz’s methodological principle and its significance in the
work of Einstein. arXiv 2019, arXiv:1909.04628.
22.
Schmid, D.; Selby, J.H.; Spekkens, R.W. Unscrambling the omelette of causation and inference: The framework of causal-inferential
theories. arXiv 2020, arXiv:2009.03297.
23. Evans, P.W. Retrocausality at no extra cost. Synthese 2015,192, 1139–1155, [CrossRef]
24. Quine, W.V.O. Ontology and Ideology. Philos. Stud. 1951,2, 11–15, [CrossRef]
25.
Einstein, A.; Podolsky, B.; Rosen, N. Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?
Phys. Rev. 1935,47, 777–780, [CrossRef]
26. Bell, J.S. The Theory of Local Beables. Epistemol. Lett. 1976,9, 11–24,
27.
Accardi, L. Nonrelativistic Quantum Mechanics as a Noncommutative Markof Process. Adv. Math.
1976
,20, 329–366, [CrossRef]
28.
Lindblad, G. Non-Markovian Quantum Stochastic Processes and Their Entropy. Commun. Math. Phys.
1979
,65, 281–294,
[CrossRef]
29.
O’Brien, J.L.; Pryde, G.J.; Gilchrist, A.; James, D.F.V.; Langford, N.K.; Ralph, T.C.; White, A.G. Quantum Process Tomography of a
Controlled-NOT Gate. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2004,93, 80502, [CrossRef] [PubMed]
30.
Riebe, M.; Kim, K.; Schindler, P.; Monz, T.; Schmidt, P.O.; Körber, T.K.; Hänsel, W.; Häffner, H.; Roos, C.F.; Blatt, R. Process
Tomography of Ion Trap Quantum Gates. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2006,97, 220407, [CrossRef] [PubMed]
31.
Kok, P.; Munro, W.J.; Nemoto, K.; Ralph, T.C.; Dowling, J.P.; Milburn, G.J. Linear optical quantum computing with photonic
qubits. Rev. Mod. Phys. 2007,79, 135–174, [CrossRef]
32.
Mohseni, M.; Lidar, D.A. Direct characterization of quantum dynamics: General theory. Phys. Rev. A
2007
,75, 62331, [CrossRef]
33.
Riebe, M.; Chwalla, M.; Benhelm, J.; Häffner, H.; Hänsel, W.; Roos, C.F.; Blatt, R. Quantum teleportation with atoms: Quantum
process tomography. New J. Phys. 2007,9, 211–211, [CrossRef]
34. Kretschmann, D.; Werner, R.F. Quantum channels with memory. Phys. Rev. A 2005,72, 62323, [CrossRef]
35.
Jamiołkowski, A. Linear transformations which preserve trace and positive semidefiniteness of operators. Rep. Math. Phys.
1972
,
3, 275–278, [CrossRef]
36. Choi, M.D. Completely positive linear maps on complex matrices. Linear Algebra Its Appl. 1975,10, 285–290, [CrossRef]
37. Adlam, E. The Operational Choi–Jamiołkowski Isomorphism. Entropy 2020,22, 1063, [CrossRef] [PubMed]
38.
Chiribella, G.; D’Ariano, G.M.; Perinotti, P. Quantum Circuit Architecture. Phys. Rev. Lett.
2008
,101, 60401, [CrossRef] [PubMed]
39.
Chiribella, G.; D’Ariano, G.M.; Perinotti, P. Theoretical framework for quantum networks. Phys. Rev. A
2009
,80, 22339, [CrossRef]
40.
Modi, K. Operational approach to open dynamics and quantifying initial correlations. Sci. Rep.
2012
,2, 581, [CrossRef] [PubMed]
41.
Luchnikov, I.A.; Vintskevich, S.V.; Filippov, S.N. Dimension truncation for open quantum systems in terms of tensor networks.
arXiv 2018, arXiv:1801.07418.
42.
Chiribella, G.; D’Ariano, G.M.; Perinotti, P. Transforming quantum operations: Quantum supermaps. Europhys. Lett.
2008
,
83, 30004, [CrossRef]
43.
Gutoski, G.; Watrous, J. Toward a General Theory of Quantum Games. In Proceedings of the Thirty-Ninth Annual ACM
Symposium on Theory of Computing, San Diego, CA, USA, 11–13 June 2007; Association for Computing Machinery: New York,
NY, USA, 2007; pp. 565–574, [CrossRef]
44. Hardy, L. The operator tensor formulation of quantum theory. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. A 2012,370, 3385–3417, [CrossRef]
45.
Chiribella, G. Perfect discrimination of no-signalling channels via quantum superposition of causal structures. Phys. Rev. A
2012
,
86, 40301, [CrossRef]
46.
Colnaghi, T.; D’Ariano, G.M.; Facchini, S.; Perinotti, P. Quantum computation with programmable connections between gates.
Phys. Lett. A 2012,376, 2940–2943, [CrossRef]
47.
Chiribella, G.; D’Ariano, G.M.; Perinotti, P.; Valiron, B. Quantum computations without definite causal structure. Phys. Rev. A
2013,88, 022318, [CrossRef]
48.
Hardy, L. Probability Theories with Dynamic Causal Structure: A New Framework for Quantum Gravity. arXiv
2005
, arXiv:gr-
qc/0509120.
49.
Oeckl, R. A “general boundary” formulation for quantum mechanics and quantum gravity. Phys. Lett. B
2003
,575, 318–324,
[CrossRef]
50.
Aharonov, Y.; Bergmann, P.G.; Lebowitz, J.L. Time Symmetry in the Quantum Process of Measurement. Phys. Rev.
1964
,
134, B1410–B1416, [CrossRef]
Entropy 2021,23, 12 18 of 18
51. Oreshkov, O.; Costa, F.; Brukner, v. Quantum correlations with no causal order. Nat. Commun. 2012,3, 1092, [CrossRef]
52.
Leifer, M.S.; Spekkens, R.W. Towards a formulation of quantum theory as a causally neutral theory of Bayesian inference.
Phys. Rev. A 2013,88, 52130, [CrossRef]
53.
Cavalcanti, E.G.; Lal, R. On modifications of Reichenbach’s principle of common cause in light of Bell’s theorem. J. Phys. Math.
Theor. 2014,47, 424018, [CrossRef]
54. Costa, F.; Shrapnel, S. Quantum causal modelling. New J. Phys. 2016,18, 063032, [CrossRef]
55.
Allen, J.M.A.; Barrett, J.; Horsman, D.C.; Lee, C.M.; Spekkens, R.W. Quantum Common Causes and Quantum Causal Models.
Phys. Rev. X 2017,7, 031021, [CrossRef]
56.
Wood, C.J. Non-Completely Positive Maps: Properties and Applications. Ph.D. Thesis, Macquarie University, Sydney, NSW,
Australia, 2009.
57. Chen, Z.; Montina, A. Measurement contextuality is implied by macroscopic realism. Phys. Rev. A 2011,83, 42110, [CrossRef]
58.
Cavalcanti, E.G. Classical Causal Models for Bell and Kochen-Specker Inequality Violations Require Fine-Tuning. Phys. Rev. X
2018,8, 21018, [CrossRef]
59. Harrigan, N.; Rudolph, T. Ontological models and the interpretation of contextuality. arXiv 2007, arXiv:0709.4266.
60.
Bohr, N. Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality be Considered Complete? Phys. Rev.
1935
,48, 696–702,
[CrossRef]
61.
Fuchs, C.A.; Mermin, N.D.; Schack, R. An introduction to QBism with an application to the locality of quantum mechanics. Am. J.
Phys. 2014,82, 749–754, [CrossRef]
62.
Wallace, D. The Emergent Multiverse: Quantum Theory according to the Everett Interpretation; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2012.
63.
Hofer-Szabó, G. Commutativity, comeasurability, and contextuality in the Kochen-Specker arguments. arXiv
2020
,
arXiv:2004.1405.
64. Jauch, J.M.; Piron, C. Can hidden variables be excluded in quantum mechanics? Helv. Phys. Acta 1963,36, 827–837.
65. Gudder, S. On the quantum logic approach to quantum mechanics. Commun. Math. Phys. 1969,12, 1–15, [CrossRef]
66.
Mittelstaedt, P.; Logic, Q. In PSA 1974: Proceedings of the 1974 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association; Cohen,
R.S., Hooker, C.A., Michalos, A.C., Van Evra, J.W., Eds.; D. Reidel Publishing Company: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1976;
pp. 501–514, [CrossRef]
67. Chiribella, G.; D’Ariano, G.M.; Perinotti, P. Probabilistic theories with purification. Phys. Rev. A 2010,81, 62348, [CrossRef]
68. Hardy, L. Quantum Theory From Five Reasonable Axioms. arXiv 2001, arXiv:quant-ph/0101012.
69.
Fritz, T. A synthetic approach to Markov kernels, conditional independence and theorems on sufficient statistics. Adv. Math.
2020,370, 107239, [CrossRef]
70.
Feintzeig, B.H.; Fletcher, S.C. On Noncontextual, Non-Kolmogorovian Hidden Variable Theories. Found. Phys.
2017
,47, 294–315,
[CrossRef]
71.
Baierlein, R.F.; Sharp, D.H.; Wheeler, J.A. Three-Dimensional Geometry as Carrier of Information about Time. Phys. Rev.
1962
,
126, 1864–1865, [CrossRef]
72.
Wheeler, J.A. Geometrodynamics and the Issue of the Final State. In Relativity, Groups, and Topology; DeWitt, C., DeWitt, B., Eds.;
Gordon and Breach Science Publishers: New York, NY, USA, 1964; pp. 315–520.
73. Misner, C.W.; Thorne, K.S.; Wheeler, J.A. Gravitation; H. W. Freeman and Company: San Francisco, CA, USA, 1973.
... The recent paper by Evans [12] takes as his point of departure what is called Einstein-Bell realism. It starts with 3 conditions: 1) Quantum mechanical probabilities are epistemic; 2) Quantum mechanics is local; 3) Quantum mechanics is consistent with the no-go theorems. ...
... The no-go theorems play an important role. Three are discussed in [12]: (i) The Bell theorem; (ii) The Kochen-Specker theorem; and (iii) The recent Shrapnel-Costa theorem. The Shrapnel-Costa theorem is seen as an extension of the Kochen-Specker theorem. ...
... Anyway, the conclusion of [12] is as follows: Causal symmetry is incapable of explaining quantum behaviour as arising as a result of noncontextual ontological properties of the world. This leads, Evans says, to a rejection of Einstein-Bell realism. ...
Preprint
Full-text available
In this paper, epistemology and ontology of quantum states are discussed based on a completely new way of founding quantum theory. The fundamental notions are conceptual variables in the mind of an observer or in the joint minds of a group of observers. These conceptual variables are very often accessible, that is, it is possible to find values of the variables by doing experiments or by making measurements. An important notion is that of maximal accessibility. It is shown here that this new machinery may facilitate the discussion of when a specific quantum state can be given an ontological interpretation, and also the more speculative question whether all states can be given such an interpretation. The discussion here is general, and has implications for the basic problem of how one should look upon information from experiments and measurement, in particularly when this information reflects properties of the real world.
... Two weaknesses of that paper, however, are first that statistical inference is limited to Bayesian inference, and next that the paper, in some sense, mixes the concept of ontology with something related to cause-and-effect relations. Another answer to the question of whether classical ontology can be made compatible with quantum mechanics is given by Evans [13], a paper where [13] is criticized as well. My own views on this question are now given in [14]. ...
... Two weaknesses of that paper, however, are first that statistical inference is limited to Bayesian inference, and next that the paper, in some sense, mixes the concept of ontology with something related to cause-and-effect relations. Another answer to the question of whether classical ontology can be made compatible with quantum mechanics is given by Evans [13], a paper where [13] is criticized as well. My own views on this question are now given in [14]. ...
Preprint
Full-text available
An alternative approach towards quantum theory is described, and tentative attempts to connect his approach to special and general relativity are discussed. Important concepts are gauge groups and information/entropy connected to some physical systems. Some recent results on information in connection to black holes are touched upon.
... Two weaknesses of that paper, however, are first that statistical inference is limited to Bayesian inference, and next that the paper in some sense mixes the concept of ontology with something related to cause-and effect relations. Another answer to the question of whether classical ontology can be made compatible with quantum mechanics, is given by Evans [13], a paper where also [13] is criticized. My own views on this question are now given in [14]. ...
... Two weaknesses of that paper, however, are first that statistical inference is limited to Bayesian inference, and next that the paper in some sense mixes the concept of ontology with something related to cause-and effect relations. Another answer to the question of whether classical ontology can be made compatible with quantum mechanics, is given by Evans [13], a paper where also [13] is criticized. My own views on this question are now given in [14]. ...
Preprint
Full-text available
An alternative approach towards quantum theory is described, and tentative attempts to connect his approach to special and general relativity are discussed. Important concepts are gauge groups and information/entropy connected to some physical systems. Some recent results on information in connection to black holes are touched upon, and it is indicated how expected information can be argued to be conserved. This argument only depends on what happens outside the black hole. Everything connected to the interior of the black hole is inaccessible.
... A detailed account of the important exchange between Pechukas (1994Pechukas ( , 1995 and Alicki (1995) is given by Cuffaro & Myrvold (2013), who also suggest a deflationary way to resolve the impasse. Schmid, Reid, & Spekkens (2019) relate the debate over complete positivity to the literature on causal models (for further discussion, see Evans, 2021). 32 Cf. ...
... Causality: Classical accounts of interventionist causality (Pearl, 2009;Woodward, 2003), as well as quantum generalizations (Allen, Barrett, Horsman, Lee, & Spekkens, 2017;Costa & Shrapnel, 2016;Evans, 2018Evans, , 2021Shrapnel, 2019), rely essentially on the concept of an open system yet assume the closed systems view of physics (in quantum generalizations, they assume ST). As a consequence, some proponents (see Woodward 2007 and for discussion and criticism see Reutlinger 2013) argue that interventionist accounts are not applicable to physics, at least not at the global scale (Woodward, 2007, sec. ...
Article
There is a deeply entrenched view in philosophy and physics, the closed systems view, according to which isolated systems are conceived of as fundamental. On this view, when a system is under the influence of its environment this is described in terms of a coupling between it and a separate system which taken together are isolated. We argue against this view, and in favor of the alternative open systems view, for which systems interacting with their environment are conceived of as fundamental, and the environment's influence is represented via the dynamical equations that govern the system's evolution. Taking quantum theories of closed and open systems as our case study, and considering three alternative notions of fundamentality: (i)~ontic fundamentality, (ii)~epistemic fundamentality, and (iii)~explanatory fundamentality, we argue that the open systems view is fundamental, and that this has important implications for the philosophy of physics, the philosophy of science, and for metaphysics.
... A detailed account of the important exchange between Pechukas (1994Pechukas ( , 1995 and Alicki (1995) is given by Cuffaro & Myrvold (2013), who also suggest a deflationary way to resolve the impasse. Schmid, Reid, & Spekkens (2019) relate the debate over complete positivity to the literature on causal models (for further discussion, see Evans, 2021). 32 Cf. ...
... Causality: Classical accounts of interventionist causality (Pearl, 2009;Woodward, 2003), as well as quantum generalizations (Allen, Barrett, Horsman, Lee, & Spekkens, 2017;Costa & Shrapnel, 2016;Evans, 2018Evans, , 2021Shrapnel, 2019), rely essentially on the concept of an open system yet assume the closed systems view of physics (in quantum generalizations, they assume ST). As a consequence, some proponents (see Woodward 2007 and for discussion and criticism see Reutlinger 2013) argue that interventionist accounts are not applicable to physics, at least not at the global scale (Woodward, 2007, sec. ...
Preprint
There is a deeply entrenched view in philosophy and physics, the closed systems view, according to which isolated systems are conceived of as fundamental. On this view, when a system is under the influence of its environment this is described in terms of a coupling between it and a separate system which taken together are isolated. We argue against this view, and in favor of the alternative open systems view, for which systems interacting with their environment are conceived of as fundamental, and the environment's influence is represented via the dynamical equations that govern the system's evolution. Taking quantum theories of closed and open systems as our case study, and considering three alternative notions of fundamentality: (i) ontic fundamentality, (ii) epistemic fundamentality, and (iii) explanatory fundamentality, we argue that the open systems view is fundamental, and that this has important implications for the philosophy of physics, the philosophy of science, and for metaphysics.
... Two weaknesses of that paper, however, are first that statistical inference is limited to Bayesian inference, and next that the paper in some sense mixes the concept of ontology with something related to cause-and-effect relations. Another answer to the question of whether classical ontology can be made compatible with quantum mechanics is given by Evans [13], a paper where [12] is criticized as well. My own views on this question are now given in [14]. ...
Preprint
Full-text available
An alternative approach towards quantum theory is described, and tentative attempts to connect his approach to special and general relativity are discussed. Important concepts are gauge groups and information/entropy connected to some physical systems. Some recent results on information in connection to black holes are touched upon, and it is indicated how expected information can be argued to be conserved. This argument only depends on what happens outside the black hole. Everything connected to the interior of the black hole is inaccessible.
... The discussion about the incompleteness of quantum mechanics is out of the scope of this paper. It is still the subject of debate and we limit ourselves to mentioning a recent paper by Evans [30]. We believe that our paper proves that CIBR affords an explanation of bounded rationality that does not require quantum probability without giving up classical ontology, thereby suggesting that CIBR deserves some attention in the debate on quantum mechanical incompleteness. ...
Article
Full-text available
The bounded rationality mainstream is based on interesting experiments showing human behaviors violating classical probability (CP) laws. Quantum probability (QP) has been shown to successfully figure out such issues, supporting the hypothesis that quantum mechanics is the central fundamental pillar for brain function and cognition emergence. We discuss the decision-making model (DMM), a paradigmatic instance of criticality, which deals with bounded rationality issues in a similar way as QP, generating choices that cannot be accounted by CP. We define this approach as criticality-induced bounded rationality (CIBR). For some aspects, CIBR is even more satisfactory than QP. Our work may contribute to considering criticality as another possible fundamental pillar in order to improve the understanding of cognition and of quantum mechanics as well.
Article
Theories of consciousness grounded in neuroscience must explain the phenomenal binding problem, e.g., how micro-units of information are combined to create the macro-scale conscious experience common to human phenomenology. An example is how single ‘pixels’ of a visual scene are experienced as a single holistic image in the ‘mind’s eye’, rather than as individual, separate, and massively parallel experiences, corresponding perhaps to individual neuron activations, neural ensembles, or foveal saccades, any of which could conceivably deliver identical functionality from an information processing point of view. There are multiple contested candidate solutions to the phenomenal binding problem. This paper explores how the metaphysical infrastructure of Integrated Information Theory (IIT) v4.0 can provide a distinctive solution. The solution—that particular entities aggregable from multiple units (‘complexes’) define existence—might work in a static picture, but introduces issues in a dynamic system. We ask what happens to our phenomenal self as the main complex moves around a biological neural network. Our account of conscious entities developing through time leads to an apparent dilemma for IIT theorists between non-local entity transitions and contiguous selves: the ‘dynamic entity evolution problem’. As well as specifying the dilemma, we describe three ways IIT might dissolve the dilemma before it gains traction. Clarifying IIT’s position on the phenomenal binding problem, potentially underpinned with novel empirical or theoretical research, helps researchers understand IIT and assess its plausibility. We see our paper as contributing to IIT’s current research emphasis on the shift from static to dynamic analysis.
Article
Full-text available
In this article, I use an operational formulation of the Choi–Jamiołkowski isomorphism to explore an approach to quantum mechanics in which the state is not the fundamental object. I first situate this project in the context of generalized probabilistic theories and argue that this framework may be understood as a means of drawing conclusions about the intratheoretic causal structure of quantum mechanics which are independent of any specific ontological picture. I then give an operational formulation of the Choi–Jamiołkowski isomorphism and show that, in an operational theory which exhibits this isomorphism, several features of the theory which are usually regarded as properties of the quantum state can be derived from constraints on non-local correlations. This demonstrates that there is no need to postulate states to be the bearers of these properties, since they can be understood as consequences of a fundamental equivalence between multipartite and temporal correlations.
Article
Full-text available
Nonlocality and contextuality are at the root of conceptual puzzles in quantum mechanics, and they are key resources for quantum advantage in information-processing tasks. Bell nonlocality is best understood as the incompatibility between quantum correlations and the classical theory of causality, applied to relativistic causal structure. Contextuality, on the other hand, is on a more controversial foundation. In this work, I provide a common conceptual ground between nonlocality and contextuality as violations of classical causality. First, I show that Bell inequalities can be derived solely from the assumptions of no signaling and no fine-tuning of the causal model. This removes two extra assumptions from a recent result from Wood and Spekkens and, remarkably, does not require any assumption related to independence of measurement settings—unlike all other derivations of Bell inequalities. I then introduce a formalism to represent contextuality scenarios within causal models and show that all classical causal models for violations of a Kochen-Specker inequality require fine-tuning. Thus, the quantum violation of classical causality goes beyond the case of spacelike-separated systems and already manifests in scenarios involving single systems.
Article
Full-text available
Realist interpretations of quantum mechanics presuppose the existence of elements of reality that are independent of the actions used to reveal them. Such a view is challenged by several no-go theorems that show quantum correlations cannot be explained by non-contextual ontological models, where physical properties are assumed to exist prior to and independently of the act of measurement. However, all such contextuality proofs assume a traditional notion of causal structure, where causal influence flows from past to future according to ordinary dynamical laws. This leaves open the question of whether the apparent contextuality of quantum mechanics is simply the signature of some exotic causal structure, where the future might affect the past or distant systems might get correlated due to non-local constraints. Here we show that quantum predictions require a deeper form of contextuality: even allowing for arbitrary causal structure, no model can explain quantum correlations from non-contextual ontological properties of the world, be they initial states, dynamical laws, or global constraints.
Article
I will argue that Kochen-Specker arguments do not provide an algebraic proof for quantum contextuality since, for the argument to be effective, (1) operators must be uniquely associated with measurements and (2) commuting operators must represent simultaneous measurements. However, in all Kochen-Specker arguments discussed in the literature either 1 or 2 is not met. Arguments meeting 1 contain commuting operators that do not represent simultaneous measurements and hence fail to physically justify the functional composition principle. Arguments meeting 2 associate some operators with more than one measurement and hence need to invoke an extra assumption different from noncontextuality.
Article
We develop Markov categories as a framework for synthetic probability and statistics, following work of Golubtsov as well as Cho and Jacobs. This means that we treat the following concepts in purely abstract categorical terms: conditioning and disintegration; various versions of conditional independence and its standard properties; conditional products; almost surely; sufficient statistics; versions of theorems on sufficient statistics due to Fisher–Neyman, Basu, and Bahadur. Besides the conceptual clarity offered by our categorical setup, its main advantage is that it provides a uniform treatment of various types of probability theory, including discrete probability theory, measure-theoretic probability with general measurable spaces, Gaussian probability, stochastic processes of either of these kinds, and many others.
Article
Bell’s theorem rules out many potential reformulations of quantum mechanics, but within a generalized framework it does not exclude all locally mediated models. Such models describe the correlations between entangled particles as mediated by intermediate parameters that track the particle worldlines and respect Lorentz covariance. These locally mediated models require the relaxation of an arrow-of-time assumption that is typically taken for granted. Specifically, some of the mediating parameters in these models must functionally depend on measurement settings in their future, i.e., on input parameters associated with later times. This option, often called retrocausal, has been repeatedly pointed out in the literature, but the exploration of explicit locally mediated toy models capable of describing specific entanglement phenomena has begun only in the past decade. A brief survey of such models is included here. These models provide a continuous and consistent description of events associated with spacetime locations, with aspects that are solved “all at once” rather than unfolding from the past to the future. The tension between quantum mechanics and relativity that is usually associated with Bell’s theorem does not occur here. Unlike in conventional quantum models, the number of parameters needed to specify the state of a system does not grow exponentially with the number of entangled particles. The promise of generalizing such models to account for all quantum phenomena is identified as a grand challenge.
Article
We present novel and simple estimation of a minimal dimension required for an effective reservoir in open quantum systems. Using a tensor network formalism we introduce a new object called a reservoir network (RN). The reservoir network is the tensor network in the form of a Matrix Product State, which contains all effects of open dynamics. This object is especially useful for understanding memory effects. We discuss possible applications of the reservoir network and the estimation of dimension to develop new numerical and machine learning based methods for open quantum systems.
Book
This self-contained essay collection is published to commemorate half a century of Bell’s theorem. Like its much acclaimed predecessor “Quantum [Un]Speakables: From Bell to Quantum Information” (published 2002), it comprises essays by many of the worlds leading quantum physicists and philosophers. These revisit the foundations of quantum theory as well as elucidating the remarkable progress in quantum technologies achieved in the last couple of decades. Fundamental concepts such as entanglement, nonlocality and contextuality are described in an accessible manner and, alongside lively descriptions of the various theoretical and experimental approaches, the book also delivers interesting philosophical insights. The collection as a whole will serve as a broad introduction for students and newcomers as well as delighting the scientifically literate general reader.
Book
This thesis uses high-precision single-photon experiments to shed new light on the role of reality, causality, and uncertainty in quantum mechanics. It provides a comprehensive introduction to the current understanding of quantum foundations and details three influential experiments that significantly advance our understanding of three core aspects of this problem. The first experiment demonstrates that the quantum wavefunction is part of objective reality, if there is any such reality in our world. The second experiment shows that quantum correlations cannot be explained in terms of cause and effect, even when considering superluminal influences between measurement outcomes. The final experiment in this thesis demonstrates a novel uncertainty relation for joint quantum measurements, where the textbook relation does not apply.
Chapter
“Bell’s theorem” can refer to two different theorems that John Bell proved, the first in 1964 and the second in 1976. His 1964 theorem is the incompatibility of quantum phenomena with the joint assumptions of locality and predetermination. His 1976 theorem is their incompatibility with the single property of local causality. This is contrary to Bell’s own later assertions, that his 1964 theorem began with the assumption of local causality, even if not by that name. Although the two Bell’s theorems are logically equivalent, their assumptions are not. Hence, the earlier and later theorems suggest quite different conclusions, embraced by operationalists and realists, respectively. The key issue is whether locality or local causality is the appropriate notion emanating from relativistic causality, and this rests on one’s basic notion of causation. For operationalists the appropriate notion is what is here called the Principle of agent-causation, while for realists it is Reichenbach’s Principle of common cause. By breaking down the latter into even more basic Postulates, it is possible to obtain a version of Bell’s theorem in which each camp could reject one assumption, happy that the remaining assumptions reflect its weltanschauung. Formulating Bell’s theorem in terms of causation is fruitful not just for attempting to reconcile the two camps, but also for better describing the ontology of different quantum interpretations and for more deeply understanding the implications of Bell’s marvellous work.