Content uploaded by Marco Del Giudice
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Marco Del Giudice on Nov 29, 2020
Content may be subject to copyright.
1
Ideological Bias in the Psychology of Sex and Gender
Marco Del Giudice
University of New Mexico
In press (2021):
Chapter in C. L. Frisby, W. T. O’Donohue, R. E. Redding, & S. O. Lilienfeld (Eds.)
Political bias in psychology: Nature, scope, and solutions. Springer.
[Preprint date: November 29, 2020]
Marco Del Giudice, Department of Psychology, University of New Mexico. Logan Hall, 2001
Redondo Dr. NE, Albuquerque, NM 87131, USA; email: marcodg@unm.edu
2
In this chapter I discuss the influence of ideological bias in the psychological study of sex
and gender. This kaleidoscopic issue would demand an entire book; attempting to be systematic
and exhaustive would be an impossible task. Instead, I take a somewhat informal approach as I
try to highlight key points of tension, clarify some conceptual muddles, offer interesting
examples, and put everything in historical perspective. The last bit is especially important,
because the received history of this topic is also ideologically slanted and full of distortions, half-
truths, and sometimes sheer fabrications. To delimit the field and remain close to the topic of this
volume, I focus mainly on academic psychology, leaving aside the applied psychological
disciplines (e.g., psychotherapy) and the neurosciences.
The Problem in a Nutshell
As pointed out by Winegard and Winegard (2018), bias in the social sciences is more
often ideological than narrowly political (in the sense of left- vs. right-wing partisanship); the
reason why sex and gender are hot topics is that they play a central role in egalitarian ideologies,
of which feminism is a prime example. Most present-day feminists embrace what Winegard and
Winegard labeled cosmic egalitarianism, or the belief that all ethnic and cultural groups, social
classes, and sexes are relatively equal on all socially desired traits; note that “equal” should be
read as biologically equal, because measurable differences may also arise because of differential
socialization, prejudice, and discrimination.
1
Thus, egalitarianism and desire for social change
toward equality go hand in hand with a social constructionist, “blank slate” perspective on
human nature (see e.g., Anomaly & Winegard, 2019; Eagly, 2018; Pinker, 2003; Murray, 2020;
Winegard & Winegard, 2018). In short:
Feminist theorists view gender not as a biologically created reality, but as a
socially constructed phenomenon (Else-Quest & Hyde, 2018, p. 13).
Many feminists are wary of biological explanations of anything, in large part
because biology always seems to end up being a convenient justification for
perpetuating the status quo (ibid., p. 45).
Because feminism is the dominant ideological influence in the study of sex and gender,
this chapter takes a critical stance toward feminist theory and research. However, my goal is not
to write an anti-feminist pamphlet. There is no doubt that feminist scholars have made valuable
contributions to psychology and brought attention to important themes; evolutionary
psychologists like myself have long recognized this (e.g., Buss & Schmitt, 2011; Campbell,
2006; Nicolas & Welling, 2015). In a recent exchange we had with some prominent feminist
scientists, my colleagues and I found several points of agreement despite our different
perspectives (Del Giudice et al., 2018a; Fine et al., 2018). While some feminist literature is—by
design—polemical and one-sided, this is not necessarily a problem; sometimes, ideological
1
So-called “Difference feminism” has been out of fashion since the late 1990s, and did not necessarily accept
biological explanations of sex differences. Of course, one can be an equal-opportunity feminist while believing that
some sex differences in behavior and cognition have a strong biological basis, and contribute to determine enduring
differences in social outcomes. But this viewpoint has virtually no traction on present-day feminism, which—
especially in academia—is moving toward increasingly extreme versions of social constructionism (see e.g., Else-
Quest & Hyde, 2018; Pluckrose & Lindsay, 2020).
3
biases help scholars see facts and explanations that others would miss. The dialectic can remain
healthy as long as multiple viewpoints are allowed and ideas are evaluated on their own merits.
The trouble begins when an entire field or discipline aligns in the same ideological direction, so
that certain domains of research become “sacralized” and hence systematically distorted (see
Winegard & Winegard, 2018).
From this standpoint, the state of psychological research on sex and gender is mixed, with
a lot of variation across subdisciplines (and evolutionary psychology as the biggest outlier; see
Buss, 2015; Pinker, 2003; Stewart-Williams, 2018). While sex is not nearly as sacralized as race,
certain questions border on taboo; for example, biological explanations of sex differences in
educational and occupational outcomes are likely to attract denunciations and attacks, especially
if they reach the general public. As the ideological landscape evolves, previously uncontroversial
issues become morally charged in the eyes of activists; right now, the idea that there are two
biological sexes seems on its way to become “problematic” (more on this below).
Because ideological pressures in this area of psychology are uneven and relatively subtle
(especially compared with more politicized social sciences like sociology and cultural
anthropology), they are mostly expressed as implicit “preferences” that affect the design,
interpretation, publication, and divulgation of research. Roughly speaking:
a. No differences are better than any differences (unless they are presented as evidence
of discrimination);
b. Small differences are better than large differences (same as above);
c. Variable, malleable differences are better than stable, unchanging differences;
d. Socialization is better than biology.
And the list may be expanding to include:
e. Nonbinary is better than binary.
To complete this summary, one should note that, from an egalitarian perspective,
differences are better tolerated if they reflect positively on a group that is perceived as
underprivileged or oppressed (e.g., findings of higher verbal ability in females tend to be less
controversial than findings of higher spatial and mathematical ability in males). Note that the
preferences listed above are not “wrong” in the sense that they should be reversed; to be sure,
discrimination does occur, sex differences are often small, and many traits—including evolved
traits—are expressed in a context-sensitive manner and can be shaped by the environment. The
problem is that their collective weight pushes the field in a particular direction, making it easier
(or harder) to publish certain kinds of results and formulate certain interpretations. These
preferences are enforced more rigidly when approaching controversial topics, such as sex
differences in educational and occupational outcomes. They also become more visible as one
moves from the technical literature to the public interface of the discipline—for example in
introductory textbooks, course materials, and statements by professional associations. (One
4
reason may be that ideological pressures in certain sections of the public are stronger than within
psychology itself.
2
)
The result is that important topics are presented in a slanted fashion, or not discussed at
all; they include the theory of sexual selection (see Geary, 2021); the existence of large sex
differences in occupational interests (e.g., Lippa, 2010; Morris, 2016), in multivariate profiles of
personality (e.g., Del Giudice et al., 2012; Kaiser, 2019; Kaiser et al., 2020), and at the tails of
cognitive abilities (e.g., Baye & Monseur, 2016; Wai et al., 2010, 2018); findings of temporal
and cross-cultural stability (e.g., Schmitt et al., 2003; Stoet & Geary, 2020); “paradoxical”
patterns that run against simple socialization accounts, with larger sex differences in more
gender-egalitarian countries (e.g., Falk & Hermle, 2018; Kaiser, 2019; MacGiolla & Kajonius,
2019; Schmitt et al., 2017; Stoet & Geary, 2015, 2018); and cross-species similarities in sexually
differentiated behaviors (e.g., Alexander & Hines, 2002; Benenson, 2019; Cashdan & Gaulin,
2016; Hassett et al., 2008). For recent overviews of these and related topics, see Archer (2019),
Geary (2021), and Murray (2020).
Interlude: Sex, Gender, and the Binary
Up to this point I have used “sex” and “gender” casually, but before moving ahead, it is
important to do some conceptual clean-up.
3
While many scholars treat these terms as more or
less synonyms (Haig, 2004), they have different histories and implications. The usage of
“gender” as the social and/or psychological counterpart of biological sex was introduced in
psychology by Money (1955), though Bentley (1945) had made the same distinction years
before. The term was popularized by Stoller (1968) and quickly adopted by feminist scholars in
the 1970s (Haig, 2004; Janssen, 2018). “Gender” was going to denote the social roles, behaviors,
and aspects of identity associated with being male or female, as distinct from the biological
characteristics of the wo sexes. The assumption was that psychological differences are largely or
exclusively determined by socialization (see Deaux, 1985; Oakley, 1972; Unger, 1979). Scholars
began to use “gender” instead of “sex” even if the proposed definitions were frustratingly
unclear. For example, a widely cited paper by Unger (1979) defined gender as:
[T]hose nonphysiological components of sex that are culturally regarded as
appropriate to males or to females. Gender may be used for those traits for
which sex acts as a stimulus variable, independently of whether those traits
have their origin within the subject or not. It refers to a social label by which
we distinguish two groups of people (Unger, 1979, p. 1086).
This definition mixes correlations with social evaluations, and individual traits with
group labels. In fact, it may be impossible to make the concept of gender fully coherent unless
one embraces a social constructionist view. The problem is that psychological traits arise from
the interplay between social and biological processes—even worse, the very distinction between
“social” and “biological” is blurry and ill-defined (see e.g., Lippa, 2005). This makes the
2
For a revealing example, consider the reactions to James Damore’s now-infamous “memo” on sex differences in
tech jobs (Damore, 2017; see Anomaly & Winegard, 2019).
3
Parts of this section are adapted from Del Giudice (2020).
5
distinction between sex and gender effectively unworkable, as many have noted over the years
(e.g., Blakemore et al., 2009; Eagly & Wood, 2013; Ellis et al., 2008; Haig, 2004). For a recent
illustration, consider the guidelines in the latest APA publication manual:
Gender refers to the attitudes, feelings, and behaviors that a given culture
associates with a person's biological sex […] Gender is a social construct and a
social identity. […] Sex refers to biological sex assignment; use the term “sex”
when the biological distinction of sex assignment (e.g., sex assigned at birth) is
predominant. […] In some cases, there may not be a clear distinction between
biological and acculturative factors, so a discussion of both sex and gender
would be appropriate (American Psychological Association, 2019, p. 138).
As usual, “gender” is defined from a social constructionist standpoint; but in practice, the
distinction between biology and socialization is almost never clear-cut, so authors are instructed
to discuss “both sex and gender” and then left to their own devices. Interestingly, biological sex
is defined as something that gets “assigned” to people, an expression that is largely meaningless
(unless one is talking about the treatment of intersex conditions) but conforms to the precepts of
transgender activism.
The flaws of the sex-gender distinction have led some feminist scholars to adopt the
hybrid term “sex/gender” (sometimes “gender/sex”) as a way to recognize that biological and
social factors are inseparable, and underscore the potential for plasticity (Fausto-Sterling, 2012;
Hyde et al., 2019; Jordan-Young & Rumiati, 2012; Rippon et al., 2014). Unfortunately, this
terminological fusion may end up deepening the conceptual confusion. The proponents of
sex/gender usually describe it as a continuum, or even a multidimensional collection of semi-
independent features; a person’s sex/gender can be hybrid, fluid, or otherwise nonbinary (see
e.g., Hyde et al., 2019; Morgenroth & Ryan, 2020). One crucial implication is that biological sex
is also non-binary and socially constructed, in line with the tenets of fourth-wave feminism
(Else-Quest & Hyde, 2018; Pluckrose & Lindsay, 2020). On this view, the “sex binary” is a
socially constructed fiction; the old idea that there are two sexes is simplistic and inaccurate, and
does not stand up to sophisticated analysis. Hence, “male” and “female” should be replaced with
multiple overlapping categories, or even (multi)dimensional scores of gendered self-concepts
and attitudes (Hyde et al., 2019; Joel & Fausto-Sterling, 2016). This argument can be seductive
but has one problem—it fundamentally misunderstands the nature of sex. I now briefly discuss
why.
The Real Sex Binary
In the social sciences, many scholars define sex as a collection of traits—X/Y
chromosomes, gonads, hormones, and genitals—that cluster together in most people but may
also occur in rare atypical combinations (e.g., Blakemore et al., 2009; Fausto-Sterling, 2012;
Helgeson, 2016; Joel, 2012). This definition is the basis for the widely repeated claim that up to
2% of live births are intersex (Blackless et al., 2000; see e.g., Hyde et al., 2019). In fact, the 2%
figure is a gross overestimate. Blackless et al. (2000) defined intersex very broadly as individuals
who deviate from the “Platonic ideal” of sex dimorphism; accordingly, they included several
conditions (e.g., Klinefelter syndrome, vaginal agenesis, congenital adrenal hyperplasia) that
6
affect sexual development but can be classified as “intersex” only in a very loose sense (Sax,
2002). If one restricts the term to conditions that involve a discordance between chromosomal
and phenotypic sex, or a phenotype that cannot be classified unambiguously as either male or
female, the frequency of intersex is almost certainly less than 0.02% (Sax, 2002; see also Hull,
2003).
On a deeper level, the “patchwork” definition of sex used in the social sciences is purely
descriptive and lacks a functional rationale. This contrasts sharply with how the sexes are
defined in biology. From a biological standpoint, what distinguishes the males and females of a
species is the size of their gametes: males produce small gametes (e.g., sperm), females produce
large gametes (e.g., eggs; Kodric-Brown & Brown, 1987).
4
Dimorphism in gamete size or
anisogamy is the dominant pattern in multicellular organisms, including animals. The evolution
of two gamete types with different sizes and roles in fertilization is the predictable consequence
of selection to maximize the efficiency of fertilization (Lehtonen & Kokko, 2011; Lehtonen &
Parker, 2014). In turn, anisogamy set the stage for sexual selection (i.e., selection via mating
competition and mate choice), with predictable consequences for the evolution of sexually
differentiated traits in morphology, development, and behavior (Janicke et al., 2016; Lehtonen et
al., 2016; Schärer et al., 2012). Of course, the existence of two distinct sexes does not mean that
sex-related traits must also have binary, sharply bimodal distributions. The sex binary is
perfectly compatible with large amounts of within-sex variation in anatomy, physiology, and
behavior. In fact, sexual selection often amplifies individual variability in sex-related traits
(typically more strongly in males), and can favor the evolution of multiple alternative phenotypes
within each sex (see Del Giudice et al., 2018b; Taborsky & Brockmann, 2010).
To be clear, the biological definition of sex is not just one option among many equally
valid alternatives; the very existence of differentiated males and females in a species depends on
the existence of two gamete types. Chromosomes and hormones participate in the mechanics of
sex determination and sexual differentiation, but do not play the same foundational role. The sex
binary, then, is not a fiction but a basic biological fact: even if a given individual may fail to
produce viable gametes, there are only two gamete types with no meaningful intermediate forms
(Lehtonen & Parker, 2014; see also Cretella et al., 2019). This dichotomy is not statistical but
functional, and hence is not challenged by the existence of intersex conditions (regardless of
their frequency), nonbinary gender identities, and other seeming exceptions. As a rule, scholars
who argue against the “sex/gender binary” are happy to dive into the fine details of sexual
differentiation, but typically avoid mentioning anisogamy, let alone grappling with its
implications for the evolution of the sexes. This has not stopped the misconception that “sex is
not binary” from spreading, not just in the social sciences but in the broader literature. In 2015,
Nature published a feature claiming that sex had been “redefined” along nonbinary lines
(Ainsworth, 2015); in 2020, a research update on the COVID-19 virus came with the disclaimer
“Nature recognizes that sex and gender are neither binary nor fixed” (Nature, 2020).
In the rest of the chapter, I always use “sex” and “sex differences” whenever the
distinction is between males and females as groups. When discussing research on stereotypes,
4
Species with simultaneous hermaphroditism (mostly plants and invertebrates) do not have distinct sexes, since any
individual can produce both types of gametes at the same time.
7
social perception, identity, etc., I use “sex” and “gender” in a context-sensitive manner, without
any implications about biology vs. socialization. (For example, it has become customary to talk
of “gender stereotypes” instead of “sex stereotypes”, and I use the standard label for simplicity.)
A Peek at the Recent Literature
Introductory Textbooks
For many college students, introductory textbooks represent the first or only exposure to
the field of psychology. As an informal survey of the field, I went through seven recent
introductory psychology textbooks, five traditional (Burton et al., 2019; Grison & Gazzaniga,
2019; Kalat, 2016; Morris & Maisto, 2018; Schachter et al., 2020) and two open-access (Noba
Project, 2020; Spielman, 2020). Note that I selected these textbooks based on availability, so this
should not be mistaken for a systematic overview. In two texts out of seven (Grison &
Gazzaniga; Spielman), sex differences in personality and cognition were not discussed at all,
except for some vague references to gender stereotypes. Sex differences in personality were
mentioned in only two textbooks (Kalat; Schacter et al.); in both cases, the authors described
them as small and emphasized overall similarities. All seven texts mentioned sex differences in
aggression and/or mating and noted possible biological explanations (Burton et al.; Kalat; Noba
Project; Schacter et al.), although in most cases the coverage was extremely cursory and partial.
Five textbooks addressed sex differences in cognitive abilities, while emphasizing similarity
and/or malleability (Burton et al.; Kalat; Morris & Maisto; Noba Project; Schacter et al.). One of
them cited evidence that cognitive sex differences are stable across time and places (Burton et
al.), but none discussed findings of stronger differences in gender-egalitarian countries. Five
texts introduced at least some concepts related to sexual selection, however briefly (Burton et al.;
Kalat; Morris & Maisto; Noba Project;
5
Schacter et al.). Finally, two texts out of seven offered
“nonbinary” accounts of sex and/or gender (Grison & Gazzaniga; Noba Project).
This quick survey illustrates many of the trends I discussed earlier. As expected, there is
an overall tendency to ignore and/or downplay sex differences, to the point that a substantial
fraction of the textbooks was partly or completely silent on the issue. At the same time, there is
quite a bit of variation in coverage, and a few outliers that deviate from the general trend. The
textbooks also revealed a tension between the standard preferences of the discipline and the
growing influence of evolutionary psychology, particularly in specific domains such as mating
and aggression (see also Ferguson et al., 2016).
Generalist Journals
Within the technical literature, generalist journals facilitate the exchange of ideas and
findings across specialized subfields. Because they publish papers from multiple areas of
research, generalist journals should provide something like an “average” picture of the discipline,
smoothing out the biases and intellectual traditions of individual areas. For this survey, I
5
The Noba Project textbook is a collection of stand-alone chapters, each written by different authors. Sexual
selection was discussed in the chapter on evolutionary psychology (Buss, 2020), but not in the one on gender, which
took a decidedly social-constructionist approach (Brown et al., 2020).
8
reviewed the papers published during the years 2018-2020 in six high-impact journals: American
Psychologist, Psychological Review, Psychological Bulletin, Annual Review of Psychology,
Current Directions in Psychological Science, and Perspectives on Psychological Science.
6
I
selected relevant papers based on their title and abstract, and counted a total of 19 articles
dealing with sex and gender.
7
Of the 19 papers, four centered on the idea of challenging the sex/gender binary: a widely
disseminated paper by Hyde et al. (2019); two comments to Hyde et al., one favorable (Reilly,
2019) ad one critical (Cretella et al., 2020); and a radical social-constructionist piece by
Morgenroth and Ryan (2020).
Three papers dealt specifically with gender stereotypes. These were a review of the topic
by Ellemers (2018), a historical analysis of stereotype changes in the USA by Eagly et al. (2020),
and an experimental study on negative stereotypes about the intellectual ability of girls and
women (Bian et al., 2018). In her review, Ellemers rejected the idea that gender stereotypes may
reflect actual psychological differences between the sexes (“If there is a kernel of truth
underlying gender stereotypes, it is a tiny kernel”; p. 278), and gave short shrift to possible
biological explanations. In the study by Bian et al., participants seemed to assume that people
with very high intelligence are more likely to be males than females. The authors dismissed this
belief as a “negative stereotype about women”; they seemed unaware that males are in fact
overrepresented at the high end of the IQ distribution (as well as the low end; e.g., Arden &
Plomin, 2006; Johnson et al., 2008).
8
A fourth paper by Gruber et al. (2020) was a wide-ranging
analysis of gender gaps in academic psychology (e.g., career advancement, salary, grants,
publication and citation rates). This paper was noteworthy because it dismissed some robust
empirical patterns—men are overrepresented at the highest levels of cognitive ability, men are
more assertive and dominant, women are more communal—as mere stereotypes (see Del
Giudice, 2015; Twenge, 1997). The authors also embraced a socialization account of sex
differences, and rejected the possibility that some of them may have an adaptive explanation.
Of the remaining eleven papers, four took an explicitly evolutionary approach: a review
of men’s and women’s response to sexual versus emotional infidelity (Buss, 2018); a
comparative analysis of peer relationships in male and female humans vs. other primates
(Benenson, 2019); a paper on mitochondrial functioning as a mechanism for variation in general
intelligence, and a possible contributing factor to sex difference in variability (Geary, 2018); and
a conceptual paper on gender as the basis for social cognition (Martin & Slepian, 2020).
9
6
I completed this survey on November 9th, 2020, and included advance publication papers that were online at that
time.
7
One additional paper (Weberman & Murphy, 2020) offered recommendations to reduce “gender-based violence
and misconduct on college campuses”. Since this paper had a strictly applied focus and did not deal with basic
research on sex and gender, I excluded it from the survey.
8
The issue of greater male variability in intellectual abilities has a long and contentious history, which I address
later in the chapter.
9
More precisely, Martin and Slepian (2020) mixed ideas about evolved psychological mechanisms from
evolutionary psychology with the socialization account of social role theory (Eagly & Wood, 2012, 2016; see
below). The result is a strangely incoherent theory, according to which (a) humans possess evolved, deeply
9
Another experimental study (Treat et al., 2020) investigated men’s perception of women’s sexual
interest, but—surprisingly—failed to mention the substantial evolutionary literature on this topic
(e.g., Haselton, 2003; Haselton et al., 2016; Murray et al., 2017; Perilloux & Kurzban, 2015).
The final six papers were all meta-analyses or systematic reviews of sex differences. The
topics were episodic memory (Asperholm et al., 2019), student achievement in reading/writing
(Reilly et al., 2019), the initiation of negotiations (Kugler et al., 2018),
10
the development of
spatial reasoning (Lauer et al., 2019), the prevalence of mental disorders (Hartung & Lefler,
2019), and maternal reminiscing styles (differentiated by the child’s sex; Waters et al., 2019). Of
the meta-analyses that included a review of theoretical models, three considered both social and
biological explanations (Asperholm et al., 2019; Hartung & Lefler, 2019; Reilly et al., 2019),
while two only considered socialization effects (Kugler et al., 2018; Waters et al., 2019).
Once again, this brief survey of generalist journals reveals a fair amount of theoretical
diversity, but also a pervasive tendency to emphasize socialization over biology and downplay
robust empirical findings as “stereotypes”. Four out of 19 papers were motivated by the
transparently ideological project of challenging (and ultimately “disrupting”) the sex/gender
binary.
Among other things, this survey is a reminder of the continuing popularity of social role
theory (SRT; Eagly & Wood, 1999, 2012, 2016; Wood & Eagly, 2012) in the sex differences
literature. SRT played a major theoretical role in four of the papers (Gruber et al., 2020; Eagly et
al., 2020; Kugler et al., 2018; Martin & Slepian, 2020) and was cited in another four (Ellemers,
2018; Hyde et al., 2019; Morgenroth & Ryan, 2020; Reilly et al., 2019), for a total of eight
papers out of 19. (SRT was also cited in four of the seven introductory textbooks: Burton et al.;
Kalat; Noba Project; Schacter et al.) In a nutshell, the theory posits that evolved sex differences
in physical and reproductive traits (e.g., size, strength, pregnancy and lactation) have shaped the
division of labor between men and women throughout history (e.g., warfare vs. child-rearing). In
turn, the continued existence of sexually differentiated tasks has created powerful cultural
stereotypes about masculine and feminine traits, most notably along the axes of
dominance/agency vs. nurturance/communion. These stereotypes affect individual behavior
through socialization (partly via role-congruent activation of hormonal changes, for example in
testosterone and oxytocin levels), leading to the development of psychological differences
between the sexes.
ingrained, and stable gender schemas about typical masculine vs. feminine behaviors; but (b) masculine and
feminine behaviors themselves are mainly shaped by socialization, and malleable to the point that they can be
changed with subtle linguistic interventions (e.g., relabeling assertive and competitive behaviors from “masculine”
to “agentic” should help women become more competitive in the workplace).
10
The meta-analysis by Kugler et al. (2018) found that sex differences in the initiation of negotiation (a behavior
that is thought to contribute to gender inequalities) were “small” by conventional statistical criteria (for a detailed
critique of conventional criteria for effect sizes, see Del Giudice, 2020). As I noted above, this is usually a preferred
outcome—but not when differences are presented as evidence of discrimination. Indeed, the authors went to some
length to explain that even small effects can cumulate over time and give rise to large differences in outcomes—a
reasonable argument, but one that is rarely brought up in the literature on “gender similarities” (e.g., Hyde, 2005,
2014; but see Zell et al., 2015).
10
According to SRT, psychological sex differences are mostly constructed by socialization
practices, but the fact that they are ultimately grounded in evolved physical differences explains
their stability across time and cultures. From a biological standpoint, SRT is extremely
implausible, as it postulates an unexplained dualism between physical traits (subject to natural
and sexual selection) and psychological traits (more or less untouched by selection and only
shaped by socialization, either directly or indirectly via hormonal regulation).
11
Moreover, the
theory fails to explain why many sex differences become larger in more gender-egalitarian
cultures (see Friedman et al., 2000; Geary, 2021; Kenrick & Li, 2000; Schmitt, 2015). However,
SRT has proven quite attractive to social scientists, likely because it allows them to effectively
adopt a pure socialization perspective—and avoid inconvenient questions about evolved sex
differences “in the brain”—without appearing to reject evolutionary biology (see also Geary,
2021).
A Jump into the Time Warp
The received view on the history of sex and gender in psychology is nicely summarized
by this quote, from an article in the Monitor on Psychology announcing the APA’s new and
controversial “guidelines for psychological practice with boys and men”:
Prior to the second-wave feminist movement in the 1960s, all psychology was
the psychology of men. Most major studies were done only on white men and
boys, who stood in as proxies for humans as a whole. Researchers assumed that
11
In a recent video interview (October 10th, 2019; https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=gPsXpDIE0LA), Alice Eagly
claimed that she had never denied the existence of sexually selected differences in psychological traits, but had
simply chosen to emphasize the role of socialization. This is a transcript of the segment (starting at 17:56):
They [the evolutionary critics] put words in my mouth that I never said! I never said there
weren’t such influences. It’s merely that I emphasized others that they forget about. So I
would not claim that there are no such effects of prenatal androgenization or sexual selection
or whatever, but the force of my work has been to show that there are other influences, and
we need to get it all together.
This will come as a surprise to the many scholars who have used SRT precisely to discount the role of sexual
selection and other biological factors. But the interview does raise the question of what SRT actually says in this
regard. Re-reading the key papers presenting the theory, I could not find a single passage explicitly stating that
psychological sex differences can be explained by sexual selection, though I did find a number of passages
suggesting the opposite (e.g., Eagly & Wood, 1999, p. 415; Eagly & Wood, 2016, p. 464). Wood and Eagly (2012)
came closest to accepting an organizational role for prenatal androgens, but described the evidence as equivocal and
concluded that “[a]lthough sex-differentiated social experience surely does not operate on a blank slate, what is
written on that slate has not been adequately deciphered so far” (p. 67). Throughout the chapter, they discussed how
socialization may affect hormonal regulation, but not how hormonal differences may modulate social interactions
(note that, in their Figure 1, socialization factors affect hormonal regulation, but not vice versa). Similarly, Wood
and Eagly (2000) stated: “[…] we recognize that such biological factors [hormones] work in concert with
psychological processes involving social expectations and self-concepts to yield sex differences in behavior”, and
seemed to endorse “a feedback model in which testosterone affects socially dominant behavior and is in turn
affected by such behavior and its outcomes”. My conclusion is that Eagly and Wood hedged their bets on the role of
sex hormones; their writing on this issue invites a deflationary reading, but remains open to alternative
interpretations (see also Eagly, 2018). On the other hand, as far as I can tell these authors always portrayed SRT as
an alternative to sexual selection on psychological traits, rather than a complementary explanation.
11
masculinity and femininity were opposite ends of a spectrum, and “healthy”
psychology entailed identifying strongly with the gender roles conferred by a
person’s biological sex (Pappas, 2019, p. 35).
To call this a distorted account would be an understatement: as I show in this section, this
familiar narrative turns out to be an almost complete fabrication. I do not blame the author of this
quote, though; she simply distilled what can be found in ostensibly authoritative sources, such as
this chapter by Denmark et al. (2008) in the second edition of Psychology of women:
12
When one examines the psychological research from Wundt’s 1874
establishment of the domain of psychology up to recent times, psychology
appeared to focus almost exclusively on the behavior of men or male animals.
In other words, the first method of examining woman was to categorize them
as lacking. Much early research that included female subjects came to the
conclusion that women were inferior in some way. Additionally, if females
were included in the sample, neither sex nor gender differences were reported,
which discounted the influence of these factors and, in essence, was an
indication of the belief that men were the norm when considering various
psychological factors. And again, if women were included in the studies,
biased results indicated that women were by nature inferior. […] However,
generally speaking, most early research never investigated comparisons
between women and men at all (Schwabacher, 1972). Wendy McKenna and
Suzanne Kessler (1976) reported that over 95 percent of all early research did
not examine female-male comparisons, therefore ignoring any possible
differences due to sex and gender. Prior to the 1970s, almost all research on
women had been relegated to the periphery of psychology rather than
integrated into its main body. (Denmark et al., 2008, pp. 5-6).
The entire passage sounds immediately suspicious if one considers that, already in 1894,
Havelock Ellis could draw on dozens of studies of psychological sex differences for his
influential book Man and woman (more on this below). I was particularly struck by the blanket
statement about “over 95 percent of all early research”, so I looked up the original paper by
McKenna and Kessler (1977; the 1976 date in the quote is incorrect). To my (mild) surprise, the
actual study had little to do with the description. McKenna and Kessler did not analyze “all early
research” in psychology, but the latest 312 human experiments on interpersonal attraction and
244 on aggression, ending on December 1973. The authors did not report the date of the earliest
studies in the analysis, but it is unlikely that they went further back than 10-20 years.
13
They
12
I recommend the Denmark et al. chapter as a counterpoint to my “revisionist” account. For a less biased history of
the field, see Chapter 2 in Blakemore et al. (2009).
13
The authors checked 600 entries for each topic as reported in the Psychological Abstracts. Google Scholar returns
1,810 results for “interpersonal attraction” between 1953 and 1973 (searched on November 11, 2020). If one third of
them was reported in the Abstracts, that would amount to about 600 entries.
12
found that 38-45% of the studies included both males and females,
14
but did not say how many
of those studies involved comparisons between the sexes.
15
This is not an isolated case; feminist history is full of similar distortions and “urban
legends” that rarely get corrected from the inside. Notable examples include the claim that
women have been underrepresented as participants in medical research (Satel, 2002); that
biologists clung to the idea of sperm as active and “macho” and eggs as passive and “coy”
because of their sexist prejudices (Gross, 1998); that Victorian physicians used vibrators on
female patients to treat hysteria (Lieberman & Schatzberg, 2018); and that before World War II,
the color pink was associated with boys while blue was associated with girls (Del Giudice, 2012,
2017). The problem is not with feminism per se but with activist history in general; whatever the
virtues, an activist mindset is a major impediment to critical scrutiny and self-correction, and
encourages distortions in the service of the ideological narrative (Hoff Sommers, 2009).
Unfortunately, activist history is what one often gets when it comes to sex and gender. In the rest
of this section, I use citations from original sources to identify recurring themes and trace some
trends that go back more than a hundred years. Some of the quotes are lengthy, but I think it is
important to go beyond the soundbites and let the sources speak more freely.
The Dark Ages (Before the Sixties)
The best place to start may be the first edition of Havelock Ellis’ Man and woman (1894).
This book is a wide-ranging overview of sex differences and similarities in physical and
psychological traits. Considering that it was written more than 120 years ago, I think it has aged
remarkably well.
16
Throughout the book, Ellis took pains to acknowledge possible biases, strike
a balance between nature and nurture, and reject the idea of female (or male) inferiority. Here are
a few quotes that convey the spirit of the book:
It is also being recognised as reasonable that both sexes should study side by
side at the school and the college, and where not side by side, still in closely
similar fashion, while the recreations of each sex are to some extent becoming
common to both. Such conditions have tended to remove artificial sexual
differences, and have largely obliterated the coarser signs of superiority which
may before have been possessed by one sex over another. The process of
transition is still in rapid progress (Ellis, 1894, p. 17).
14
Combined data from Table 1 and Table 2 in McKenna and Kessler (1977).
15
McKenna and Kessler cited a paper by Carlson and Carlson (1960), who examined 298 human studies published
in the Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology between 1958 and 1960. They found that 36% of the studies
included participants of both sexes, and that 30% of those studies reported statistical tests of sex differences. There
was no information about the proportion of studies that reported descriptive statistics for both sexes without
performing a test (and vice versa).
16
Needless to say, there are a lot of incorrect or outdated statements in the book, and some ideas of the time (e.g.,
the recurring distinction between “higher” and “lower” races) have definitely not aged well. But readers familiar
with current research on sex differences will be struck by how many issues Ellis managed to get approximately
right, despite the limited data and conceptual tools available at the time.
13
On biases in sex differences research:
We have to recognise, it will be seen, not merely the difficulties which come
from too small a number of observations, where we have the resource of
putting one series of observations against another, but also the more serious
difficulty of inevitable bias in the investigator's mind. […] Thus one
conscientious investigator (like Manouvrier) may find that all the facts of
anatomy and physiology point to the superiority of women; another, equally
conscientious (like Delaunay), may find that they all point to the superiority of
men (ibid., pp. 28-29).
On sex differences in brain anatomy:
While, however, the brain is at present an unprofitable region for the study of
sexual difference, it is, as we have seen, an extremely instructive region for
the study of sexual equality. Men possess no relative superiority of brain-
mass; the superiority in brain-mass, so far as it exists, is on woman's side;
17
this, however, implies no intellectual superiority, but is merely a characteristic
of short people and children. Nor is there any well-marked sexual arrangement
of the nervous elements which implies relative inferiority on one side or the
other (ibid., p. 113).
On sex differences in emotionality (discussed under the rubric of “affectability”):
The question still remains how far the affectability of women is natural and
organic, how far it is the mere accidental result of external circumstances. Is
the greater emotionality of women a permanent and ineradicable fact? There
can be no doubt that to a very large extent emotionality may be modified. […]
Just as we have sure reason to believe that sensibility may by training be
increased, so there is still greater reason to believe that affectability may by
training be decreased. That there is, however, a limit to this sexual
equalisation of affectability remains extremely probable. […] Affectability in
women may be reduced to finer and more delicate shades; it can scarcely be
brought to the male standard.
This result is by no means to be regretted. We have seen that the affectability
of women ensures to them certain solid advantages, and assists to safeguard
them against evils from which men are specially prone to suffer. (ibid., p. 313-
314).
18
17
Note that Ellis was talking about differences in relative brain mass, after adjusting for differences in body mass or
size. Ellis spent several pages (pp. 95-101) reviewing alternative ways to make this adjustment and considering their
limitations. In contrast with Ellis’ conclusions, the recent evidence shows that men have a larger brain even
controlling for body size (e.g., Ankney, 1992; Ritchie et al., 2018).
18
Neuroticism/Emotional stability is one of the personality traits showing the largest and most robust differences
between men and women. Sex differences become even larger in more gender-egalitarian countries, a finding that
would have surprised even Ellis (see MacGiolla & Kajonius, 2018; Schmitt et al., 2017).
14
On Darwin’s hypothesis of greater male variability:
Both the physical and the mental characters of men show wider limits of
variation than do the physical and mental characters of women. Monsters are
more often male than female. […] Abnormal variations of nearly all kinds are
more frequent in men than in women. […] We must regard genius as an
organic congenital abnormality (although the evidence in proof of this cannot
be entered into here), and in nearly every department it is, undeniably, of more
frequent occurrence among men than among women. The statement of this
fact has sometimes been regarded by women as a slur upon their sex; they
have sought to explain it by lack of opportunity, education, etc. It does not
appear that women have been equally anxious to find fallacies in the statement
that idiocy is more common among men. Yet the two statements must be
taken together. Genius is more common among men by virtue of the same
general tendency by which idiocy is more common among men. The two facts
are but two aspects of a larger zoological fact—the greater variability of the
male (ibid., p. 358-366).
And finally:
Any reader who has turned to this book for facts or arguments bearing on the
everlasting discussion regarding the “alleged inferiority of women,” and who
has followed me so far, will already have gathered the natural conclusion we
reach on this point. We may regard all such discussion as absolutely futile and
foolish. If it is a question of determining the existence and significance of
some particular physical or psychic sexual difference a conclusion may not be
impossible. To make any broad statement of the phenomena is to recognise
that no general conclusion is possible. Now and again we come across facts
which group themselves with a certain degree of uniformity, but as we
continue we find other equally important facts which group themselves with
equal uniformity in another sense. The result produces compensation (ibid.,
pp. 393-394).
One should remember that first-wave feminism was already ascendant at the end of the
19th century, and was going to intensify in the early decades of the 20th. A key representative of
this period was Helen Thompson Woolley, who in 1903 published The mental traits of sex, a
thorough experimental investigation of sex differences across dozens of tasks.
19
At the end of the
book, Woolley took issue with then-current biological explanations of sex differences
20
—
19
Unfortunately the sample was very small (25 men and 25 women), so the results were far less reliable than
assumed at the time. For example, Woolley failed to detect any sex differences in emotion-related measures, and
used this finding to argue that women’s higher emotionality was a baseless stereotype (see below).
20
In particular, Woolley criticized Geddes and Thomson’s (1889) theory of the evolution of sex, a then-popular
alternative to Darwin’s (1871) theory of sexual selection. Many biologists regarded sexual selection theory as
dubious until it was formalized by Fisher (1930); in the meantime, there were several attempts to develop an
alternative account of the evolution of males and females. Geddes and Thomson’s theory was one of those attempts,
15
including the hypothesis of greater male variability —and concluded with a plea for
environmental explanations:
The biological theory of psychological differences of sex is not in a condition
to compel assent. While it is true, therefore, that the present investigation
tends to support the theory, it is also true that the uncertain basis of the theory
itself leaves room for other explanations of the facts, if there are other
satisfactory ways of explaining them.
[…] Although the timeworn controversy is far from satisfactory settlement,
the results of recent observation of individual development have tended to
emphasize more and more the extreme importance of environment. […]
The fact that very genuine and important differences of environment do exist
can be denied only by the most superficial observer. Even in our country,
where boys and girls are allowed to go to the same schools and to play
together to some extent, the social atmosphere is different, from the cradle.
Different toys are given them, different occupations and games are taught
them, different ideals of conduct are held up before them. […]
It will probably be said that this view of the case puts the cart before the
horse—that the training and social surroundings of the sexes are different
because their natural characteristics are different. It will be said that a boy is
encouraged to activity because he is naturally active […] But there are many
indications that these very interests are socially stimulated. […]
There are, as everyone must recognize, signs of a radical change in the social
ideals of sex. The point to be emphasized as the outcome of this study is that,
according to our present light, the psychological differences of sex seem to be
largely due, not to difference of average capacity, nor to difference in type of
mental activity, but to differences in the social influences brought to bear on
the developing individual from early infancy to adult years. The question of
the future development of the intellectual life of women is one of social
necessities and ideals, rather than one of inborn psychological characteristics
of sex (Thompson, 1903, pp. 176-182).
Woolley’s book exemplifies some then-developing trends that have persisted to this day,
including the preference for socialization accounts and the diffidence toward biological
explanations. In 1910 and 1914, Woolley wrote two influential reviews of sex differences
research in the Psychological Bulletin. These reviews foreshadow other important themes—
including the growing emphasis on sex similarities within psychology, and the increasing
divergence between the findings of rigorous research and laypeople’s ideas about male and
female psychology. For example:
[T]here seems to be a general trend toward the opinion that mind is probably
not a secondary sexual character—in other words that there are probably few
if any psychological differences of sex which are of biological origin—a
statement which I think holds true in spite of the continued popularity of such
based on the opposition between anabolic and catabolic processes; in fairness to Woolley, there was plenty to be
critical about.
16
books as Mobius' Physiologischer Schwachsinn des Weibes and Weininger's
Geschlecht und Character. The tendency to minimize sexual differences is
most marked with regard to intellectual processes, the field where most of the
experimental work has been done, and in which the practical educational tests
have been made. Even the time-honored belief that men are more capable of
independent and creative work is beginning to give way in view of the
successful competition of women in graduate work and in obtaining the
doctorate [….] The fundamental importance of sexual differences in affective
processes and in standards of conduct still commands a larger measure of
credence. The world at large is quite agreed that women are to a greater extent
than men dominated by emotions, though the only direct experimental
evidence does not support this view […]
Finally, one might characterize the drift of recent discussion as a shift of
emphasis from a biological to a sociological interpretation of the mental
characteristics of sex. The very small amount of difference between the sexes
in those functions open to experimentation, the contradictory results obtained
from different series of investigations, and the nature of the differences which
prove to be most constant, have led to the belief that the psychological
differences of sex are of sociological rather than of biological origin
(Woolley, 1910, pp. 341-342).
In 1914, Woolley remarked that psychological research on sex differences was growing
so fast that it had become impossible to keep up with all the new literature:
During the four years since my last review of the literature of the psychology
of sex […] the number of experimental investigations in the field has
increased to such an extent that whereas it was difficult at that time to find
anything to review, it is now impossible to review all I could find (Woolley,
1914, p. 353).
Compare this statement with the narrative that “up to recent times, psychology appeared
to focus almost exclusively on the behavior of men or male animals,” or that “most early
research never investigated comparisons between women and men at all” (Denmark et al., 2008).
It can also be useful to stress that the psychologists of the 1910s were not simply concluding that
“women were by nature inferior”; on the contrary, Woolley (1910, 1914) listed several areas in
which women had been found to consistently outperform men, including aspects of perception,
memory, and reasoning.
Psychological research in Europe slowed down during World War I, but there were
enough studies to fill regular reviews in the Psychological Bulletin. Leta Hollingworth wrote a
series of those reviews in 1916, 1918, and 1919. A recurring theme was the variability
hypothesis, which Hollingworth herself had critiqued and researched (e.g. Hollingworth, 1914).
The data available at this point were contradictory, and opinions on the topic remained sharply
17
divided.
21
As I discuss later, the question of variability would take almost another hundred years
to be answered with confidence. This is how Hollingworth concluded her 1919 review:
The year's work yields nothing consistent as a result of the comparison of the
sexes in mental traits. In this respect it resembles the work of other years.
Pressey finds that girls excel boys in mental tests at all ages, from 8 to 16
years, inclusive; Porteus finds that boys excel girls at nearly all ages. Pressey
finds that boys are more variable than girls; Frasier finds that there are no sex
differences in variability. In group after group of superior children, the highest
intelligence is found now in a boy, now in a girl. Perhaps the logical
conclusion to be reached on the basis of these findings is that the custom of
perpetuating this review is no longer profitable, and may as well be
abandoned (Hollingworth, 1919, p. 373).
Like other feminist authors, Hollingworth was acutely skeptical of biological
explanations, and emphasized the role of environmental differences and the limitations imposed
by pregnancy and childcare. By then, this attitude was fairly widespread in academic circles. I do
not want to exaggerate the impact of egalitarian ideals on early 20th century psychology;
especially in applied areas such as clinical psychology and education, it is easy to find influential
works full of unsupported speculations about sex differences. A case in point is the often-quoted
Youth: its education, regimen, and hygiene by G. Stanley Hall (1906).
22
But I do want to
challenge the myth that academic psychology was indifferent or hostile to women until second-
wave feminism came about in the 1960s and 70s.
23
As literature reviews on sex differences continued to be published regularly, the concerns
of the field kept evolving. Allen (1927, 1930) noted the growing interest in sex hormones,
fostered by the striking advances in endocrinology that were taking place in the 1920s and 30s.
While the variability hypothesis was still debated, the prevailing opinion was that sex differences
are heavily influenced by environmental factors, and tend to be relatively small across the board.
Allen repeated the same conclusions in both his 1927 and 1930 reviews:
By way of summary, three points should be noted:
1. Few, if any, of the so-called “sex differences” are due solely to sex.
Individual differences often are greater than differences determined on the
basis of sex.
21
For example, Edward Thorndike was an early advocate of the hypothesis (Thorkdike, 1906); Lewis Terman
initially argued against it, but changed his mind in his later work (see McNemar & Terman, 1936; Terman et al.,
1946).
22
Then again, see Thorndike (1906) for a different perspective on the same issue.
23
Shields (1975) recounts the same period in the history of psychology, but from the standard feminist assumptions
that sex differences are largely socially constructed; that the variability hypothesis (like other biological
explanations) was only accepted because it justified women’s subordination; that the idea of an evolved “maternal
instinct” is nothing but a subtly oppressive fiction; etc. From this vantage point, everything looks much darker. But
even then, there is no ground for the narrative that “all psychology was the psychology of men”; and the
contributions of Hollingworth, Woolley, and other feminist psychologists were not marginalized, but published in
top journals, widely discussed, and accepted by many in the discipline.
18
2. The social training of the two sexes is, and always has been, different,
producing differential selective factors, interests, standards, etc.
3. The number of variables which either cannot or have not been controlled
hitherto make conclusions uncertain. Among other factors, a more careful
definition of terms is needed (Allen, 1927, p. 301).
Before moving on, I want to briefly discuss Terman and Miles’ (1936) seminal work on
masculinity-femininity (M-F) as a trait of individual variation. Terman and Miles measured M-F
as a bipolar construct, an idea that was to come under fire in the 1970s and be quickly
abandoned, only to be rediscovered in the 1990s (more on this below). The point I want to bring
up is that, contrary to the received view, discuss Terman and Miles did not equate mental health
with a rigid identification with one’s biologically prescribed role. Instead, they described
masculinity and femininity as continuous rather than mutually exclusive categories, and argued
that inflexible masculine/feminine roles take a toll on individuals and society:
Masculinity and femininity are important aspects of human personality. They
are not to be thought of as lending to it merely a superficial coloring and
flavor; rather they are one of a small number of cores around which the
structure of personality gradually takes shape. The masculine-feminine
contrast is probably as deeply grounded, whether by nature or by nurture, as
any other which human temperament presents. […] Whether it is less or more
grounded in general physiological and biochemical factors than these remains
to be seen. In how far the lines of cleavage it represents are inevitable is
unknown, but the possibility of eliminating it from human nature is at least
conceivable. The fact remains that the M-F dichotomy, in various patterns, has
existed throughout history and is still firmly established in our mores. In a
considerable fraction of the population it is the source of many acute
difficulties in the individual’s social and sexual adjustment and in a greater
fraction it affords a most important impetus to creative work and happiness.
The indications are that the present situation, together with the problems it
raises for education, psychology, and social legislation, will remain with us
for a long time to come.
As long as the child is faced by two relatively distinct patterns of personality,
each attracting him by its unique features, and is yet required by social
pressures to accept the one and reject the other, a healthy integration of
personality may often be difficult to achieve. Cross-parent fixations will
continue to foster sexual inversion; the less aggressively inclined males will
be driven to absurd compensations to mask their femininity; the more
aggressive and independent females will be at a disadvantage in the marriage
market; competition between the sexes will be rife in industry, in politics, and
in the home as it is today (Terman & Miles, 1936, p. 451-452).
This is what Terman and colleagues wrote ten years later:
19
Present-day concepts of sexuality no longer regard maleness and femaleness
as mutually exclusive categories. Sex is not an all-or-none affair; masculinity
and femininity are relative terms. […]
The biochemical forces which activate masculine and feminine behavior are in
some degree present in both sexes. […] As someone has stated it, there are no
men, there are no women; there are only sexual majorities (Terman et al.,
1946, p. 955).
With the rise and consolidation of behaviorism, the eclipse of evolutionary psychology at
the end of the 1930s (Gillette, 2007),
24
and the ebbing of fist-wave feminism, the 1940s and 50s
were relatively uneventful for sex differences research. The idea that popular stereotypes
exaggerate small and inconsequential differences persisted (e.g., Fernberger, 1948); other
scholars saw the possibility for a détente between nature and nurture:
For the present we may well avoid the extreme position common both among
laymen and scientists a generation ago, that nearly all sex differences are to be
accounted for in terms of original nature, and avoid equally the extreme
position which holds that the temperaments of men and women are no more
sex-determined than their clothing. Now that feminism is no longer a violent
issue, it is becoming possible to examine the picture of sex differences
unmoved by emotions deriving from sex rivalry. The physiologist has long
known that woman is something other than a wombed man, the social
psychologist is beginning to suspect it, and one dares look forward to a change
in the present-day bias of the cultural anthropologists (Johnson & Terman,
1940, p. 331).
All of this was going to change dramatically, starting with the late 1960s and culminating
in the 1970s; so this is where I go next.
The Seventies
The rise of second-wave feminism was not the only historical shift in the psychology of
the Seventies. There were also the decline of behaviorism and psychoanalysis; the situationist
turn in social and personality psychology; and the (attempted) resurrection of evolutionary
psychology on the wings of the sociobiological revolution (see Segerstråle, 2000). The mix was
explosive. The moment is best captured by Naomi Weisstein’s famous essay Psychology
constructs the female, first published in 1968:
It is an interesting but limited exercise to show that psychologists and
psychiatrists embrace these sexist norms of our culture, that they do not see
beyond the most superficial and stultifying media conceptions of female
nature, and that their ideas of female nature serve industry and commerce so
well. Just because it’s good for business doesn’t mean it’s wrong. What I will
24
Few know that the term “evolutionary psychology” was not coined in the 1990s (e.g., Barkow et al., 1992), but
was already in use in the late 19th and early 20th century. See for example Stanley (1895), Howard (1927), and
Jastrow (1927). For a historical overview see Gillette (2007).
20
show is that it is wrong: that there isn’t the tiniest shred of evidence that these
fantasies of servitude and childish dependence have anything to do with
women’s true potential; that the idea of the nature of human possibility which
rests on the accidents of individual development or genitalia, on what is
possible today because of what happened yesterday, on the fundamentalist
myth of sex organ causality, has strangled and deflected psychology so that it
is relatively useless in describing, explaining, or predicting humans and their
behavior. […]
[T]he evidence is collecting that what a person does, and who he believes
himself to be, will in general be a function of what people around him expect
him to be, and what the overall situation in which he is acting implies that he
is. Compared to the influence of the social context within which a person
lives, his or her history and “traits”, as well as biological makeup, may simply
be random variations, “noise” superimposed on the true signal which can
predict behavior.
[…] If subjects under quite innocuous and non-coercive social conditions can
be made to kill other subjects and other types of social conditions will
positively refuse to do so; if subjects can react to a state of physiological fear
by becoming euphoric because there is somebody else round who is euphoric
or angry because there is somebody else round who is angry; if students
become intelligent because teachers expect them to be intelligent, and rats run
mazes better because experimenters are told the rats are bright, then it is
obvious that a study of human behavior requires, first and foremost, a study of
the social contexts within which people move, the expectations as to how they
will behave, and the authority which tells them who they are and what they
are supposed to do. […]
Thus, for example, if out of two individuals diagnosed as having the
adrenogenital syndrome of female hermaphroditism, one is raised as a girl and
one as a boy, each will act and identify her/himself accordingly. The one
raised as a girl will consider herself a girl; the one raised as a boy will
consider himself a boy; and each will conduct her/himself successfully in
accord with that self-definition.
So, identical behavior occurs given different physiological states; and
different behavior occurs given an identical physiological starting point. So it
is not clear that differences in sex hormones are at all relevant to behavior.
[…]
But even for the limited function that primate arguments serve, the evidence
has been misused. Invariably, only those primates have been cited which
exhibit exactly the kind of behavior that the proponents of the biological basis
of human female behavior wish were true for humans. Thus, baboons and
rhesus monkeys are generally cited: males in these groups exhibit some of the
most irritable and aggressive behavior found in primates, and if one wishes to
argue that females are naturally passive and submissive, these groups provide
vivid examples. […] [I]n general, a counter-example can be found for every
sex-role behavior cited, including, as mentioned in the case of marmosets,
male “mothering” (Weisstein, 1971).
21
Thus, the feminist psychology of the Seventies recovered the classic themes of the earlier
decades (often without knowing; see Shields, 1975), but took them much further in a social
constructionist direction (see also Eagly, 2018; Eagly & Wood, 2013). The variability hypothesis
was seen as permanently discredited, and often brought up as an example of old-fashioned sexist
pseudoscience (e.g., Shields, 1975; Seller, 1981; Unger, 1979). The concept of gender
crystallized this attitude; to some scholars, it pointed to the socially constructed reality of
biological sex and the male-female binary:
Scientific knowledge does not inform the answer to the question: what makes
a person either a female or a male, a woman or a man? Rather, scientific
knowledge justifies, appears to give grounds for, and reflexively demonstrates
the already existing knowledge that a person is either a female or a male.
Biological, psychological and sociological differences do not lead to two non-
overlapping categories of people. Rather, the socially shared, common sense,
methodical construction of a world of two and only two genders leads to the
discovery of biological, psychological and sociological differences.
[…] Although it seems that the biological facts have an existence independent
of gender labels (there are XY chromosomes, etc. and all these together are
labeled “male”), the process, seen through the ethnomethodological approach,
is the reverse. […]
The role that biology plays in gender attribution is to provide “signs”, signs
which serve as good reasons for our attributions. […] In our culture,
biological facts give grounds for, and support, the facticity of two genders. At
the same time, biology is grounded in, and gets its support from, the basic
assumption that there are two, and only two, genders (McKenna, 1978, pp. 3-
8).
But these radical ideas were ahead of their time, and did not leave an enduring impression
on the discipline. Another flare was Sandra Bem’s work on androgyny and psychological
adjustment (Bem, 1974, 1975), which proved an empirical dead end and was soon attacked for
being insidiously sexist and male-centric (see Lippa, 2001). On the other hand, Bem’s argument
that masculinity and femininity are not the ends of a continuum, but rather independent
dimensions of behavior made a lasting contribution to the deconstruction of gender (see also
Constantinople, 1973). Also, from the ashes of androgyny rose gender schema theory (Bem,
1981), which is still a mainstream approach to the development of gender and gender identity
(see Blakemore et al., 2009; Liben, 2016).
In terms of staying power, the landmark contribution of this period was probably
Maccoby and Jacklin’s hugely influential book The psychology of sex differences (1974). The
authors collected and analyzed a large number of studies, and concluded that only four
differences could be regarded as well established, namely: males are more aggressive; females
excel in verbal ability; males excel in visuospatial ability; and males have superior mathematical
skills. They noted that the evidence was equivocal for sex differences in tactile sensitivity, fear
and anxiety, activity levels, competitiveness, dominance, compliance, and nurturant/“maternal”
behaviors; but dismissed sex differences in sociability, suggestibility, self-esteem, and a host of
22
other traits as “unfounded beliefs”. Also, they failed to find consistent evidence of differential
socialization in boys and girls, although this particular conclusion is often glossed over.
Maccoby and Jacklin’s book cemented the perception that, with very few exceptions,
laypeople’s ideas about male and female behavior are just groundless stereotypes:
How is it possible that people continue to believe, for example, that girls are
more "social" than boys, when careful observation and measurement in a
variety of situations show no sex difference? Of course it is possible that we
have not studied those particular situations that contribute most to the popular
beliefs. But if this is the problem it means that the alleged sex difference
exists only in a limited range of situations and the sweeping generalizations
embodied in popular beliefs are not warranted. […] A more likely explanation
for the perpetuation of “myths” we believe, is the fact that stereotypes are
such powerful things (Maccoby & Jacklin, 1974, p. 355).
The psychology of sex differences has been canonized as a careful, rigorous, even-handed
analysis of the literature of the time. In reality, it was a biased and surprisingly shoddy piece of
work. The authors failed to analyze many studies finding significant differences, even though
they had cited them in the bibliography; overinterpreted non-significant tests as evidence of no
difference, without taking into account statistical power and measurement reliability; largely
based their conclusions on studies of young children (12 years old or younger in 75% of the
studies); and dismissed several patterns indicative of sex differences with ad-hoc reasons. Block
(1976) discussed these problems in detail and reanalyzed Maccoby and Jacklin’s main findings,
reaching dramatically different conclusions. This did not prevent the book from becoming a
classic that is still cited to this day, often uncritically.
Where Are We? When Are We?
Almost fifty years and two waves of feminism later, what is the state of the field?
Evolutionary psychology is hopefully here to stay; but despite some attempts at reconciliation
(e.g., Buss & Schmitt, 2011; Campbell, 2006; Nicolas & Welling, 2015) and the contributions of
scholars with a distinct feminist perspective (e.g., Fisher et al., 2013; Hrdy, 2009), it continues to
attract harsh criticism by feminists outside the field (e.g., Barnett & Rivers, 2004; Fausto-
Sterling, 1992, 2000; Fine, 2017; McCaughey, 2007; Saini, 2017). A coherent evolutionary
approach challenges every single one of the preferences that inform the psychology of sex and
gender, so there is no resolution in sight. Social role theory is a false compromise, and while I
suspect that it will remain popular for some time, it cannot provide the needed common ground
(see also Geary, 2021). Like a hundred years ago, sexual selection is the main target of feminist
critiques, not just in psychology (e.g., Fine, 2017; Tavris, 1992) but also in anthropology and
biology (e.g., Dunsworth, 2020; Fausto-Sterling, 1992; Roughgarden, 2013; see Hankinson
Nelson, 2017). Since the basic logic of sexual selection seems to be essentially correct, but most
feminists cannot bring themselves to accept it (Vandermassen, 2004), the debate does not
advance and it’s déjà vu all over again.
23
In the meantime, the variability hypothesis—a “pernicious hypothesis” for Noddings
(1992), a “social Darwinist myth” for Denmark et al. (2008)—has been largely confirmed across
species (Reinhold & Engqvist, 2013; Wyman & Rowe, 2014). In humans, larger samples and
better analytical techniques have shown that males are systematically more variable than
females, both in general intelligence (indexed by IQ) and in most specific cognitive skills (e.g.,
Arden & Plomin, 2006; Baye & Monseur, 2016; Feingold, 1992; He & Wong, 2011; Johnson et
al., 2008; Lohman & Lakin, 2009; Machin & Pekkarinen, 2008). The same applies to many
physical and physiological traits (Lehre et al., 2009). In the domain of personality, men’s scores
also tend to be somewhat more variable; the main exception is neuroticism/emotional stability,
which shows significantly higher variability in women (see Del Giudice, 2015, 2020; Del
Giudice et al., 2018b). Empirical confirmation has not made the hypothesis less incendiary,
however. Both Larry Summers (former President of Harvard; see Taylor, 2005) and James
Damore (see Anomaly & Winegard, 2019) were ostracized for mentioning greater male
variability, among other things; in 2017, a mathematical paper that discussed the logic of the
hypothesis (Hill, 2017) was immediately “un-published” after controversy erupted (see Hill,
2018). As I noted earlier, it is still quite possible to publish in top psychology journals without
acknowledging the evidence of higher male variability in intellectual abilities.
In psychology, the landmark work of the 2000s was surely Janet Hyde’s (2005) paper on
the gender similarities hypothesis, or the hypothesis that “‘males and females are similar on
most, but not all, psychological variables. That is, men and women, as well as boys and girls, are
more alike than they are different.” (Hyde, 2005, p. 581). This had also been the message of
Maccoby and Jacklin’s book, so what was new? First, Hyde relied on data from large meta-
analyses instead of individual studies. And second, she used conventional thresholds to sort sex
differences into “trivial”, “small”, “moderate”, and “large”.
On the positive side, the paper highlighted the importance of quantification, and
demonstrated the potential of integrating data on a large scale. But the idea of interpreting sex
differences automatically and out of context, based on meaningless conventional thresholds, was
deeply unfortunate (for extended discussion of why this is the case, see Del Giudice, 2020; Hill
et al., 2008). In all likelihood, the paper’s visibility has contributed to entrench this mechanical
practice even deeper in the literature (e.g., Zell et al., 2015); to illustrate, three of the meta-
analyses I surveyed for this chapter interpreted their findings based on the same thresholds
(Kugler et al., 2018; Lauer et al., 2019; Reilly et al., 2019). Other limitations of Hyde’s approach
include averaging functionally distinct traits within the same category, neglecting measurement
error, and failing to consider that differences can cumulate across traits yielding large
multivariate distances between male and female profiles (see Del Giudice, 2020; Del Giudice et
al., 2012). Be as it may, the conclusion that most sex differences are trivial to small struck a
chord, and the paper has become a standard reference in the literature on gender stereotypes
(e.g., Ellemers, 2018).
As an aside, Hyde (2005, 2014) recognized that trait variability is often higher in males,
even though she downplayed the practical significance of this finding and emphasized the
context-dependence of sex differences. In Hyde’s view, it is not only laypeople who are victim
of inflated stereotypes, but also scientists—and they should stop caring so much:
24
When researchers find a gender difference, they might productively ask
themselves, is this important, and why is it important? Are other issues more
important?
Nonetheless, research on psychological gender differences will continue for
years to come, given many scientists’ firm beliefs that such differences exist
and are large and the media’s insatiable thirst for new findings of gender
differences (Hyde, 2014, p. 3.21).
This attitude toward sex differences in fairly common in the psychological literature. The
underlying assumption is that “stereotypes” of large and/or stable sex differences are harmful,
both to individuals and society at large (e.g., Barnett & Rivers, 2004; Ellemers, 2018; Gruber et
al., 2020; Hyde, 2005, 2014). For example:
It is time to consider the costs of overinflated claims of gender differences.
Arguably, they cause harm in numerous realms, including women’s
opportunities in the workplace, couple conflict and communication, and
analyses of self-esteem problems among adolescents (Hyde, 2005, p. 590).
I do not dispute that exaggerating sex differences, and depicting them as overly rigid and
inflexible, can cause all sorts of problems. But the converse is also obviously true: if there are
some meaningful and robust sex differences, minimizing or denying them can be just as
harmful—for example by distorting people’s understanding of themselves and others, hindering
communication between partners and on the workplace, reducing the effectiveness of
psychotherapy, and encouraging the adoption of unrealistic or counterproductive policies. The
virtually complete neglect of these potential risks—in the face of constant alarm about the
dangers of exaggerated stereotypes—is one of the clearest manifestations of ideological bias in
this area of research.
The other major theme I have discussed is the deconstruction of gender and sex. Starting
from the 1990s, the idea that masculinity and femininity are independent dimensions of variation
has been challenged by research showing that, even if M-F is not a simple unitary construct, it is
possible to derive robust and meaningful M-F dimensions from patterns of interest and
personality (see Lippa, 2001, 2010; Del Giudice, 2020). The more radical project of disrupting
the “sex binary” started in the 1970s and was still underway in the 1990s (e.g., Fausto-Sterling,
1993), but did not start to get serious traction until the mid-2010s, when it merged with fourth-
wave feminism and transgender activism. It is still too early to know how psychology will be
impacted, but I suspect that future (re)incarnations of this chapter will have an interesting story
to tell.
The Other Side of Bias
Before ending this exploration, it is important to consider the possible influence of other
kinds of ideology besides feminism and egalitarianism. The polar opposite of cosmic
egalitarianism is anti-egalitarianism—the belief that groups are naturally unequal, with
“superior” groups that deserve to win and dominate, and “inferior” ones that deserve to lose and
be dominated. Psychologically, this perspective aligns with the trait known as social dominance
25
orientation (SDO; see Pratto et al., 1994). I’m not sure if I have ever talked to a single
psychologist who held such an anti-egalitarian worldview. On the other hand, plenty of
psychologists do not subscribe to cosmic egalitarianism and believe that there are robust—
though not necessarily fixed—differences between males and females, which are rooted in our
evolutionary history and not primarily caused by socialization. In the feminist literature, this is
called “gender essentialism” and viewed as a set of defensive beliefs whose function is to resist
social change, foster acceptance of (socially constructed) sex differences, and legitimize the
status quo (e.g., Morton et al., 2009; Skewes et al., 2018; Wood & Eagly, 2012).
Naturally, the notion that the status quo is by definition unjust and in need of radical
transformation is debatable—unless, of course, one is already an activist. And if one takes an
activist perspective, the only real explanation for disagreement becomes ideological opposition,
with the result that legitimate scientific debates get routinely recast as ideological ones.
Reflecting on the influence of feminism in psychology, Eagly (2018) remarked that “ideology is
the most difficult of biases to erase because its advocates seldom recognize or acknowledge it”
(p. 12). To me, this seems disingenuous: throughout history, feminist scholars have openly
acknowledged their ideological motivations and often embraced them with pride.
25
The
ideological roots of feminist research are anything but hidden or implicit; the notion that “we are
all ideologically biased” has a kernel of truth, but should not be used to suggest false
equivalences between approaches that strive to minimize bias and those that seek to amplify it
(see Tybur & Navarrete, 2018).
That said, the empirical data do indicate that “gender essentialist” beliefs tend to correlate
with more conservative politics and higher SDO in the general population (Skewes et al., 2018).
Also, perceiving larger differences between the sexes predicts stronger endorsement of so-called
“sexist” beliefs (Zell et al., 2016)—although the latter mainly consist of being critical of
feminism, attributing certain positive/negative qualities to women (e.g., good taste, being easily
offended), and expressing protectiveness or romantic admiration.
26
The assumption that
“essentialist” ideas about sex differences point to a hidden conservative agenda may explain why
25
To give just one example, Else-Quest and Hyde (2018) advocate a feminist approach to psychology, and clearly
note that “[f]eminism is a political movement and ideology as well as a theoretical perspective” (p. 7).
26
In fact, the questionnaire that is commonly used to measure sexism (the “ambivalent sexism inventory”; Glick &
Fiske, 1996) is a textbook example of blatant ideological bias in psychology. Here are some sample items indicating
“benevolent sexism”:
- In a disaster, women ought not necessarily to be rescued before men (reverse-scored).
- Women, as compared to men, tend to have a more refined sense of culture and good taste.
- Women, compared to men, tend to have a superior moral sensibility.
- No matter how accomplished he is, a man is not truly complete as a person unless he has the love of a
woman.
And some examples of “hostile sexism”:
- Feminists are making entirely reasonable demands of men (reverse-scored).
- Many women are actually seeking special favors, such as hiring policies that favor them over men, under
the guise of asking for “equality.”
- Women are too easily offended.
- Most women interpret innocent remarks or acts as being sexist.
The last item is especially ironic, considering that the questionnaire is full of arguably innocent remarks that are
interpreted as indicators of sexism.
26
academics who are more liberal (in the sense of left-wing) tend to view evolutionary psychology
with more skepticism (Buss & von Hippel, 2018, Jonason & Schmitt, 2016; see also Tybur &
Navarrete, 2018). As it turns out, however, evolutionary psychologists and anthropologists are
just as left-wing as their non-evolutionary colleagues (Lyle & Smith, 2012; Tybur et al., 2007).
27
Almost all my colleagues who study sex differences from a biological perspective are politically
liberal, and in favor of equalizing opportunities and conditions between the sexes as much as
possible. This does not mean that subtle biases and distortions cannot happen; but the suspicion
that evolutionary psychologists as a group are motivated by right-wing or anti-egalitarian
concerns has no basis in reality.
More generally, the traditions and theoretical commitments of a field can easily create
biases that, even if not “ideological” in a strong sense, end up distorting the science produced
within that field. For example, the evidence for “human universals” has played a crucial role in
lending credibility to evolutionary psychology (see Pinker, 2003). Even if cross-cultural
variation is a major topic of research (e.g., Chapais, 2017; Gangestad et al., 2006; Schmitt, 2015;
Schmitt et al., 2017), the field as a whole may be unduly biased in favor of constancy and
universality, at the risk of discounting change and variability. On the issue of sex and gender,
bias can take the form of exaggerating sex differences, downplaying the flexibility of sex roles in
humans and other animals, and focusing too much on women’s attractiveness and mating while
neglecting parenting and post-reproductive behavior (see e.g., Burch, 2020; Eagly & Wood,
2013; Fischer et al., 2013; Stewart-Williams & Thomas, 2013). While the sex binary (properly
understood) is not a myth to dispel but a fundamental biological reality, it is true that differences
and variation in gender identity have not received the attention they deserve from evolutionists. I
also think that evolutionary psychologists could do a better job of communicating the nuance of
their theories and findings to the public, for example by putting more emphasis on within-sex
variation and context-dependence. As usual, the best antidote to bias is open conversation (see
Del Giudice et al., 2018a; Fine et al., 2018; Fine, 2020; von Hippel et al., 2020). The worst
aspect of pervasive ideology is the way in which it suppresses dialogue, and ensures that some
ideas will not be heard and discussed.
Conclusion: What’s Next?
This is the point in the chapter where one looks at the future to offer suggestions and
advice. I am writing this chapter at the end of 2020, as political/ideological tensions in the USA
and other Western countries are reaching a peak of intensity. This may be just about the worst
possible time to make predictions; but some trends seem reasonably clear, and do not make me
optimistic in the short run. At least for a while, egalitarian and anti-biological biases in
psychology are going to get stronger, making universities and academic journals more hostile
toward the “wrong” kind of research. Anecdotes from colleagues and in the news suggest that
academic censorship is tightening, both before publication (ethical reviews, journal reviews,
editorial decisions) and after (retraction campaigns; e.g., Reynolds, 2020). Even teaching about
certain sex differences is becoming difficult or impossible; the speech codes of many universities
27
To be clear, I do not think this is necessarily a good thing. While evolutionary psychology may be quite effective
at limiting the impact of researchers’ ideological biases (thanks to the “buffering” effect of strong theory; Tybur &
Navarrete, 2018), more political diversity would almost certainly benefit the field, and add another layer of
protection against conformity and groupthink.
27
now proscribe “gender harassment”, an ill-defined concept that can be expanded to include any
form of unwelcome “stereotyping” (e.g., Leskinen et al., 2014). On the positive side, researchers
have the option to reach the broader public through online videos, podcasts, blogs, and
magazines, effectively creating a sort of academic counterculture. While this is not ideal (and
online channels are also vulnerable to censorship), it may help the field survive a spell of
ideological suppression. Another reason for hope is that large, information-rich datasets (often
from multiple countries) are becoming increasingly common and easy to access. In this sense,
there has never been a better time to study sex differences and similarities; even in a worsening
ideological climate, I expect to see a lot of exciting new research—both by academics and by
independent researchers.
Is there anything that can be done right now to mitigate bias? As I noted earlier,
conversations across scientific/ideological barriers are extremely important and should be
encouraged whenever possible. Recently, noted feminist psychologist Alice Eagly argued that
her colleagues should break with a tradition of diffidence, and start considering how biological
influences contribute to shape behavior in males and females (Eagly, 2018). Unfortunately,
mainstream feminism is moving fast in the opposite direction; also, some of the issues at stake
(e.g., the role of sexual selection) have been contentious for more than a century—a fact that
does not inspire hope for a resolution (Vandermassen, 2020). On the other hand, it is possible
that more scholars will become frustrated with the growing polarization in their field, and begin
to seek dialogue with “moderates” on the other side of these issues. Facilitating these exchanges
should become a priority for non-partisan organizations, societies, and journals.
After spending some time on textbooks, I believe there are many untapped opportunities
to combat bias at the level of introductory courses. A slanted introduction to the field—one that
ignores or downplays sex differences, and fails to provide the conceptual tools to make sense of
them—can leave a lasting impression that is hard to correct later on (if it gets corrected at all).
One option for sex differences researchers is to contact the authors of popular textbooks to offer
feedback, advice, and links to useful teaching materials (e.g., videos, interviews, exchanges
between researchers with different viewpoints). Another option would be to produce brief
“supplements”, written in a textbook style and designed to balance out the standard narrative that
students are likely to encounter. Supplements of this kind could be easily made available online,
and disseminated via social media and other channels (the same approach might work for other
topics covered in this volume). There are probably many other ways to improve the curriculum
and give students a fuller picture of the field, while avoiding the pressures and compromises
faced by textbooks authors and course instructors.
As I have stressed through the chapter, ideological biases in the psychology of sex and
gender are deeply entrenched, and as old as the discipline itself. Whatever happens in the next
years, quick and simple fixes are not going to work; making real progress will require courage,
patience, focused effort—and all the creativity we can muster.
Acknowledgments
Warm thanks to Romina Angeleri, Mike Bailey, David Geary, and Richard Lippa for
their helpful and constructive comments.
28
References
Ainsworth, C. (2015). Sex redefined. Nature, 518, 288-291. https://doi.org/10.1038/518288a
Alexander, G. M., & Hines, M. (2002). Sex differences in response to children's toys in nonhuman primates
(Cercopithecus aethiops sabaeus). Evolution and Human Behavior, 23, 467-479.
https://doi.org/10.1016/S1090-5138(02)00107-1
Allen, C. N. (1927). Studies in sex differences. Psychological Bulletin, 24, 294–304.
https://doi.org/10.1037/h0074974
Allen, C. N. (1930). Recent studies in sex differences. Psychological Bulletin, 27, 394–407.
https://doi.org/10.1037/h0070355
American Psychological Association (2019). Publication manual (7th ed.). American Psychological Association.
Ankney, C. D. (1992). Sex differences in relative brain size: The mismeasure of woman, too? Intelligence, 16, 329-
336. https://doi.org/10.1016/0160-2896(92)90013-H
Anomaly, J., & Winegard, B. (2020). The egalitarian fallacy: Are group differences compatible with political
liberalism? Philosophia, 48, 433-444. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-019-00129-w
Archer, J. (2019). The reality and evolutionary significance of human psychological sex differences. Biological
Reviews, 94, 1381-1415. https://doi.org/10.1111/brv.12507
Arden, R., & Plomin, R. (2006). Sex differences in variance of intelligence across childhood. Personality and
Individual Differences, 41, 39–48. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.paid.2005.11.027
Asperholm, M., Högman, N., Rafi, J., & Herlitz, A. (2019). What did you do yesterday? A meta-analysis of sex
differences in episodic memory. Psychological Bulletin, 145, 785–821. https://doi.org/10.1037/bul0000197
Barkow, J. H., Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (Eds.). (1992). The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the
generation of culture. Oxford University Press.
Barnett, R., & Rivers, C. (2004). Same difference: How gender myths are hurting our relationships, our children,
and our jobs. Basic Books.
Baye, A., & Monseur, C. (2016). Gender differences in variability and extreme scores in an international context.
Large-scale Assessments in Education, 4, 1. https://doi.org/10.1186/s40536-015-0015-x
Bem, S. L. (1974). The measurement of psychological androgyny. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology,
42, 155–162. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0036215
Bem, S. L. (1975). Sex role adaptability: One consequence of psychological androgyny. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 31, 634–643. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0077098
Bem, S. L. (1981). Gender schema theory: A cognitive account of sex typing. Psychological Review, 88, 354–364.
https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-295X.88.4.354
Benenson, J. F. (2019). Sex differences in human peer relationships: A primate’s-eye view. Current Directions in
Psychological Science, 28, 124-130. https://doi.org/10.1177/0963721418812768
Bentley, M. (1945). Sanity and hazard in childhood. American Journal of Psychology, 58, 212–246.
https://doi.org/10.2307/1417846
Bian, L., Leslie, S. J., & Cimpian, A. (2018). Evidence of bias against girls and women in contexts that emphasize
intellectual ability. American Psychologist, 73, 1139-1153. https://doi.org/10.1037/amp0000427
Blackless, M., Charuvastra, A., Derryck, A., Fausto-Sterling, A., Lauzanne, K., & Lee, E. (2000). How sexually
dimorphic are we? Review and synthesis. American Journal of Human Biology, 12, 151-166.
https://doi.org/10.1002/ajhb.10122
Blakemore, J. E. O., Berenbaum, S. A., & Liben, L. S. (2009). Gender development. Psychology Press.
Block, J. H. (1976). issues, problems, and pitfalls in assessing sex differences: a critical review of “the psychology
of sex differences”. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly of Behavior and Development, 22, 283-308.
https://www.jstor.org/stable/23084065
Brown, C. S., Jewell, J. A., & Tam, J. M. (2020). Gender. In Noba Project (2020). Discover psychology 2.0 – A brief
introductory text (pp. 97-111). Noba.
29
Burch, R. L. (2020). More than just a pretty face: The overlooked contributions of women in evolutionary
psychology textbooks. Evolutionary Behavioral Sciences, 14, 100–114. https://doi.org/10.1037/ebs0000166
Burton, L. J., Westen, D., & Kowalski, R. M. (2019). Psychology (5th Australian and New Zealand ed.). Wiley.
Buss, D. M. (Ed.) (2015). The handbook of evolutionary psychology (2nd ed.). Wiley.
Buss, D. M. (2018). Sexual and emotional infidelity: Evolved gender differences in jealousy prove robust and
replicable. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 13, 155-160.
https://doi.org/10.1177/1745691617698225
Buss, D. M. (2020). Evolutionary theories in psychology. In Noba Project (2020). Discover psychology 2.0 – A brief
introductory text (pp. 69-83). Noba.
Buss, D. M., & Schmitt, D. P. (2011). Evolutionary psychology and feminism. Sex Roles, 64, 768.
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11199-011-9987-3
Buss, D. M., & von Hippel, W. (2018). Psychological barriers to evolutionary psychology: Ideological bias and
coalitional adaptations. Archives of Scientific Psychology, 6, 148-158. https://doi.org/10.1037/arc0000049
Campbell, A. (2006). Feminism and evolutionary psychology. In J. H. Barkow (Ed.), Missing the revolution:
Darwinism for social scientists (pp. 63-99). Oxford University Press.
Carlson, E. R., & Carlson, R. (1960). Male and female subjects in personality research. Journal of Abnormal and
Social Psychology, 61, 482–483. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0048389
Cashdan, E., & Gaulin, S. J. (2016). Why go there? Evolution of mobility and spatial cognition in women and men.
Human Nature, 27, 1-15. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12110-015-9253-4
Chapais, B. (2017). Psychological adaptations and the production of culturally polymorphic social universals.
Evolutionary Behavioral Sciences, 11, 63–82. https://doi.org/10.1037/ebs0000079
Cretella, M. A., Rosik, C. H., & Howsepian, A. A. (2019). Sex and gender are distinct variables critical to health:
Comment on Hyde, Bigler, Joel, Tate, and van Anders (2019). American Psychologist, 74, 842–844.
https://doi.org/10.1037/amp0000524
Damore, J. (2017). Google’s ideological Echo chamber.
https://assets.documentcloud.org/documents/3914586/Googles-Ideological-Echo-Chamber.pdf (Accessed
6 November 2020).
Darwin, C. (1871). The descent of man, and selection in relation to sex. John Murray.
Deaux, K. (1985). Sex and gender. Annual Review of Psychology, 36, 49-81.
https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.ps.36.020185.000405
Del Giudice, M. (2012). The twentieth century reversal of pink-blue gender coding: A scientific urban legend?
Archives of Sexual Behavior, 41, 1321-1323. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10508-012-0002-z
Del Giudice, M. (2015). Gender differences in personality and social behavior. In J. D. Wright (Ed.), International
encyclopedia of the social and behavioral sciences (2nd ed.) (pp. 750-756). New York: Elsevier.
Del Giudice, M. (2017). Pink, blue, and gender: An update. Archives of Sexual Behavior, 46, 1555-1563.
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10508-017-1024-3
Del Giudice, M. (2020). Measuring sex differences and similarities. In D. P. VanderLaan & W. I. Wong (Eds.),
Gender and sexuality development: Contemporary theory and research. Springer.
Del Giudice, M., Barrett, E. S., Belsky, J., Hartman, S., Martel, M. M., Sangenstedt, S., & Kuzawa, C. W. (2018b).
Individual differences in developmental plasticity: A role for early androgens? Psychoneuroendocrinology,
90, 165-173. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.psyneuen.2018.02.025
Del Giudice, M., Booth, T., & Irwing, P. (2012). The distance between Mars and Venus: Measuring global sex
differences in personality. PLoS ONE, 7, e29265. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0029265
Del Giudice, M., Puts, D. A., Geary, D. C., & Schmitt, D. P. (2018a). Sex differences in brain and behavior: Eight
counterpoints. Psychology Today, https://www.psychologytoday.com/us/blog/sexual-
personalities/201904/sex-differences-in-brain-and-behavior-eight-counterpoints
Demnark, F.L., Klara, M., Baron, E., & Cambareri-Fernandez, L. (2008). Historical development of the psychology
of women. In F. L. Denmark & M. A. Paludi (Eds.), Psychology of women: A handbook of issues and
theories (2nd ed.) (pp. 3-39). Praeger.
30
Dunsworth, H. M. (2020). Expanding the evolutionary explanations for sex differences in the human skeleton.
Evolutionary Anthropology, https://doi.org/10.1002/evan.21834
Eagly, A. H. (2018). The shaping of science by ideology: How feminism inspired, led, and constrained scientific
understanding of sex and gender. Journal of Social Issues, 74, 871-888. https://doi.org/10.1111/josi.12291
Eagly, A. H., Nater, C., Miller, D. I., Kaufmann, M., & Sczesny, S. (2020). Gender stereotypes have changed: A
cross-temporal meta-analysis of US public opinion polls from 1946 to 2018. American Psychologist, 75,
301-315. https://doi.org/10.1037/amp0000494
Eagly, A.H. and Wood, W. (1999) The origins of sex differences in human behavior: Evolved dispositions versus
social roles. American Psychologist, 54, 408–423. https://doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.54.6.408
Eagly, A. H., & Wood, W. (2012). Social role theory. In P. van Lange, A. Kruglanski, & E. T. Higgins (Eds.),
Handbook of theories in social psychology (pp. 458–476). Sage.
http://dx.doi.org/10.4135/9781446249222.n49
Eagly, A. H., & Wood, W. (2013). The nature–nurture debates: 25 years of challenges in understanding the
psychology of gender. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8, 340-357.
https://doi.org/10.1177/1745691613484767
Eagly, A. H., & Wood, W. (2016). Social role theory of sex differences. In N. A. Naples (Ed.), The Wiley-Blackwell
encyclopedia of gender and sexuality studies. Wiley. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781118663219.wbegss183
Ellemers, N. (2018). Gender stereotypes. Annual Review of Psychology, 69, 275-298.
https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-psych-122216-011719
Ellis, H. (1894). Man and Woman: A study of human secondary sexual characters. Scribner.
Ellis, L., Hershberger, S., Field, E., Wersinger, S., Pellis, S., Geary, D., … & Karadi, K. (2008). Sex differences:
Summarizing more than a century of scientific research. New York: Psychology Press.
Else-Quest, N. M., & Hyde, J. S. (Eds.) (2018). The psychology of women and gender: Half the human experience
(9th ed.). Sage.
Falk, A., & Hermle, J. (2018). Relationship of gender differences in preferences to economic development and
gender equality. Science, 362, eaas9899. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.aas9899
Fausto-Sterling, A. (1992). Myths of gender: Biological theories about women and men (2nd ed.) Basic Books.
Fausto-Sterling, A. (1993). The five sexes: Why male and female are not enough. The Sciences, 33, 20-24.
https://doi.org/10.1002/j.2326-1951.1993.tb03081.x
Fausto-Sterling, A. (2000). Beyond difference: Feminism and evolutionary biology. In H. Rose & S. Rose (Eds.),
Alas, poor Darwin: Arguments against evolutionary psychology. Jonathan Cape.
Fausto-Sterling, A. (2012). Sex/gender: Biology in a social world. New York: Routledge.
Feingold, A. (1992). Sex differences in variability in intellectual abilities: A new look at an old controversy. Review
of Educational Research, 62, 61-84. https://doi.org/10.3102/00346543062001061
Ferguson, C. J., Brown, J. M., & Torres, A. V. (2018). Education or indoctrination? The accuracy of introductory
psychology textbooks in covering controversial topics and urban legends about psychology. Current
Psychology, 37, 574-582. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12144-016-9539-7
Fernberger, S. W. (1948). Persistence of stereotypes concerning sex differences. Journal of Abnormal and Social
Psychology, 43, 97–101. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0059904
Fine, C. (2017). Testosterone rex: unmaking the myths of our gendered minds. Norton.
Fine, C. (2020). Constructing unnecessary barriers to constructive scientific debate: A response to Buss and von
Hippel (2018). Archives of Scientific Psychology, 8, 5-10. https://doi.org/10.1037/arc0000070
Fine, C., Joel, D., & Rippon, G. (2018). Responding to ideas on sex differences in brain and behavior. Psychology
Today, https://www.psychologytoday.com/us/blog/sexual-personalities/201907/responding-ideas-sex-
differences-in-brain-and-behavior
Fisher, M. L., Garcia, J. R., & Sokol-Chang, R. (Eds.). (2013). Evolution’s empress: Darwinian perspectives on the
nature of women. Oxford University Press.
Fisher, R. A. (1930). The genetical theory of natural selection. Clarendon Press.
Friedman, B. X., Bleske, A. L., & Scheyd, G. J. (2000). Incompatible with evolutionary theorizing. American
Psychologist, 55, 1059–1060. https://doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.55.9.1059
31
Gangestad, S. W., Haselton, M. G., & Buss, D. M. (2006). Evolutionary foundations of cultural variation: Evoked
culture and mate preferences. Psychological Inquiry, 17, 75-95.
https://doi.org/10.1207/s15327965pli1702_1
Geary, D. C. (2018). Efficiency of mitochondrial functioning as the fundamental biological mechanism of general
intelligence (g). Psychological Review, 125, 1028–1050. https://doi.org/10.1037/rev0000124
Geary, D. C. (2021). Male, female: The evolution of human sex differences (3rd ed.). American Psychological
Association.
Geddes, P., & Thomson, J. A. (1889). The evolution of sex. Walter Scott.
Gillette, A. (2007). Eugenics and the nature-nurture debate in the twentieth century. Palgrave Macmillan.
Glick, P., & Fiske, S. T. (1996). The Ambivalent Sexism Inventory: Differentiating hostile and benevolent sexism.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 70, 491–512. https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.70.3.491
Grison, S., & Gazzaniga, M. (2019). Psychology in your life (3rd ed.). Norton.
Gross, P. A. (1998). Bashful eggs, macho sperm, and Tonypandy. In N. Koertge (Ed.), A house built on sand:
Exposing postmodernist myths about science (pp. ). Oxford University Press.
Gruber, J., Mendle, J., Lindquist, K. A., Schmader, T., Clark, L. A., Bliss-Moreau, E., ... & Borelli, J. L. (2020). The
future of women in psychological science. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 1745691620952789.
https://doi.org/10.1177%2F1745691620952789
Haig, D. (2004). The inexorable rise of gender and the decline of sex: Social change in academic titles, 1945–2001.
Archives of Sexual Behavior, 33, 87-96. https://doi.org/10.1023/B:ASEB.0000014323.56281.0d
Hall, G. S. (1906). Youth: Its education, regimen, and hygiene. Appleton.
Hankinson Nelson, L. (2017). Biology and feminism: A philosophical introduction. Cambridge University Press.
Hartung, C. M., & Lefler, E. K. (2019). Sex and gender in psychopathology: DSM–5 and beyond. Psychological
Bulletin, 145, 390–409. https://doi.org/10.1037/bul0000183
Haselton, M. G. (2003). The sexual overperception bias: Evidence of a systematic bias in men from a survey of
naturally occurring events. Journal of Research in Personality, 37, 34–47. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0092-
6566(02)00529-9
Haselton, M. G., Nettle, D., & Murray, D. (2016). The evolution of cognitive bias. In D. M. Buss (Ed.), The
handbook of evolutionary psychology (2nd ed., pp. 968–987). Wiley.
Hassett, J. M., Siebert, E. R., & Wallen, K. (2008). Sex differences in rhesus monkey toy preferences parallel those
of children. Hormones and Behavior, 54, 359-364. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.yhbeh.2008.03.008
He, W. J., & Wong, W. C. (2011). Gender differences in creative thinking revisited: Findings from analysis of
variability. Personality and Individual Differences, 51, 807-811. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.paid.2011.06.027
Helgeson, V. S. (2016). Psychology of gender (5th ed.). New York: Routledge.
Hill, T. P. (2017). An elementary mathematical theory for the variability hypothesis. New York Journal of
Mathematics, 23, 1641-1655.
Hill, T. P. (2018). Academic activists send a published paper down the memory hole. Quillette.
https://quillette.com/2018/09/07/academic-activists-send-a-published-paper-down-the-memory-hole/ 3
Hoff Sommers, C. (2009). Persistent myths in feminist scholarship. The Chronicle of Higher Education, June 29,
2009. https://www.chronicle.com/article/persistent-myths-in-feminist-scholarship/
Hollingworth, L. S. (1914). Variability as related to sex differences in achievement: A critique. American Journal of
Sociology, 19, 510-530. https://www.jstor.org/stable/2762962
Hollingworth, L. S. (1916). Sex differences in mental traits. Psychological Bulletin, 13, 377–384.
https://doi.org/10.1037/h0072261
Hollingworth, L. S. (1918). Comparison of the sexes in mental traits. Psychological Bulletin, 15, 427–432.
https://doi.org/10.1037/h0075023
Hollingworth, L. S. (1919). Comparison of the sexes in mental traits. Psychological Bulletin, 16, 371–373.
https://doi.org/10.1037/h0072007
Howard, D. T. (1927). The influence of evolutionary doctrine on psychology. Psychological Review, 34, 305-312.
https://doi.org/10.1037/h0070903
32
Hrdy, S. B. (2009). Mothers and others: The evolutionary origins of mutual understanding. Belknap.
Hull, C. L. (2003). Letter to the Editor: How sexually dimorphic are we? Review and synthesis. American Journal of
Human Biology, 15, 112-116. https://doi.org/10.1002/ajhb.10122
Hyde, J. S. (2005). The gender similarities hypothesis. American Psychologist, 60, 581-592.
https://doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.60.6.581
Hyde, J. S. (2014). Gender similarities and differences. Annual Review of Psychology, 65, 373-398.
https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-psych-010213-115057
Hyde, J. S., Bigler, R. S., Joel, D., Tate, C. C., & van Anders, S. M. (2019). The future of sex and gender in
psychology: Five challenges to the gender binary. American Psychologist, 74, 171-193.
https://doi.org/10.1037/amp0000307
Janicke, T., Häderer, I. K., Lajeunesse, M. J., & Anthes, N. (2016). Darwinian sex roles confirmed across the animal
kingdom. Science Advances, 2, e1500983. https://doi.org/10.1126/sciadv.1500983
Janssen, D. F. (2018). Know thy gender: Ethymological primer. Archives of Sexual Behavior, 47, 2149-2154.
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10508-018-1300-x
Jastrow, J. (1927). The reconstruction of psychology. Psychological Review, 34, 169-195.
https://doi.org/10.1037/h0071505
Joel, D. (2012). Genetic-gonadal-genitals sex (3G-sex) and the misconception of brain and gender, or, why 3G-
males and 3G-females have intersex brain and intersex gender. Biology of Sex Differences, 3, 27.
https://doi.org/10.1186/2042-6410-3-27
Joel, D., & Fausto-Sterling, A. (2016). Beyond sex differences: New approaches for thinking about variation in
brain structure and function. Philosophical Transaction of the Royal Society of London B, 371, 20150451.
https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2015.0451
Johnson, W., Carothers, A., & Deary, I. J. (2008). Sex differences in variability in general intelligence: A new look
at the old question. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3, 518-531. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1745-
6924.2008.00096.x
Jonason, P. K., & Schmitt, D. P. (2016). Quantifying common criticisms of evolutionary psychology. Evolutionary
Psychological Science, 2, 177-188. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40806-016-0050-z
Jordan-Young, R., & Rumiati, R. I. (2012). Hardwired for sexism? Approaches to sex/gender in neuroscience.
Neuroethics, 5, 305-315. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-011-9134-4
Kaiser, T. (2019). Nature and evoked culture: Sex differences in personality are uniquely correlated with ecological
stress. Personality and Individual Differences, 148, 67-72. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.paid.2019.05.011
Kaiser, T., Del Giudice, M., & Booth, T. (2020). Global sex differences in personality: Replication with an open
online dataset. Journal of Personality, 88, 415-429. https://doi.org/10.1111/jopy.12500
Kalat, J. W. (2016). Introduction to psychology. Cengage.
Kenrick, D. T., & Li, N. (2000). The Darwin is in the details. American Psychologist, 55, 1060–1061.
https://doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.55.9.1060
Kodric-Brown, A., & Brown, J. H. (1987). Anisogamy, sexual selection, and the evolution and maintenance of sex.
Evolutionary Ecology, 1, 95-105. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02067393
Kugler, K. G., Reif, J. A., Kaschner, T., & Brodbeck, F. C. (2018). Gender differences in the initiation of
negotiations: A meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 144, 198 –222. https://doi.org/10.1037/bul0000135
Lauer, J. E., Yhang, E., & Lourenco, S. F. (2019). The development of gender differences in spatial reasoning: A
meta-analytic review. Psychological Bulletin, 145, 537 –565. https://doi.org/10.1037/bul0000191
Lehre, A. C., Lehre, K. P., Laake, P., & Danbolt, N. C. (2009). Greater intrasex phenotype variability in males than
in females is a fundamental aspect of the gender differences in humans. Developmental Psychobiology, 51,
198-206. https://doi.org/10.1002/dev.20358
Lehtonen, J., & Kokko, H. (2011). Two roads to two sexes: unifying gamete competition and gamete limitation in a
single model of anisogamy evolution. Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, 65, 445-459.
https://doi.org/10.1007/s00265-010-1116-8
Lehtonen, J., & Parker, G. A. (2014). Gamete competition, gamete limitation, and the evolution of the two sexes.
Molecular Human Reproduction, 20, 1161-1168. https://doi.org/10.1093/molehr/gau068
33
Lehtonen, J., Parker, G. A., & Schärer, L. (2016). Why anisogamy drives ancestral sex roles. Evolution, 70, 1129-
1135. https://doi.org/10.1111/evo.12926
Leskinen, E. A., & Cortina, L. M. (2014). Dimensions of disrespect: Mapping and measuring gender harassment in
organizations. Psychology of Women Quarterly, 38, 107-123. https://doi.org/10.1177/0361684313496549
Lieberman, H., & Schatzberg, E. (2018). A failure of academic quality control: The technology of orgasm. Journal
of Positive Sexuality, 4, 24-47. https://journalofpositivesexuality.org/wp-content/uploads/2018/08/Failure-
of-Academic-Quality-Control-Technology-of-Orgasm-Lieberman-Schatzberg.pdf
Lippa, R. A. (2001). On deconstructing and reconstructing masculinity–femininity. Journal of Research in
Personality, 35, 168-207. https://doi.org/10.1006/jrpe.2000.2307
Lippa, R. A. (2005). Gender, nature, and nurture (2nd ed.). Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Lippa, R. A. (2010). Gender differences in personality and interests: When, where, and why? Social and Personality
Psychology Compass, 4, 1098-1110. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1751-9004.2010.00320.x
Lohman, D. F., & Lakin, J. M. (2009). Consistencies in sex differences on the Cognitive Abilities Test across
countries, grades, test forms, and cohorts. British Journal of Educational Psychology, 79, 389-407.
https://doi.org/10.1348/000709908X354609
Lyle, H. F., & Smith, E. A. (2012). How conservative are evolutionary anthropologists? Human Nature, 23, 306-
322. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12110-012-9150-z
Maccoby, E. E., & Jacklin, C. N. (1974). The psychology of sex differences. Stanford University Press.
Mac Giolla, E., & Kajonius, P. J. (2019). Sex differences in personality are larger in gender equal countries:
Replicating and extending a surprising finding. International Journal of Psychology, 54, 705-711.
https://doi.org/10.1002/ijop.12529
Machin, S., & Pekkarinen, T. (2008). Global sex differences in test score variability. Science, 322, 1331–1332.
https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1162573
Martin, A. E., & Slepian, M. L. (2020). The primacy of gender: Gendered cognition underlies the big two
dimensions of social cognition. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 1745691620904961.
https://doi.org/10.1177/1745691620904961
McCaughey, M. (2007). The caveman mystique: Pop-Darwinism and the debates over sex, violence, and science.
Routledge.
McKenna, W. (1978). Biological and commonsense constructions of gender. Paper presented at the Symposium on
Biology and Society, American Psychological Association, Toronto.
McKenna, W., & Kessler, S. (1977). Experimental design as a source of sex bias in social psychology. Sex Roles, 3,
117-128. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00288663
McNemar., Q., & Terman, L. M. (1936). Sex differences in variational tendency. Genetic Psychology Monographs,
18, 1-65.
Money, J. (1955). Hermaphroditism, gender and precocity in hyperadrenocorticism: Psychologic findings. Bulletin
of the Johns Hopkins Hospital, 96, 253–264.
Morgenroth, T., & Ryan, M. K. (2020). The effects of gender trouble: An integrative theoretical framework of the
perpetuation and disruption of the gender/sex binary. Perspectives on Psychological Science,
1745691620902442. https://doi.org/10.1177/1745691620902442
Morris, C. G., & Maisto, A. A. (2018). Understanding psychology (12th ed.). Pearson.
Morris, M. L. (2016). Vocational interests in the United States: Sex, age, ethnicity, and year effects. Journal of
Counseling Psychology, 63, 604–615. https://doi.org/10.1037/cou0000164
Morton, T. A., Postmes, T., Haslam, S. A., & Hornsey, M. J. (2009). Theorizing gender in the face of social change:
Is there anything essential about essentialism? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 96, 653–664.
https://doi.org/10.1037/a0012966
Murray, C. (2020). Human diversity: The biology of gender, race, and class. Hachette UK.
Murray, D. R., Murphy, S. C., von Hippel, W., Trivers, R., & Haselton, M. G. (2017). A preregistered study of
competing predictions suggests that men do overestimate women’s sexual intent. Psychological Science,
28, 253–255. https://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0956797616675474
34
Nature (2020). COVID research updates: A vaccine that mimics the coronavirus prompts potent antibodies. Nature,
https://doi.org/10.1038/d41586-020-00502-w
Nicolas, S. C. A., & Welling, L. L. M. (2015). The Darwinian mystique? Synthesizing evolutionary psychology and
feminism. In V Zeigler-Hill, L. M. Welling, & T. K. Shackelford (Eds.), Evolutionary perspectives on
social psychology (pp. 203-212). Springer.
Noba Project (2020). Discover psychology 2.0 – A brief introductory text. Noba.
https://nobaproject.com/textbooks/discover-psychology-v2-a-brief-introductory-text
Noddings, N. (1992). Variability—a pernicious hypothesis. Review of Educational Research, 62, 85–88.
https://doi.org/10.3102/00346543062001085
Oakley, A. (1972). Sex, gender, and society. Harper Colophon.
Pappas, S. (2019). APA issues first-ever guidelines for practice with men and boys. Monitor on Psychology, January
2019, 35-39.
Perilloux, C., & Kurzban, R. (2015). Do men overperceive women’s sexual interest? Psychological Science, 26, 70–
77. https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797614555727
Pinker, S. (2003). The blank slate: The modern denial of human nature. Penguin.
Pluckrose, H., & Lindsay, J. A. (2020). Cynical theories: How activist scholarship made everything about race,
gender, and identity—and why this harms everybody. Pitchstone.
Pratto, F., Sidanius, J., Stallworth, L. M., & Malle, B. F. (1994). Social dominance orientation: A personality
variable predicting social and political attitudes. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67, 741-
763. https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.67.4.741
Reilly, D. (2019). Gender can be a continuous variable, not just a categorical one: Comment on Hyde, Bigler, Joel,
Tate, and van Anders (2019). American Psychologist, 74, 840–841. https://doi.org/10.1037/amp0000505
Reilly, D., Neumann, D. L., & Andrews, G. (2019). Gender differences in reading and writing achievement:
Evidence from the National Assessment of Educational Progress (NAEP). American Psychologist, 74, 445–
458. https://doi.org/10.1037/amp0000356
Reinhold, K., & Engqvist, L. (2013). The variability is in the sex chromosomes. Evolution, 67, 3662-3668.
https://doi.org/10.1111/evo.12224
Reynolds, T. (2020). Retracting a controversial paper won’t help female scientists. Quillette.
https://quillette.com/2020/11/23/retracting-a-controversial-paper-wont-help-female-scientists/
Rippon, G., Jordan-Young, R., Kaiser, A., & Fine, C. (2014). Recommendations for sex/gender neuroimaging
research: Key principles and implications for research design, analysis, and interpretation. Frontiers in
Human Neuroscience, 8, 650. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2014.00650
Ritchie, S. J., Cox, S. R., Shen, X., Lombardo, M. V., Reus, L. M., Alloza, C., ... & Liewald, D. C. (2018). Sex
differences in the adult human brain: Evidence from 5216 UK Biobank participants. Cerebral Cortex, 28,
2959-2975. https://doi.org/10.1093/cercor/bhy109
Roughgarden, J. (2013). Evolution's rainbow: Diversity, gender, and sexuality in nature and people. University of
California Press.
Saini, A. (2017). Inferior: How science got women wrong and the new research that's rewriting the story. Beacon
Press.
Satel, S. (2002). PC, MD: How political correctness is corrupting medicine. Perseus.
Sax, L. (2002). How common is intersex? A response to Anne Fausto-Sterling. Journal of Sex Research, 39, 174-
178. https://doi.org/10.1080/00224490209552139
Schacter, D. L., Gilbert, D. T., Nock, M. K., & Wegner, D. M. (2020). Psychology (5th ed.). Macmillian.
Schärer, L., Rowe, L., & Arnqvist, G. (2012). Anisogamy, chance and the evolution of sex roles. Trends in Ecology
& Evolution, 27, 260-264. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tree.2011.12.006
Schmitt, D. P. (2015). The evolution of culturally-variable sex differences: Men and women are not always
different, but when they are… it appears not to result from patriarchy or sex role socialization. In T. K.
Shackelford, R. D. Hansen (eds.), The evolution of sexuality (pp. 221-256). Springer.
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-09384-0_11
35
Schmitt, D. P., & the International Sexuality Description Project (2003). Universal sex differences in the desire for
sexual variety: Tests from 52 nations, 6 continents, and 13 islands. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 85, 85-101. https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.85.1.85
Schmitt, D. P., Long, A. E., McPhearson, A., O'Brien, K., Remmert, B., & Shah, S. H. (2017). Personality and
gender differences in global perspective. International Journal of Psychology, 52, 45-56.
https://doi.org/10.1002/ijop.12265
Schwabacher, S. (1972). Male versus female representation in psychological research: An examination of the
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 1970, 1971. JSAS Catalog of Selected Documents, 1972, 2,
20-21.
Segerstråle, U. (2000). Defenders of the truth: The battle for science in the sociobiology debate and beyond. Oxford
University Press.
Seller, M. (1981). G. Stanley Hall and Edward Thorndike on the education of women: Theory and policy in the
progressive era. Educational Studies, 11, 365-374. https://doi.org/10.1207/s15326993es1104_2
Shields, S. (1975). Functionalism, Darwinism, and the psychology of women. American Psychologist, 30, 739–754.
https://doi.org/10.1037/h0076948
Skewes, L., Fine, C., & Haslam, N. (2018). Beyond Mars and Venus: The role of gender essentialism in support for
gender inequality and backlash. PLoS ONE, 13, e0200921. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0200921
Spielman, R. M. (Ed.) (2020). Psychology. Openstax. https://openstax.org/details/books/psychology
Stanley, H. M. (1895). Studies in the evolutionary psychology of feeling. Sonnenschein.
Stewart-Williams, S. (2018). The ape that understood the universe: How the mind and culture evolve. Cambridge
University Press.
Stewart-Williams, S., & Thomas, A. G. (2013). The ape that thought it was a peacock: Does evolutionary
psychology exaggerate human sex differences? Psychological Inquiry, 24, 137-168.
https://doi.org/10.1080/1047840X.2013.804899
Stoet, G., & Geary, D. C. (2015). Sex differences in academic achievement are not related to political, economic, or
social equality. Intelligence, 48, 137-151. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.intell.2014.11.006
Stoet, G., & Geary, D. C. (2018). The gender-equality paradox in science, technology, engineering, and mathematics
education. Psychological Science, 29, 581-593. https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797617741719
Stoet, G., & Geary, D. C. (2020). Sex-specific academic ability and attitude patterns in students across developed
countries. Intelligence, 81, 101453. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.intell.2020.101453
Stoller, R. J. (1968). Sex and Gender: The Development of Masculinity and Femininity. New York: Science House.
Taborsky, M., & Brockmann, H. J. (2010). Alternative reproductive tactics and life history phenotypes. In Kappeler,
P. (Ed.), Animal behavior: Evolution and mechanisms (pp. 537–586). Springer.
Tavris, C. (1992). The mismeasure of woman. Simon & Schuster.
Taylor, S., Jr. (2005). Why feminist careerists neutered Larry Summers. The Atlantic.
https://www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2005/02/why-feminist-careerists-neutered-larry-
summers/303795/
Terman, L. M., Johnson, W. B., Kuznets, G., & McNemar, O. W. (1946). Psychological sex differences. In L.
Carmichael (Ed.), Manual of child psychology (pp. 954-993). Wiley.
Terman, L. M., & Miles, C. C. (1936). Sex and personality: Studies in masculinity and femininity. McGraw-Hill.
Thompson, H. (1903). The mental traits of sex: An experimental investigation of the normal mind in men and
women. University of Chicago Press.
Thorndike, E. L. (1906). Sex in education. Bookman, 23, 211-214.
Treat, T. A., McMurray, B., Betty, J. R., & Viken, R. J. (2020). Tracking men’s perceptions of women’s sexual
interest. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 29, 71-79.
https://doi.org/10.1177/0963721419884322
Twenge, J. M. (1997b). Changes in masculine and feminine traits over time: A meta-analysis. Sex Roles, 36, 305–
325. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02766650
36
Tybur, J. M., Miller, G. F., & Gangestad, S. W. (2007). Testing the controversy. An empirical examination of
adaptationists’ attitudes toward politics and science. Human Nature, 18, 313-328.
https://doi.org/10.1007/s12110-007-9024-y
Tybur, J. M., & Navarrete, C. D. (2018). Interrupting bias in social psychology: Evolutionary psychology as a guide.
(pp. 247-264). In J. T. Crawford & L. Jussim (Eds.), The politics of social psychology. Routledge.
Unger, R. K. (1979). Toward a redefinition of sex and gender. American Psychologist, 34, 1085-1094.
https://doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.34.11.1085
Vandermassen, G. (2004). Sexual selection: A tale of male bias and feminist denial. European Journal of Women's
Studies, 11, 9-26. https://doi.org/10.1177/1350506804039812
Vandermassen, G. (2020). Why the feminist aversion to biology is misguided. IDW: The magazine of the
intellectual dark web. https://intellectualdarkwebanonymous.com/why-the-feminist-aversion-to-biology-is-
misguided/
von Hippel, W., Buss, D. M., & Richardson, G. B. (2020). Science progresses through open disagreement: Rejoinder
to Fine (2020). Archives of Scientific Psychology, 8, 11-14. https://doi.org/10.1037/arc0000073
Wai, J., Cacchio, M., Putallaz, M., & Makel, M. C. (2010). Sex differences in the right tail of cognitive abilities: A
30 year examination. Intelligence, 38, 412-423. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.intell.2010.04.006
Wai, J., Hodges, J., & Makel, M. C. (2018). Sex differences in ability tilt in the right tail of cognitive abilities: A 35-
year examination. Intelligence, 67, 76-83. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.intell.2018.02.003
Waters, T. E., Camia, C., Facompré, C. R., & Fivush, R. (2019). A meta-analytic examination of maternal
reminiscing style: Elaboration, gender, and children’s cognitive development. Psychological Bulletin, 145,
1082–1102. https://doi.org/10.1037/bul0000211
Webermann, A. R., & Murphy, C. M. (2020). How can psychology help reduce gender-based violence and
misconduct on college campuses? American Psychologist. https://doi.org/10.1037/amp0000705
Weisstein, N. (1971). Psychology constructs the female; or the fantasy life of the male psychologist (with some
attention to the fantasies of his friends, the male biologist and the male anthropologist). Social Education,
35, 362-373.
Winegard, B. M., & Winegard, B. (2018). Paranoid egalitarian meliorism (pp. 193-209). In J. T. Crawford & L.
Jussim (Eds.), The politics of social psychology. Routledge.
Wood, W., & Eagly, A. H. (2000). Once again, the origins of sex differences. American Psychologist, 55, 1062-
1063. https://doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.55.9.1062
Wood, W., & Eagly, A. H. (2012). Biosocial construction of sex differences and similarities in behavior. Advances
in Experimental Social Psychology, Vol. 46 (pp. 55-123). Academic Press. https://doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-
12-394281-4.00002-7
Woolley, H. T. (1910). A review of the recent literature on the psychology of sex. Psychological Bulletin, 7, 335–
342. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0066338
Woolley, H. T. (1914). The psychology of sex. Psychological Bulletin, 11, 353–379.
https://doi.org/10.1037/h0070064
Wyman, M. J., & Rowe, L. (2014). Male bias in distributions of additive genetic, residual, and phenotypic variances
of shared traits. The American Naturalist, 184, 326-337. https://doi.org/10.1086/677310
Zell, E., Krizan, Z., & Teeter, S. R. (2015). Evaluating gender similarities and differences using metasynthesis.
American Psychologist, 70, 10-20. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0038208
Zell, E., Strickhouser, J. E., Lane, T. N., & Teeter, S. R. (2016). Mars, Venus, or Earth? Sexism and the
exaggeration of psychological gender differences. Sex Roles, 75, 287-300. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11199-
016-0622-1