PresentationPDF Available

Why do we need a Unified Theory of Embodied Cognition?

Authors:

Abstract

Abstract: The range, diversity and the different metaphysical assumptions of Embodied Cognition (EC) hypotheses that have been formulated in recent years, a) do not allow for their pragmatic, problem-solving oriented adoption by Cognitive Science and (b) favor their fragmentary use by various scientific and practical fields, resulting in misunderstandings concerning their content and validity. Through a brief overview, this presentation aims to highlight the reasons why research towards a unified theory of embodied cognition can contribute to solving old and modern problems regarding Human Cognition and Artificial Intelligence. Keywords: Embodied Cognition, Embodied Mind
Presentation for the 94th Joint Session of the Mind Association and the
Aristotelian Society | University of Kent, 10 -12 July 2020 (Open Session)1
Why do we need a
Unified Theory of Embodied Cognition?
Dr. Alkis Gounaris
National and Kapodistrian University of Athens (NKUA)
Abstract: The range, diversity and the different metaphysical assumptions of
Embodied Cognition (EC) hypotheses that have been formulated in recent years, a)
do not allow for their pragmatic, problem-solving oriented adoption by Cognitive
Science and (b) favor their fragmentary use by various scientific and practical fields,
resulting in misunderstandings concerning their content and validity. Through a brief
overview, this presentation aims to highlight the reasons why research towards a
unified theory of embodied cognition can contribute to solving old and modern
problems regarding Human Cognition and Artificial Intelligence.
Sub Disciplinary Area: Philosophy of Cognitive Science, Philosophy of Artificial
Intelligence
Keywords: Embodied Cognition, Embodied Mind
In this presentation I will attempt to answer the question of why we need a Unified
Theory of Embodied Cognition (UTEC), or why we need to untangle the thread of all
the hypotheses made over the last twenty years, regarding the role of the body and
the world in the process of understanding and explaining mental phenomena.
1 Gounaris, A. (2020). Why do we need a Unified Theory of Embodied Cognition? Presentation for the
94th Joint Session of the Mind Association and the Aristotelian Society. University of Kent, Online
Open Session. Retrieved July 15th, 2020 from https://alkisgounaris.gr/en/research/why-do-we-need-
a-unified-theory-of-embodied-cognition/
The 94th Joint Session of the Mind Association and the Aristotelian Society |
University of Kent, 10 -12 July 2020 (Open Session)
COPYRIGHT © 2020 ALKIS GOUNARIS | alkisg@philosophy.uoa.gr | PAGE 2 FROM 6
I will begin by outlining how we ended up talking about such a wide range of EC
hypotheses, in what ways they differ and what their levels of study and comparison
are, and I will conclude with (1) how clarifying and delineating them can lead us to a
unified theory and (2) why such a theory contributes to the evolution of Cognitive
Science and beyond.
It has been commonly known, ever since the early days of Standard Cognitive
Science (SCS) in the 1970s, that there have been many and important objections to
the philosophical assertions or the “dogma” of the computational and
representational theory of mind (Gomila & Calvo, 2008:11) mainly to: a) assuming
that Human Cognition (HC) is a computational process of symbolic representations
and b) assuming the existence of internal representations of the world inside the
brain. In the dominant model of SCS, cognitive functions have a definite beginning,
with data input into the brain, and a definite end with output from it, essentially
limiting research to processes “inside” the brain (Shapiro, 2011:26-27). From this
solipsistic view, the body and the world are absent.
Soon, the hypothesis that the environment in which a cognitive being operates is
nothing more than data entered into the system to be processed, without taking into
account the world itself, began to create problems in HC and AI research programs
(Dreyfus, 1972, 1992, 2007). For example, SCS could not provide an answer to the
frame problem (Wheeler, 2005; Zambak, 2013), or, the referential nature of
representations limited machine learning (Abrahamsen & Bechtel 2012:28).
Accordingly, the formal symbolic structure of language was unable to provide an
adequate answer to the grounding problem (Vogt, 2006:176-209), and then
questions regarding the nature of data and information itself occurred, as well as
regarding the way meaning is derived (Shapiro, 2007:339).
Subsequently, applied research in AI faced paradoxes, such as that of Moravec,
concerning the way complex cognitive computing processes (like chess) require
comparatively little computational resources, while simple cognitive tasks (such as
descending a staircase) require enormous amounts.
At the same time, in recent years, numerous findings of applied research in
education have demonstrated the important role of the body and the environment in
achieving cognitive goals such as learning, memorizing, language comprehension
etc. (Skulmowski, 2018; Kosmas, 2019). More research has also demonstrated the
anthropomorphic nature of cognition and the role of mirror neurons in monitoring
physical movements and behaviors (Gazzola & Rizzolatti, 2007).
From the 1990s and on, all this has led the field of SCS research to move “in depth”
(see cognitive neuroscience) and “outwards” (see EC) (Abrahamsen & Bechtel,
2012:29), resulting in new research programs, according to which cognition is not a
process that happens inside an isolated “box” but is something more complex, which
happens because an organism lives, moves and acts within an environment.
Other programs moving in this direction and often combined with EC research were:
(a) neural networks, which adopted distributed and coded patterns of
representations, carrying information in their internal properties (Clark, 1993:19) and
The 94th Joint Session of the Mind Association and the Aristotelian Society |
University of Kent, 10 -12 July 2020 (Open Session)
COPYRIGHT © 2020 ALKIS GOUNARIS | alkisg@philosophy.uoa.gr | PAGE 3 FROM 6
(b) dynamic systems theory, which introduced time variability as a determinant factor
in the cognitive process of the system (Van Gelder,1998).
A common assumption of all these hypotheses is that cognition is not an exclusive
function of a computational mind “passive” to external stimuli, but, in fact, the bodily
functions and the interactions of the cognitive being with its environment, contribute
directly and decisively to mental processes (Leitan & Chaffey, 2014).
However, despite the above common assumption, EC hypotheses are extremely
heterogeneous and diverse (Wilson, 2002). This may partly be due to the fact that
many of the research projects that have featured these hypotheses over the years
originate, either independently or combined, from different scientific disciplines such
as Philosophy, Psychology, Linguistics, Neuroscience, Artificial Intelligence, Robotics
etc. and have possibly coupled EC with other metaphysical theories such as the
emergence of properties of complex systems (Kuniyoshi et al., 2007) and others.
These divergences stemmed mainly from philosophical and conceptual assumptions
and resulted in significant differences in both their technical terminology and the
meaning of the common terms they use.
Influenced by theoretical traditions such as Phenomenology, American Naturalism,
the Ecological Theory of Visual Perception (Gibson, 1979), Gestalt psychology,
Cognitive Development Theory and others, EC theories have attempted to exempt
themselves (more or less) from the standard metaphysical or epistemological
assumptions of SCS, such as the “Cartesian theater”, the autonomy and causality of
mind, the formal syntactic structure of mental content, the meaningful data
hypothesis and others.
At the same time they made new claims that could be summarized according to
Shapiro (ibid:4) as follows: a) the bodily properties of an organism delimit or constrain
the concepts that the organism can acquire, b) the interaction of an organism with its
environment replaces the need for a representational process, c) the body and the
world play a constitutive, rather than simply a causal role in the cognitive process.
Such a classification, although extremely useful in understanding the general content
of the EC spectrum claims, is not “competent” enough to lead in the direction of
unification.
The need for a unified EC theory has been formulated for about a decade (Barsalou,
2008; Gomila & Calvo, 2008), while efforts have been made to classify individual
theories based on their ontological characteristics (Gallagher, 2011). However,
research in this direction has not been very fruitful, mainly because of the
researchers' attempt to somehow adapt a unified theory in the framework of their
own assertions.
Most will agree with Shapiro's (2011:3) claim that a UTEC, or at least a unified field
of research, will make it possible to compare and evaluate two fields that will then be
clearly defined UTEC and SCS rather than comparing a series of heterogeneous
research programs, as found in EC today, with a compact field such as SCS. This
comparison would essentially reveal whether these two approaches: a) offer
The 94th Joint Session of the Mind Association and the Aristotelian Society |
University of Kent, 10 -12 July 2020 (Open Session)
COPYRIGHT © 2020 ALKIS GOUNARIS | alkisg@philosophy.uoa.gr | PAGE 4 FROM 6
competing explanations for the same phenomena, b) aim at a different explanatory
model overall, or c) develop different yet compatible views through which they
understand the cognitive process.
This is certainly a good and useful reason why we should step up and intensify
research in this direction, but in my opinion it is not the main reason. The main
reasons are that through a UTEC we will be able a) to preserve and b) to utilize in an
interdisciplinary manner the wealth of EC ideas such as the notion of “affordances”
(Gibson, 1977), the systemic theories of meaning and its independency from
representations, as well as the possibility to eliminate the traditional assumptions of
“folk psychology” and its inherited terminology that lead us to dead ends.
Clearly, the main beneficiary of such an endeavor will be the theory of Next Day
Cognitive Science (NDCS), but those who are involved in applied research such as
neuroscience as well as robotics and artificial intelligence research programs, will
also benefit greatly, since a UTEC can become a tool for shaping research
hypotheses and can make a substantial contribution to the progress of their research
objectives.
Incidentally, as various EC theories are selectively, and rather superficially, adopted
by fields of applied science such as clinical psychology, education, sports science,
modern marketing and advertising (Leitan & Chaffey, 2014) among others, there will
be a clarification of the distorted assertions that create a veneer of science, and
above all, the authority of the sciences of the mind, cognition and intelligence will be
safeguarded.
If we consider an NDCS oriented towards problem solving as a commonly accepted
demand, we should be willing to move on to a cash value - pragmatic approach of a
UTEC, so that the differences in the spectrum of EC hypotheses will be addressed
at a practical level. An important first step in such a venture may be to classify
existing EC hypotheses according to the area and the objectives of their study. For
example:
[a] at a level of compatibility or not with SCS, [b] at a level of scientific fields of
application, [c] according to characteristics mainly related to the philosophical origins,
[d] at a conceptual level, [e] at a terminology level, [f] at a methodology level, etc.
Finally, an additional (visionary) reason that a UTEC can prove to be extremely
useful is the possibility of reaping a significant payoff: The unification of EC theories
is likely to pave the way for the unification of the sciences of the mind, cognition and
intelligence and possibly explain the precise role that the body, the environment,
language and other systemic factors play in mental processes.
Such an understanding may help to conceptualize and formulate new “bridging laws”
between the various description levels among research fields, from the level of the
cognitive organism acting in the world and interacting with others, to the level of the
basic elements (i.e. neurons, molecules, etc) or, respectively for AI, from the level of
the agent coping in the world to the basic level of data.
The 94th Joint Session of the Mind Association and the Aristotelian Society |
University of Kent, 10 -12 July 2020 (Open Session)
COPYRIGHT © 2020 ALKIS GOUNARIS | alkisg@philosophy.uoa.gr | PAGE 5 FROM 6
Selected Bibliography:
Abrahamsen, Α. Bechtel. W. (2012). History and Core Themes. In: Frankish, K. -
Ramsey, W. The Cambridge Handbook of Cognitive Science. Cambridge University
Press
Barsalou, L.W. (2008). Grounded Cognition. Annual Review of Psychology. 59,
pp.617-645. http://dx.doi.org/10.1146/annurev.psych.59.103006.093639
Clark, A. (1993). Associative Engines: Connectionism, Concepts, and
Representational Change. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Dreyfus, H. (1992). What Computers Still Can't Do: A Critique of Artificial Reason.
Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press
Dreyfus, H. (2007). Why Heideggerian AI Failed and How Fixing It Would Require
Making it More Heideggerian. Philosophical Psychology. Routledge. Vol.20. No.2,
pp.247-268
Gallagher, S. (2011). Interpretations of embodied cognition. In W. Tschacher and C.
Bergomi (Eds.). The Implications of Embodiment: Cognition and Communication.
pp.59-70. United Kingdom: Imprint Academic
Gazzola, V. Rizzolatti, G., et, al. (2007). The anthropomorphic brain: The mirror
neuron system responds to human and robotic actions. DOI:
10.1016/j.neuroimage.2007.02.003
Gibson, J. J. (1977). The theory of affordances. In Shaw, R. and Bransford, J. (eds.).
Perceiving, acting, and knowing: Toward an ecological psychology. NJ: Erlbaum,
pp.67-82
Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston, MA:
Houghton Mifflin
Gomila, T. & Calvo, P. (2008). Directions for an Embodied Cognitive Science:
Toward an Integrated Approach. In Calvo P. & Gomila A. (Eds.). Handbook of
Cognitive Science: An Embodied Approach. San Diego, Elsevier
Kosmas, P. (2019), Implementing embodied learning in the classroom: effects on
children’s memory and language skills. DOI: 10.1080/09523987.2018.1547948
Kuniyoshi, Y. et al. (2007). Emergence and development of embodied cognition: A
constructivist approach using robots. Progress in brain research. 164:425-45. DOI:
10.1016/S0079-6123(07)64023-0
Leitan, N. & Chaffey, L. (2014). Embodied cognition and its applications. Sensoria: A
Journal of Mind, Brain & Culture. DOI: 10.7790/sa.v10i1.384
Shapiro, L. (2007). The Embodied Cognition Research Programme. Philosophy
Compass. 2/2 (2007): pp.338-346, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2007.00064.x
The 94th Joint Session of the Mind Association and the Aristotelian Society |
University of Kent, 10 -12 July 2020 (Open Session)
COPYRIGHT © 2020 ALKIS GOUNARIS | alkisg@philosophy.uoa.gr | PAGE 6 FROM 6
Shapiro, L. (2011). Embodied Cognition. New York: Routledge
Skulmowski, Α. (2018). Embodied learning: introducing a taxonomy based on bodily
engagement and task integration. DOI: 10.1186/s41235-018-0092-9
Van Gelder, T. et al. (1998). The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 21, pp.615-665
Vogt, P. (2006). Language evolution and robotics: Issues on symbol grounding and
language acquisition. In: Loula, A. Gudwin, R. Queiroz, J. (Eds.). Artificial Cognition
Systems. Hershey, PA.: Idea Group. pp. 176-209
Wilson, M. (2002). Six views of embodied cognition. Psychonomic Bulletin and
Review. 9: pp.625-636
Wheeler, Μ. (2005). Reconstructing the Cognitive World: The Next Step. Cambridge,
MA: A Bradford Book. The MIT Press
Zambak, A. (2013). The Frame Problem. Autonomy Approach versus Designer
Approach. In V.C. Müller (ed.): Philosophy and Theory of Artificial Intelligence.
Springer
ResearchGate has not been able to resolve any citations for this publication.
Article
Full-text available
The relationship among bodily movements, cognitive abilities, and academic achievement in children is receiving considerable attention in the research community. The embodied learning approach is based on the idea of an inseparable link between body and mind in learning, aiming for teaching methods that promote children’s active engagement in the classroom. This study implements embodied learning as a part of the classroom curriculum in a real classroom environment using motion-based games. A total of 52 elementary students engaged in embodied learning in-class activities for four months. The data-set included standardized pre-post testing for children’s cognitive and academic performance, general learning analytics from games’ usage, interviews, and observations from the teachers involved. Findings showed significant effects both on children’s cognitive abilities (i.e., short-memory skills) and academic performance (i.e., expressive vocabulary). This article contributes to the educational technology community by providing an example of implementing embodied learning via use of motion-based technologies in a real classroom environment.
Book
In Reconstructing the Cognitive World, Michael Wheeler argues that we should turn away from the generically Cartesian philosophical foundations of much contemporary cognitive science research and proposes instead a Heideggerian approach. Wheeler begins with an interpretation of Descartes. He defines Cartesian psychology as a conceptual framework of explanatory principles and shows how each of these principles is part of the deep assumptions of orthodox cognitive science (both classical and connectionist). Wheeler then turns to Heidegger's radically non-Cartesian account of everyday cognition, which, he argues, can be used to articulate the philosophical foundations of a genuinely non-Cartesian cognitive science. Finding that Heidegger's critique of Cartesian thinking falls short, even when supported by Hubert Dreyfus's influential critique of orthodox artificial intelligence, Wheeler suggests a new Heideggerian approach. He points to recent research in "embodied-embedded" cognitive science and proposes a Heideggerian framework to identify, amplify, and clarify the underlying philosophical foundations of this new work. He focuses much of his investigation on recent work in artificial intelligence-oriented robotics, discussing, among other topics, the nature and status of representational explanation, and whether (and to what extent) cognition is computation rather than a noncomputational phenomenon best described in the language of dynamical systems theory. Wheeler's argument draws on analytic philosophy, continental philosophy, and empirical work to "reconstruct" the philosophical foundations of cognitive science in a time of a fundamental shift away from a generically Cartesian approach. His analysis demonstrates that Heideggerian continental philosophy and naturalistic cognitive science need not be mutually exclusive and shows further that a Heideggerian framework can act as the "conceptual glue" for new work in cognitive science. Bradford Books imprint
Chapter
Instead of opting for a hybrid view of human cognition, the possibility exists to reinterpret higher level, decoupled, cognition, in terms of post-cognitivist principles. This chapter views that cognitivism, both in its classical version and in its connectionist form, is unable to deal fully with the dichotomy regarding cognition that the games of chess and pool example served to illustrate at the outset of this chapter. It is only when post-cognitivist models of cognition enter the picture that an answer to our opening question can begin to be given. Roughly speaking, the working hypothesis of post-cognitivism is that higher level cognitive activity never goes completely formal. Instead, it remains a "game of pool," in which non-formal perception-action activation patterns are ubiquitous.
Article
This chapter focuses on recent studies on the origins and evolution of language which have used multiple robot systems as their primary platform. After presenting some theoretical background regarding language evolution and the symbol grounding problem, the chapter discusses a number of themes within evolutionary linguistics that have been subject of robotic studies this far. These themes include categorisation, the formation of vocabularies, the evolution of grammar and the emergence of meaningful communication. Following this review, future avenues for research are discussed. The objective of the chapter is to present why robotics is a fruitful approach to study language origins and evolution, identify the main topics, report the major achievements and problems and provide a roadmap to future studies. The chapter concludes that robotics is, indeed, a very promising methodology to study language evolution and that, although many insights have been gained, we are still closer to the starting point than to the endpoint.
Article
Embodied Cognition is an approach to cognition that departs from traditional cognitive science in its reluctance to conceive of cognition as computational and in its emphasis on the significance of an organism's body in how and what the organism thinks. Three lines of embodied cognition research are described and some thoughts on the future of embodied cognition offered.
Article
Hubert L. Dreyfus, used Heidegger as a guide for the whole AI (artificial intelligence) program at MIT. He introduced Heidegger's non-representational account of the absorption of Dasein (human being) in the world. He also explained that Heidegger distinguished two modes of being, the readiness-to-hand of equipment when we are involved in using it, and the presence-at-hand of objects when we contemplate them. In his 1925 course, Logic: The Question of Truth, Heidegger describes the most basic experience of what he later calls 'pressing into possibilities' not as dealing with the desk, the door, the lamp, the chair and so forth, but as directly responding to a 'what for'. According to Heidegger, every act of having things in front of oneself and perceiving them is held within the disclosure of those things, a disclosure that things get from a primary meaningfulnesss in terms of the what-for.
Article
In humans and monkeys the mirror neuron system transforms seen actions into our inner representation of these actions. Here we asked if this system responds also if we see an industrial robot perform similar actions. We localised the motor areas involved in the execution of hand actions, presented the same subjects blocks of movies of humans or robots perform a variety of actions. The mirror system was activated strongly by the sight of both human and robotic actions, with no significant differences between these two agents. Finally we observed that seeing a robot perform a single action repeatedly within a block failed to activate the mirror system. This latter finding suggests that previous studies may have failed to find mirror activations to robotic actions because of the repetitiveness of the presented actions. Our findings suggest that the mirror neuron system could contribute to the understanding of a wider range of actions than previously assumed, and that the goal of an action might be more important for mirror activations than the way in which the action is performed.