Content uploaded by Hugh Desmond
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Hugh Desmond on Feb 04, 2021
Content may be subject to copyright.
Service and Status Competition May Help Explain Perceived Ethical Acceptability
Hugh Desmond
Published in American Journal for Bioethics - Neuroscience
The arguably dominant view on the ethics of cognitive enhancement (CE) is that it is primarily
beholden to the principle of autonomy (e.g. Harris 2007; Agar 2005), sometimes supplemented
with justice-related considerations (Buchanan 2011). The hard external constraints on
enhancement – whether ‘sanctity’, or avoiding to ‘play God’, and being open to ‘givenness’ –
seem to have more or less faded from view, both in the academic communities as well as among
the public (Ranisch and Ehni 2020).
Against this backdrop, the results found by Dinh et al. are all the more surprising. They tested
for ethical acceptability while varying contextual factors such as use by peers, endorsement by
authority figures, and the presence of competition. All these contextual factors undermine the
exercise of autonomy, at least in the sense that the enhancee could not claim with full
justification that their choices are entirely “their own”. Also the importance of the enhancee’s
social role (student/athlete vs. employee) seems to be at odds with the principle of autonomy,
where all that matters is the nature of personal choices. Yet, oddly, only the presence of a
competitive environment negatively impacts ethical acceptability.
These empirical results can be relatively straightforwardly explained if one assigns central
ethical significance to the principle of service rather than to that of autonomy. The core insight
underlying the principle of service, at least in this context, is that the good obtained from
enhancement is never a purely “personal good” (cf. Buchanan 2011), but rather impacts the
lives of others. In ethically evaluating the ensemble of impacts, distributive justice is less
important than the degree of “service” (i.e. benefit to the community) obtained by an individual
act of CE.
A theoretical case for the principle of service is laid out in Desmond (forthcoming), but can be
briefly summarized here. Social status is one of the most powerful motivators in human
psychology (Anderson, Hildreth, and Howland 2015), and our concern with it reflects the very
real impact status can have on life histories, including health and morality rate (Marmot 2005).
Now, status is not just a personal good but a positional good, and humans have evolved to be
nervous about others achieving status, since with status comes power and the ability to impose
one’s desires on the collective. Most animal status hierarchies are largely based on dominance;
however, what is unique to humans is how status is also freely given to highly competent
individuals who render some service to the community. Some evolutionary anthropologists
describe “service-for-prestige” norms observable across a wide range of societies (Price and
Van Vugt 2014). In this way, one could say that human status hierarchies have evolved to be
oriented, as much as possible, towards service.
Enhancements, as means to increase capacities, insert themselves right at the heart of these
status dynamics. They can be used for service, but they can also be used for purposes of
dominance. This is a fortiori true of cognitive enhancements, since these increase the capacities
most crucial for status. Given the central role that status plays in our psychology, it could be
expected that the ethical approval of enhancement would depend strongly on whether the act
of enhancement is perceived to obey service-for-prestige norms or not.
The empirical findings of Dinh et al. relating to the importance of contextual factors can be
interpreted through the lens of the principle of service.
Social role. Service does not seem to be of core importance to the activity of sports (at least
compared with medical or legal professions), and in professional sports, athletic success entails
large rewards both financially and in terms of status. Enhancement of the individual is not
likely to benefit the community. By contrast, if CE allows an employee to do a job better, the
benefits will also clearly extend to the client or institution, at least in the short-term. Thus it
can be expected that CE among athletes, compared to CE among employees, would be more
likely to be viewed as promoting a perverse competition (i.e., one that leaves everyone worse
off) and as flouting service-for-prestige norms.
The authors also note that use of CE by students is more likely to meet moral
disapproval. This likely reflects the fact that education is often viewed by both students and
their parents as a way to increase one’s status later in life, for instance by landing a prestigious
job (see e.g. Segrin et al. 2013). However, education is notoriously ambiguous given that the
dissemination of information and understanding is also an important common good. For
instance, the student trying to excel in medical school in order to help discover the proverbial
cure for cancer is likely to face a different moral judgment than one single-mindedly trying to
advance personal wealth. If a future survey, building on Dinh et al.’s work, were to take the
ultimate intended purpose of student CE-use into account, the prediction here is that the ethical
approval of student CE-use would depend significantly on this ultimate intended purpose.
Competition. Dinh et al. rightly note the importance of (perceived) zero-sum competitions,
and the main addition of this commentary would be to draw attention to a specific type of zero-
sum competition: status competition, whether this involves competition for scarce positions of
leadership and power (in corporations, politics), or for positions where one has the ability to
do types of intrinsically satisfying and highly financially rewarded work (e.g., medicine, law,
engineering). Moreover, and this is where the commentary may possibly diverge from the Dinh
et al.: some status competitions are perverse, leaving everyone anxious and self-centered, but
others can be markedly more healthy, leaving the community better off.
Authority and Peers. When an enhancement has been endorsed by a figure of authority or is
used by the majority, it is often perceived as the norm. Enhancement then ceases to be
perceived as a tool for self-advancement, and moreover, it becomes not unreasonable to assume
that the enhancement has been made the norm because it allows a better service to be offered.
This latter assumption is of course sometimes unjustified, but it reflects how humans have
evolved unconscious biases towards imitating the majority or towards imitating high-status
individuals, precisely because this is, often, a good learning strategy (Henrich and Boyd 1998).
The examples of the use of enhancement by surgeons and pilots fit this picture: if the regulating
body mandates the consumption of Adderall, it is not unreasonable to assume that this was
mandated to help the surgeon save a life or help a pilot to safely bring passengers to their
destination. Thus, upon reflection, the factors of peer-influence and influence by authority
figures thus seem to be very similar: they serve to establish the use of enhancements as the
norm.
This analysis generates the following hypothesis: if an authority figure were perceived
to mandate enhancement for his/her own gain, then likely the use of enhancements would not
be seen as ethically acceptable. In other words, it is likely that the participants in the study of
Dinh et al. implicitly read “authority figure” as a “trusted authority figure”. Once the majority
or the authority figure is no longer trusted, then enhancement by peers or authority figures
would likely no longer mitigate ethical disapproval of CE.
Conclusion.
In closing, I would like to suggest what the policy implications would be of following the
principle of service. The variation in moral intuitions need not strengthen a libertarian stance
– a take-home the authors hint at in their remark “it may make sense for people in any given
setting to define the conditions of CE use on their own”. Instead, insofar our moral intuitions
follow service-for-prestige norms, some social regulation of behavior would be appropriate.
This would not (or even: should not) take the form of legislative regulation: when service is
legislated or enforced it can too easily become servitude. Moral education, a softer form of
regulation where values are communicated but with significant respect for individual freedom,
seems more appropriate. Such a moral education would sketch how enhancements affect some
of our deep-seated status-related fears, how they can thus affect the lives of many people
around the enhance, and how it is important that enhancement is undertaken for right, service-
oriented reasons.
References
Agar, Nicholas. 2005. Liberal Eugenics: In Defence of Human Enhancement. Malden, MA:
Blackwell.
Anderson, Cameron, John Angus D. Hildreth, and Laura Howland. 2015. “Is the Desire for
Status a Fundamental Human Motive? A Review of the Empirical Literature.”
Psychological Bulletin 141 (3): 574–601. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0038781.
Buchanan, Allen. 2011. Better than Human: The Promise and Perils of Enhancing Ourselves.
Philosophy in Action: Small Books about Big Ideas. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Desmond. H. (forthcoming) The Service View on Enhancement: A New Evolutionary
Perspective. The Hastings Center Report.
Harris, John. 2007. Enhancing Evolution: The Ethical Case for Making Better People.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Henrich, Joseph, and Robert Boyd. 1998. “The Evolution of Conformist Transmission and
the Emergence of Between-Group Differences.” Evolution and Human Behavior 19
(4): 215–41. https://doi.org/10.1016/S1090-5138(98)00018-X.
Marmot, Michael. 2005. Status Syndrome: How Your Social Standing Directly Affects Your
Health. London: A&C Black.
Price, Michael E., and Mark Van Vugt. 2014. “The Evolution of Leader–Follower
Reciprocity: The Theory of Service-for-Prestige.” Frontiers in Human Neuroscience
8. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2014.00363.
Ranisch, Robert, and Hans‐Jörg Ehni. 2020. “Fading Red Lines? Bioethics of Germline
Genome Editing.” Bioethics 34 (1): 3–6. https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.12709.
Segrin, Chris, Alesia Woszidlo, Michelle Givertz, and Neil Montgomery. 2013. “Parent and
Child Traits Associated with Overparenting.” Journal of Social and Clinical
Psychology 32 (6): 569–95. https://doi.org/10.1521/jscp.2013.32.6.569.