Access to this full-text is provided by Wiley.
Content available from Wiley interdisciplinary reviews: Climate Change
This content is subject to copyright. Terms and conditions apply.
OPINION
Is solar geoengineering ungovernable? A critical assessment
of governance challenges identified by the
Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change
Jesse L. Reynolds
1,2
1
School of Law, University of California
Los Angeles, Los Angeles, California
2
Utrecht Centre for Water, Oceans and
Sustainability Law, Utrecht University,
Utrecht, The Netherlands
Correspondence
Jesse L. Reynolds, School of Law,
University of California Los Angeles, Los
Angeles, CA.
Email: reynolds@law.ucla.edu
Funding information
Open Philanthropy Project
Edited by Mike Hulme,
Editor-in-Chief
Abstract
Solar radiation modification (SRM) could greatly reduce climate change and
associated risks. Yet it has not been well-received by the climate change expert
community. This is evident in the authoritative reports of the Intergovernmental
Panel on Climate Change (IPCC), which emphasize SRM's governance, political,
social, and ethical challenges. I find seven such challenges identified in the IPCC
reports: that SRM could lessen mitigation; that its termination would cause
severe climatic impacts; that researching SRM would create a “slippery slope”to
its inevitable and unwanted use; that decisions to use it could be contrary to
democratic norms; that the public may not accept SRM; that it could be
unethical; and that decisions to use SRM could be unilateral. After assessing the
extent to which these challenges are supported by existing evidence, scholarly
literature, and robust logic, I conclude that, for six of the seven, the IPCC's
claims variously are speculative, fail to consider both advantages and disadvan-
tages, implicitly make unreasonable negative assumptions, are contrary to exis-
ting evidence, and/or are meaninglessly vague. I suggest some reasons for the
reports' failure to meet the IPCC's standards of balance, thoroughness, and accu-
racy, and recommend a dedicated Special Report on SRM.
This article is categorized under:
Integrated Assessment of Climate Change > Assessing Climate Change in
the Context of Other Issues
KEYWORDS
geoengineering, Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change, IPCC, solar radiation
modification, SRM
1|INTRODUCTION
Greenhouse gas emissions reductions and carbon dioxide removal (together, “mitigation”) continue to be insufficient to pre-
vent dangerous anthropogenic climate change. Additionally, adapting to a changed climate has limited and uncertain
Received: 21 April 2020 Revised: 25 September 2020 Accepted: 3 October 2020
DOI: 10.1002/wcc.690
This is an open access article under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits use, distribution and reproduction in any medium, provided
the original work is properly cited.
© 2020 The Author. WIREs Climate Change published by Wiley Periodicals LLC.
WIREs Clim Change. 2021;12:e690. wires.wiley.com/climatechange 1of8
https://doi.org/10.1002/wcc.690
PERSPECTIVE
potential and is expensive. In response, some scientists and others are researching solar radiation modification (SRM, some-
times called solar radiation management or solar geoengineering) as an additional means to limit climate change and its
risks.
SRM is a set of proposed technologies to intentionally modify the Earth's shortwave radiative budget with the aim
of reducing climate change (IPCC, 2018, p. 558). It would block or reflect a small portion of incoming sunlight and con-
sequently cool the planet. The leading suggested method would replicate volcanoes' cooling effect by injecting an aero-
sol into the stratosphere. According to evidence to date—mostly from modeling—SRM has substantial potential to
reduce climate change (Irvine & Keith, 2020; National Research Council, 2015). Moreover, it could do so in ways that
other responses could not: it appears to be relatively inexpensive (Smith, 2020), rapid, and possible without broad inter-
national cooperation. At the same time, SRM poses a number of physical and environmental risks, especially in scenar-
ios of its suboptimal use. For example, because SRM would compensate for precipitation changes more efficiently (per
unit of radiative forcing or aerosol mass) and less consistently than it would for the temperature ones, using SRM to
return the global mean temperature to its preindustrial level would result in some wet and especially some dry areas
(Tilmes et al., 2013).
Despite its apparent potential to reduce climate change and the associated risks, SRM has not been well-received by
the community of climate change experts. Skepticism and aversion are evident in the authoritative reports of the Inter-
governmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC). Its highest-profile statement to date on SRM, in the Summary for
Policymakers of the Synthesis Report of the Fifth Assessment Report (AR5), is:
Solar Radiation Management (SRM) involves large-scale methods that seek to reduce the amount of
absorbed solar energy in the climate system. SRM is untested and is not included in any of the mitigation
scenarios. If it were deployed, SRM would entail numerous uncertainties, side effects, risks and shortcom-
ings and has particular governance and ethical implications. SRM would not reduce ocean acidification. If
it were terminated, there is high confidence that surface temperatures would rise very rapidly impacting
ecosystems susceptible to rapid rates of change. (italics in original here and elsewhere; IPCC, 2014c, pp.
25–26)
Similarly, the Summary for Policymakers of the more recent Special Report Global Warming of 1.5C(SR1.5) is,
again in full:
Solar radiation modification (SRM) measures are not included in any of the available assessed pathways.
Although some SRM measures may be theoretically effective in reducing an overshoot, they face large
uncertainties and knowledge gaps as well as substantial risks and institutional and social constraints to
deployment related to governance, ethics, and impacts on sustainable development. They also do not miti-
gate ocean acidification (IPCC, 2018, pp. 14–15).
In these two paragraphs, only 12 of 146 words speak of SRM's efficacy, and even this clause is qualified with
“although”and “theoretically.”Most of the remaining words address SRM's risks and limitations. Furthermore, these
reports give no reason for excluding SRM from their scenarios. This is particularly noteworthy in the case of SR1.5,
which, in a box toward its end, concludes “with high agreement that [stratospheric aerosol injection] could limit
warming to below 1.5C”(IPCC, 2018, p. 558), a goal that is out of reach through emissions reduction alone
(IPCC, 2018, p. 17).
SRM poses multiple physical risks as well as regulatory, political, social, and ethical challenges (here, “governance
challenges”). Physical risks and governance challenges differ in how they can be assessed. At least in principle, the
former—such as the potential residual precipitation anomalies described above—could be weighed against SRM's
reduction of climate change; decision-makers and the public may or may not subsequently deem SRM acceptable. In
contrast, its governance challenges are less amenable to instrumental assessment and now persist as the stronger set of
objections to SRM. For example, the executive summary of SR1.5's relevant chapter concludes, “Even in the uncertain
case that the most adverse side-effects of SRM can be avoided, public resistance, ethical concerns and potential impacts
on sustainable development could render SRM economically, socially and institutionally undesirable”(IPCC, 2018,
p. 317). In other words, the IPCC asserts that SRM's governance challenges could be insurmountable, independent of
its net effect on physical risks. Along these lines, SRM has been called “ungovernable”(Hulme, 2014). Because these
2of8 REYNOLDS
governance challenges constitute the leading set of objections in the IPCC reports and in the wider climate change com-
munity, they warrant explication and interrogation.
In order to assess the IPCC's claims, I reviewed the five IPCC Assessment Reports as well as the more recent SR1.5
and found SRM's governance challenges that they identify. I then examined the extent to which these are supported by
existing evidence, scholarly literature, and robust logic. Attention to SRM's governance challenges is largely confined to
AR5 and SR1.5; prior Assessment Reports focus almost entirely on SRM's environmental effects. Below, I describe and
assess the governance challenges as represented in these IPCC reports, grouping them into seven coherent categories:
that SRM could lessen mitigation; that its termination would cause severe climatic impacts; that researching SRM
would create a “slippery slope”to its inevitable and unwanted use; that decisions to use it could be contrary to demo-
cratic norms; that the public may not accept SRM; that it could be unethical; and that decisions to use SRM could be
unilateral. For six of these seven governance challenges, I conclude that the IPCC's claims are variously speculative, fail
to consider both advantages and disadvantages, implicitly make unreasonable negative assumptions, are contrary to
existing evidence (several times misrepresenting cited academic publications), and/or are meaninglessly vague. Thereaf-
ter, the paper briefly concludes with possible explanations and a recommendation.
2|LESSENED MITIGATION
Perhaps the most widespread and influential concern regarding SRM is that it could lessen mitigation. AR5 expresses
this passively: “it has been argued that geoengineering could become a distraction from urgent mitigation and adapta-
tion measures”(IPCC, 2014b, p. 484, see also pp. 219, 488). According to SR1.5, “the literature shows low agreement on
whether SRM research and use may lead policy-makers to reduce mitigation efforts”(IPCC, 2018, p. 349).
There is no evidence that SRM's research and development would lessen mitigation but instead only assertions of
that effect. In this sense, AR5 is correct: it has been argued. In contrast, SR1.5 speaks of the literature showing low
agreement, yet the one scientific article that is cited after the above quote (Linnér & Wibeck, 2015) does not discuss
SRM's potential effect on mitigation.
In fact, what evidence there is suggests the opposite. In almost all opinion surveys and behavioral experiments that have
explored this possibility, after learning about SRM or having it added to their choices, respondents increase their concern
about climate change and/or support for mitigation (for references, see Reynolds, 2019, pp. 37–40).ThissuggeststhatSRM
may be seen by many as so undesirable that it leads them to realize climate change's seriousness and mitigation's impor-
tance, a prospect that SR1.5 does cautiously note. Of course, these surveys and experiments are not dispositive about what
will actually occur. The actions of future decision-makers—who will face political pressures—will not necessarily align
with current laypersons' preferences and choices. At the same time, decision-makers are influenced by popular sentiment.
Elected politicians rely on voters; appointed officials are accountable to elected ones; and businesses depend on customers.
Even authoritarian leaders are partially constrained by public opinion. Thus, if SRM's research and development were to
increase support for mitigation among the general population, as suggested by the surveys and experiments to date, then
similar shifts should be expected among decision-makers, albeit imperfectly so. In the end, the IPCC's statements that SRM
would be a distraction from or reduce mitigation are speculations that are contrary to the existing empirical evidence.
Even if the introduction of SRM into a mix of responses to climate change were to lessen mitigation undertaken,
doing so could still be a net benefit. If SRM could counteract climate change, then its use coupled with a modest lessen-
ing of mitigation could, on the whole, reduce net climate risks. Such “risk compensation,”in which the introduction of
a safety rule or technology causes an increase in the underlying risky activity, is common in public policy
(Hedlund, 2000). Tellingly, the net result of the safety measure and the subsequent compensatory behavioral change is
usually a net reduction of harm, and the risk-reducing rules and technologies are typically praised. Yet the IPCC reports
do not consider such a risk compensation scenario and instead take into account only the negative consequences of
SRM potentially lessening mitigation but not its expected concomitant benefits of reducing climate change. This would
be analogous to considering only that seat belts cause car drivers to drive faster while neglecting the belts' safety effects.
3|TERMINATION
The IPCC reports frequently note that if SRM were used and then stopped, then the previously suppressed climate change
would manifest rapidly and dangerously (IPCC, 2013a, pp. 29, 98, 575, 635; 2014a, pp. 454, 1043; 2014b, pp. 488,
REYNOLDS 3of8
1023; 2014c, pp. 26, 89; 2018, p. 351). Indeed, one of the four sentences in the IPCC's highest-profile statement on SRM—
the AR5 Synthesis Report's Summary for Policymakers, quoted above—was dedicated to termination's consequences
(IPCC, 2014c, p. 26). This is the only governance challenge to which IPCC reports prior to AR5 referred
(IPCC, 1996, p. 813).
Although it is true that sudden and sustained termination of relatively high-magnitude (i.e., greatly negative radia-
tive forcing) SRM would be harmful, this would require meeting multiple conditions, some of which seem improbable.
AR5 does accurately state that “this ‘termination effect’might be avoided if SRM were used at a modest magnitude and
for a relatively short period of time”(IPCC, 2013a, p. 631). Even if SRM were used neither at a modest magnitude nor
for a short time, reasonable governance measures could prevent a harmful termination (Parker & Irvine, 2018;
Rabitz, 2019; Reynolds, Parker, & Irvine, 2016). If the implementing state(s) (or other actors) wished to end it, SRM
could be gradually phased out. Furthermore, they could create redundant and secure infrastructure to increase the sys-
tem's ability to withstand shocks. If these state(s) did abruptly terminate high-magnitude SRM, for whatever reason,
then any other capable state(s) could resume it sufficiently quickly to prevent harmful warming. Such capable states
could be numerous, because SRM appears inexpensive and technically modest. Importantly, all of these steps—gradual
phase-out, redundant and secure systems, and other states' resumption of SRM—would be in the states' interests to
undertake. Ultimately, the IPCC reports implicitly assume that reasonable actions would not be taken to prevent the
sudden and sustained termination of high-magnitude SRM.
4|“SLIPPERY SLOPE”
Another governance challenge of SRM is that early research activities could unduly increase the probability of its future
use. As stated in AR5, “research might make deployment inevitable”(IPCC, 2014b, p. 219). SR1.5 is vaguer, passively
saying that “The argument that SRM research increases the likelihood of deployment (the ‘slippery slope’argument), is
also made”(IPCC, 2018, p. 349).
AR5's claim of inevitability is illogical and contrary to evidence. Research of new technologies is usually unsuccess-
ful, but the failures are not widely known due to survivorship bias. (Although success and failure are both difficult to
measure, medical development has benchmarks. There, only about 10% of clinical trials lead to an approved drug or
biologic [Thomas et al., 2016].) Other successfully developed technologies, such as supersonic commercial passenger
transport, have been developed and later rejected through social and political means.
What's more, the two scholarly sources that AR5 cites do not support the above-quoted claim that “research might
make deployment inevitable.”Each asserts that research programs make development and use more probable
(Bunzl, 2009, p. 2; Jamieson, 1996, p. 333). Only one (Jamieson) says that this could be a problem, and even that calls
for geoengineering research with safeguards.
The claim of SR1.5 that research increases the chance of the use of SRM is obviously true but trivial, because the lat-
ter requires the former. And as in AR5, the one article that SR1.5 cites does not make a slippery slope argument.
Instead, it reports an increase in implementation's likelihood due to the abstract economic model's initial assumptions
(Quaas, Quaas, Rickels, & Boucher, 2017). SR1.5's claim is unsupported.
5|CONTRARY TO DEMOCRATIC NORMS
The IPCC's SR1.5 report states that decision-making regarding SRM may be contrary to widely-held democratic norms.
It does so in two ways. First, SR1.5 points to a debate over whether SRM is compatible with democracy (IPCC, 2018,
p. 348). The assertion that SRM is incompatible with democratic processes (Szerszynski, Kearnes, Macnaghten, Owen, &
Stilgoe, 2013) has come under serious criticism (Horton et al., 2018, which SR1.5 does cite).
Second, SR1.5 claims “Unequal representation and deliberate exclusion are plausible in decision-making on SRM”
(IPCC, 2018, p. 349). Yet once again, the scholarly article that the report cites here (Ricke, Moreno-Cruz, &
Caldeira, 2013) says nothing about the plausibility of unequal representation and deliberate exclusion but instead
assumed them and then models the expected SRM magnitude and climatic effects. Such a conflation of assumptions
and conclusions is seen in SR1.5's treatment of a possible “slippery slope,”described above. Thus, this claim regarding
unequal representation and deliberate exclusion is unsupported.
4of8 REYNOLDS
6|PUBLIC ACCEPTANCE
The IPCC reports claim that the public might not accept SRM. AR5 concludes, “Whether SRM field research or even
deployment would be socially and politically acceptable is also dependent on the wider discursive context in which the
topic is being discussed”(IPCC, 2014b, pp. 488–489). Similarly, “public resistance”is among the governance challenges
that the executive summary of SR1.5's chapter highlights, quoted above.
Public opinion concerning acceptance of and possible resistance to SRM will be central to its governance. However,
at the moment, the extent to which SRM would or would not be widely accepted remains unclear. Most people are
unaware of it. SR1.5 appropriately notes that public opinion remains inchoate and highly sensitive to the information
provided and question wording (IPCC, 2018, p. 349; see also Burns et al., 2016; Carlisle, Feetham, Wright, &
Teagle, 2020). Furthermore, attitudes among the public would likely change if severe climate change impacts were to
manifest or influential political actors began to advocate on the issue. Ultimately, it is speculative to claim that “public
resistance…could render SRM…undesirable”(IPCC, 2018, p. 317).
7|ETHICS
The IPCC reports point toward diverse potential ethical objections to SRM. Because all substantial decisions have ethi-
cal implications, some of these potential objections overlap with those governance challenges described above. Specifi-
cally, AR5 offers the potential exacerbation of inequalities and “a critical assessment of technology and modern
civilization in general”(IPCC, 2014b, p. 219; 2014c, p. 89). Additional ethical objections that SR1.5 lists include “financ-
ing, compensation for negative effects, the procedural justice questions of who is involved in decisions, privatization
and patenting, welfare, informed consent by affected publics, intergenerational ethics”(IPCC, 2018, p. 349).
These objections are of varying robustness, including some that are unsupported or unhelpful. For example, model-
ing evidence suggests that a judicious use of SRM would reduce inter-country inequalities (Harding, Ricke, Heyen, Mac-
Martin, & Moreno-Cruz, 2020). Other ethical objections, such as “a critical assessment of technology and modern
civilization in general,”are so broad as to be vacuous. Regardless, most of these objections would strongly depend on
how SRM would be developed and used (as well as the resolution of scientific uncertainties and the observer's particu-
lar normative framework). As in other policy domains, well-crafted governance could address ethical issues such as
responsibility for implementation, financing, compensation for harm, private actors' roles, welfare impacts, and public
participation in decision-making. As with public acceptance, SRM's ethical implications remain speculative and, as with
termination and “slippery slopes,”implicitly assume that reasonable policies would not be adopted.
Furthermore, the IPCC reports should—but do not—consider also ethical arguments that support SRM's research,
development, and possible use. Climate change poses severe risks to ecosystems and humans, especially to the already
vulnerable. If SRM could reduce these risks, as current evidence indicates, then an ethical duty to at least explore its
potential seems reasonable (Callies, 2019; Horton & Keith, 2016; Morrow, 2019; Svoboda, Irvine, Callies, &
Sugiyama, 2019). Even the first publication on geoengineering ethics considers the case for research and the conditions
under which implementation could be acceptable (Jamieson, 1996).
8|UNILATERAL DEPLOYMENT
The IPCC reports regularly raise the challenge that one or a few actors—probably states, but perhaps “even non-state
actors, such as wealthy individuals”(IPCC, 2014b, p. 1023)—could implement SRM contrary to international consensus
(IPCC, 2014a, p. 1066; 2014b, pp. 488, 1007, 1023; 2014c, p. 89). SR1.5 says, “There is robust evidence but medium agree-
ment for unilateral action potentially becoming a serious SRM governance issue”(IPCC, 2018, p. 347).
Unlike the other six identified governance challenges, this one is mostly accurate as worded (arguably with the
exception of the claim of possible nonstate SRM deployment). Even in the absence of it actually occurring, international
negotiations concerning how to prevent unilateral implementation could be a serious issue. At the same time, some
scholars argue that problematic unilateral SRM is unlikely (Halstead, 2018; Horton, 2011; Keohane, 2015, p. 23;
Parson, 2014, pp. 98–103; Rabitz, 2016).
REYNOLDS 5of8
9|CONCLUSION
Current evidence suggests that SRM could substantially reduce climate change and its risks, yet its reception in the cli-
mate change expert community is incommensurate with this potential. This is evident in the IPCC's authoritative and
influential reports, which emphasize SRM's various governance challenges while downplaying its potential efficacy.
However, I conclude here that six of the seven identified challenges are misrepresented in the reports in various ways.
One might counter that the reports use modal verbs of uncertainty, such as “could”and “might,”and are thus not
incorrect. Of course, a nearly infinite number of such not-incorrect sentences of potentiality are possible on any topic
while not being helpful. (Notably, the aggressive mitigation that would be needed to prevent dangerous climate change
“could”be done in ways contrary to democratic norms, that the public would not accept, and that would be unethical.
Yet IPCC does not foreground these possibilities.) Instead, the reports are to “provide a balanced and complete assess-
ment of current information”described in “calibrated uncertainty language that expresses the diversity of the scientifi-
cally and technically valid evidence, based mainly on the strength of the evidence and the level of agreement in the
scientific, technical, and socio-economic literature”(IPCC, 2013b). I assert that AR5 and SR1.5 have not met this stan-
dard with regard to SRM's governance challenges.
I consider three possible reasons for the reports' failure to meet the IPCC's standards of balance, thoroughness, and
accuracy. First, the IPCC reports' content is, for the most part, limited to summarizing and assessing peer-reviewed pub-
lications. SRM scholarship seems to have evolved. In my perception, early publications emphasized SRM's limitations,
risks, and challenges, while more recent ones offer relatively more nuanced considerations. AR5, in particular, was
unable to cite some of the latter cohort.
Second, the reports' chapters that discuss SRM contain few, if any, SRM researchers. Climate researchers who do
not investigate SRM may be skeptical of or even hostile to it (and even those who do study it are unenthusiastic;
Anshelm & Hansson, 2014; see Dannenberg & Zitzelsberger, 2019). To some degree, this is understandable. Those con-
cerned about humans' environmental impacts generally aim for less intervention in nature, not more. Further, climate
scientists have been calling for mitigation, often in a hostile political environment, for about 30 years; other responses
to climate change may be perceived as dangerous distractions. These IPCC authors may, consciously or not, prefer that
SRM remains as low as possible on the climate change agenda in order to keep mitigation at the top.
Third, the IPCC reports have, over the decades, increasingly considered social, political, governance, and ethical
issues. Its method of assessment identifies existing and emerging consensuses while remaining “policy-relevant and yet
policy-neutral, never policy-prescriptive.”This may be poorly suited for the social sciences and humanities, which rely
to a greater degree on qualitative evidence, inductive reasoning, subjective values, and argumentation (Minx, Calla-
ghan, Lamb, Garard, & Edenhofer, 2017). If so, then the IPCC should perhaps undertake these assessments with cau-
tion and within explicit boundaries.
More and more, SRM appears able to prevent dangerous climate change and necessary to do so. It must be indepen-
dently, authoritatively, and internationally assessed in order to help guide its responsible research, development, and—
if warranted—use. The IPCC is the logical site for this assessment. Although evaluations could, in principle, be accom-
plished through greater and more rigorous attention in future Assessment Reports, a dedicated chapter may not be able
to do so given SRM's cross-cutting nature. And even then, this would not be possible until the Seventh Assessment
Report in the late 2020s. Instead, a Special Report on SRM after the Sixth Assessment Report is warranted. While its
contributors should include some SRM-novices and skeptics, most of its authors must be both deeply familiar with the
field and willing to rationally assess SRM's advantages and disadvantages, capabilities and limitations, and opportuni-
ties and risks. Launching a Special Report would clarify—in my opinion beneficially so—that the IPCC is the principal
international site for assessing responses to climate change. (In 2019, the UN Environmental Assembly considered a
resolution on geoengineering and its governance. Among the reasons that this resolution did not pass was divergence
of views concerning institutional responsibility for scientific assessment) It is possible that a Special Report on SRM
could be, in part, performative. Similar to how SR1.5 (and the preceding Paris Agreement) helped reify 1.5C warming
as a scientifically important, politically acceptable, and rhetorically powerful threshold (Asayama, Bellamy, Geden, Pea-
rce, & Hulme, 2019), a Special Report might legitimatize SRM into an object worthy of study as a potential complemen-
tary response to climate change. If so, such an effect—if it occurred—would not necessarily be undesirable.
CONFLICT OF INTEREST
The author has declared no conflicts of interest for this article.
6of8 REYNOLDS
ORCID
Jesse L. Reynolds https://orcid.org/0000-0002-0624-5741
RELATED WIREs ARTICLES
Perceptions of geoengineering: public attitudes, stakeholder perspectives, and the challenge of ‘upstream’engagement
‘In case of emergency press here’: framing geoengineering as a response to dangerous climate change
Climate geoengineering: issues of path-dependence and socio-technical lock-in
Intellectual property policies for solar geoengineering
REFERENCES
Anshelm, J., & Hansson, A. (2014). Battling promethean dreams and Trojan horses: Revealing the critical discourses of geoengineering.
Energy Research & Social Science,2, 135–144. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.erss.2014.04.001
Asayama, S., Bellamy, R., Geden, O., Pearce, W., & Hulme, M. (2019). Why setting a climate deadline is dangerous. Nature Climate Change,
9(8), 570–572. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41558-019-0543-4
Bunzl, M. (2009). Researching geoengineering: should not or could not?. Environmental Research Letters,4(4), 045104. http://dx.doi.org/10.
1088/1748-9326/4/4/045104.
Burns, E. T., Flegal, J. A., Keith, D. W., Mahajan, A., Tingley, D., & Wagner, G. (2016). What do people think when they think about solar
geoengineering? A review of empirical social science literature, and prospects for future research. Earth's Future,4(11), 536–542. https://
doi.org/10.1002/2016EF000461
Callies, D. E. (2019). Climate engineering: A normative perspective, Lanham, Maryland: Lexington Books.
Carlisle, D. P., Feetham, P. M., Wright, M. J., & Teagle, D. A. H. (2020). The public remain uninformed and wary of climate engineering. Cli-
matic Change,160, 303–322. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10584-020-02706-5
Dannenberg, A., & Zitzelsberger, S. (2019). Climate experts' views on geoengineering depend on their beliefs about climate change impacts.
Nature Climate Change.,9, 769–775. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41558-019-0564-z
Halstead, J. (2018). Stratospheric aerosol injection research and existential risk. Futures,102,63–77. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.futures.2018.
03.004
Harding, A. R., Ricke, K., Heyen, D., MacMartin, D. G., & Moreno-Cruz, J. (2020). Climate econometric models indicate solar geoengineering
would reduce inter-country income inequality. Nature Communications,11(1), 1–9. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41467-019-13957-x
Hedlund, J. (2000). Risky business: Safety regulations, risk compensation, and individual behavior. Injury Prevention,6(2), 82–89. http://dx.
doi.org/10.1136/ip.6.2.82.
Horton, J., & Keith, D. (2016). Solar geoengineering and obligations to the global poor. In C. J. Preston (Ed.), Climate justice and geo-
engineering: Ethics and policy in the atmospheric Anthropocene (pp. 79–92). Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield.
Horton, J. B. (2011). Geoengineering and the myth of unilateralism: Pressures and prospects for international cooperation. Stanford Journal
of Law, Science, and Policy,4(1), 56–69.
Horton, J. B., Reynolds, J. L., Buck, H. J., Callies, D., Schäfer, S., Keith, D. W., & Rayner, S. (2018). Solar geoengineering and democracy.
Global Environmental Politics,18(3), 5–24. https://doi.org/10.1162/glep_a_00466
Hulme, M. (2014). Can science fix climate change? A case against climate engineering, Cambridge, UK: Polity.
IPCC. (1996). Climate change 1995: Impacts, adaptations and mitigation of climate change: Scientific-technical analyses. Contribution of Work-
ing Group II to the second assessment report of the intergovernmental panel on climate change, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
Press.
IPCC. (2013a). Climate change 2013: The physical science basis. Contribution of Working Group I to the fifth assessment report of the intergov-
ernmental panel on climate change, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
IPCC. (2013b). Procedures for the preparation, review, acceptance, adoption, approval and publication of IPCC reports. Retrieved from https://
www.ipcc.ch/site/assets/uploads/2018/09/ipcc-principles-appendix-a-final.pdf
IPCC. (2014a). Climate change 2014: Impacts, adaptation, and vulnerability. Contribution of Working Group II to the fifth assessment report of
the intergovernmental panel on climate change, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
IPCC. (2014b). Climate change 2014: Mitigation of climate change. Contribution of Working Group III to the fifth assessment report of the inter-
governmental panel on climate change, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
IPCC. (2014c). Climate change 2014: Synthesis report. Contribution of Working Groups I, II and III to the fifth assessment report of the intergov-
ernmental panel on climate change. Geneva: IPCC.
IPCC. (2018). Global warming of 1.5C. Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. Geneva: World Meteorological Organization.
Irvine, P. J., & Keith, D. W. (2020). Halving warming with stratospheric aerosol geoengineering moderates policy-relevant climate hazards.
Environmental Research Letters,15(4), 044011. https://doi.org/10.1088/1748-9326/ab76de
Jamieson, D. (1996). Ethics and intentional climate change. Climatic Change,33(3), 323–336. https://doi.org/10.1007/bf00142580
Jinnah, S., & Nicholson, S. (2019). The hidden politics of climate engineering. Nature Geoscience,12(11), 876–879. https://doi.org/10.1038/
s41561-019-0483-7
Keohane, R. O. (2015). The global politics of climate change: Challenge for political science. PS: Political Science & Politics,48(1), 19–26.
https://doi.org/10.1017/S1049096514001541
REYNOLDS 7of8
Linnér, B.-O., & Wibeck, V. (2015). Dual high-stake emerging technologies: A review of the climate engineering research literature. Wiley
Interdisciplinary Reviews: Climate Change,6(2), 255–268. https://doi.org/10.1002/wcc.333
Minx, J. C., Callaghan, M., Lamb, W. F., Garard, J., & Edenhofer, O. (2017). Learning about climate change solutions in the IPCC and
beyond. Environmental Science & Policy,77, 252–259. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.envsci.2017.05.014
Morrow, D. R. (2019). A mission-driven research program on solar geoengineering could promote justice and legitimacy. Critical Review of
International Social and Political Philosophy,23(5), 618–640. https://doi.org/10.1080/13698230.2020.1694220
National Research Council. (2015). Climate intervention: Reflecting sunlight to cool earth, Washington, DC: National Academies Press.
https://doi.org/10.17226/18988.
Parker, A., & Irvine, P. J. (2018). The risk of termination shock from solar geoengineering. Earth's Future,6(3), 456–467. https://doi.org/10.
1002/2017EF000735
Parson, E. A. (2014). Climate engineering in global climate governance: Implications for participation and linkage. Transnational Environ-
mental Law,3(1), 89–110. https://doi.org/10.1017/S2047102513000496
Quaas, M. F., Quaas, J., Rickels, W., & Boucher, O. (2017). Are there reasons against open-ended research into solar radiation management?
A model of intergenerational decision-making under uncertainty. Journal of Environmental Economics and Management,84,1–17.
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jeem.2017.02.002
Rabitz, F. (2016). Going rogue? Scenarios for unilateral geoengineering. Futures,84,98–107. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.futures.2016.11.001
Rabitz, F. (2019). Governing the termination problem in solar radiation management. Environmental Politics,28(3), 502–522. https://doi.org/
10.1080/09644016.2018.1519879
Reynolds, J. L. (2019). The governance of solar geoengineering: Managing climate change in the anthropocene, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316676790
Reynolds, J. L., Parker, A., & Irvine, P. (2016). Five solar geoengineering tropes that have outstayed their welcome. Earth's Future,4(12),
562–568. https://doi.org/10.1002/2016EF000416
Ricke, K. L., Moreno-Cruz, J. B., & Caldeira, K. (2013). Strategic incentives for climate geoengineering coalitions to exclude broad participa-
tion. Environmental Research Letters,8(1), 014021. https://doi.org/10.1088/1748-9326/8/1/014021
Smith, W. (2020). The cost of stratospheric aerosol injection through 2100. Environmental Research Letters.,15(11), 114004. https://doi.org/
10.1088/1748-9326/aba7e7
Svoboda, T., Irvine, P. J., Callies, D., & Sugiyama, M. (2019). The potential for climate engineering with stratospheric sulfate aerosol injec-
tions to reduce climate injustice. Journal of Global Ethics,14(3), 353–368. https://doi.org/10.1080/17449626.2018.1552180
Szerszynski, B., Kearnes, M., Macnaghten, P., Owen, R., & Stilgoe, J. (2013). Why solar radiation management geoengineering and democ-
racy won't mix. Environment and Planning A: Economy and Space,45, 2809–2816. https://doi.org/10.1068/a45649
Thomas, D. W., Burns, J., Audette, J., Carroll, A., Dow-Hygelund, C., & Hay, M. (2016). Clinical development success rates 2006–2015. Bio-
technology Innovation Organization (BIO). Retrieved from http://bit.ly/22o5TGf
Tilmes, S., Fasullo, J., Lamarque, J.-F., Marsh, D. R., Mills, M., Alterskjær, K., …Yoon, J.-H. (2013). The hydrological impact of geo-
engineering in the geoengineering model Intercomparison project (GeoMIP). Journal of Geophysical Research,118(19), 11036–11058.
https://doi.org/10.1002/jgrd.50868.
How to cite this article: Reynolds JL. Is solar geoengineering ungovernable? A critical assessment of
governance challenges identified by the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. WIREs Clim Change. 2021;
12:e690. https://doi.org/10.1002/wcc.690
8of8 REYNOLDS
Available via license: CC BY 4.0
Content may be subject to copyright.