PreprintPDF Available

Shared understanding of color among congenitally blind and sighted adults

Authors:
Preprints and early-stage research may not have been peer reviewed yet.

Abstract and Figures

Empiricist philosophers such as Locke famously argued that people born blind could only acquire shallow, fragmented facts about color. Contrary to this intuition, we report that blind and sighted people share an in-depth understanding of color, despite disagreeing about arbitrary color facts. Relative to the sighted, blind individuals are less likely to generate ‘yellow’ for banana and ‘red’ for stop-sign. However, blind and sighted adults are equally likely to infer that two bananas (natural kinds) and two stop-signs (artifacts with functional colors) are more likely to have the same color than two cars (artifacts with non-functional colors), make similar inferences about novel objects’ colors, and provide similar causal explanations. We argue that people develop inferentially-rich and intuitive “theories” of color regardless of visual experience. Linguistic communication is more effective at aligning people’s theories than their knowledge of verbal facts.
Content may be subject to copyright.
Shared understanding of color among congenitally
1
blind and sighted adults
2
3
Authors: Judy Sein Kim1*, Brianna Aheimer1, Verónica Montané Manrara1, Marina Bedny
4
Affiliations: 1Department of Psychological and Brain Sciences, Johns Hopkins University
5
*Correspondence to: judyseinkim@gmail.com
6
7
Abstract
8
Empiricist philosophers such as Locke famously argued that people born blind could only
9
acquire shallow, fragmented facts about color. Contrary to this intuition, we report that blind and
10
sighted people share an in-depth understanding of color, despite disagreeing about arbitrary
11
color facts. Relative to the sighted, blind individuals are less likely to generate yellow for
12
banana and red for stop-sign. However, blind and sighted adults are equally likely to infer that
13
two bananas (natural kinds) and two stop-signs (artifacts with functional colors) are more likely
14
to have the same color than two cars (artifacts with non-functional colors), make similar
15
inferences about novel objects’ colors, and provide similar causal explanations. We argue that
16
people develop inferentially-rich and intuitive theories of color regardless of visual experience.
17
Linguistic communication is more effective at aligning people’s theories than their knowledge of
18
verbal facts.
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
2
Introduction
31
Humans acquire knowledge through a variety of meansthrough direct sensory
32
experience, communication with others, and by thinking (1,2). The question of where knowledge
33
comes from is at the heart of many cognitive theories, but disentangling the relative contributions
34
of these sources is challenging (e.g., 3-8). Color knowledge in blindness provides a wedge into
35
this puzzle by isolating the contribution of first-person sensory experience (9-11). British
36
Empiricists like Locke and Hume argued that color ideas are inaccessible to people born blind
37
since sensory experience is the foundation of knowledge. More recently, Frank Jackson’s
38
influential thought experiment featuring Mary, a color scientist who lives in a black-and-white
39
room, inspired many debates about knowledge gained from first-person experience (e.g., 11-15).
40
Only a handful of empirical studies have examined what people born blind actually know about
41
color. Landau & Gleitman (16) showed that Kelli, a congenitally blind 4-year-old, applied color
42
words to concrete objects but not mental entities (e.g., ideas) and understood that color could
43
only be perceived visually, unlike texture or size. Blind and sighted adults share knowledge of
44
similarities between colors (e.g. green and blue are similar but different from orange and red) (17-
45
19). Several studies have also identified differences in blind and sighted people's color
46
knowledge. A recent study found that unlike sighted adults, adults born blind are unlikely to agree
47
on the colors of common animals (20). Even for objects for which blind and sighted people
48
generate the same color labels, blind individuals are less likely to use color as a dimension during
49
semantic similarity judgments (21). One interpretation of this evidence is that color knowledge
50
acquired through verbal communication consists largely of associative verbal facts and is thus
51
inferentially shallow (21-23). An individual born blind might know that the word ‘yellow’ is used to
52
describe ‘bananas’ without having in-depth understanding of color.
53
An alternative possibility is that blind individuals share with those who are sighted
54
inferentially-rich understanding of color. In fact, it is possible that in the absence of first-person
55
3
sensory experience of color, inferentially-rich knowledge is more preserved than knowledge of
56
associative color facts. Sighted children’s inferentially-rich, causal understanding of color enables
57
them to make inferences about real and novel object colors. Children expect an object’s
58
relationship with color to differ depending on whether it is a natural kind (e.g. animal, plant, gem)
59
or an artifact (e.g. machine, tool). When asked, “Could something still be a Glick even if it was a
60
different color?” 5 year-old children are more likely to say yes for an artifact than for an animal
61
(24). Such intuitions about color are part of broader frameworks, often referred to as ‘intuitive
62
theories’, about physical objects (e.g., 25, 26). Children view natural kinds as having intrinsic
63
essences emanating from nature, but link properties of artifacts to human intentions (e.g., 27-29).
64
In response to “Why is this object yellow?” children prefer explanations that appeal to biological
65
mechanisms for natural kinds but human intentions for artifacts (30). Such knowledge about color
66
can be distinguished from that of other object properties: for example, while different instances of
67
a natural kind (e.g., bananas) are more likely to have the same color than instances of an artifact
68
(e.g., cars), natural kinds and artifacts are similarly likely to have consistent shapes (24). The role
69
of first-person sensory experience in acquiring such causal-explanatory and inferentially-rich color
70
knowledge is not known.
71
In the current study, we probed sighted and congenitally blind people’s associative and
72
causal-explanatory knowledge of color. Experiment 1 first queried associative memory for real
73
objects’ colors by asking participants to generate “a common color of X” (Figure 1). We next asked
74
participants to judge how likely two instances of the same object are to have the same color, for
75
natural kinds (e.g. two bananas) and artifacts (e.g. two cars). We reasoned that if people share
76
intuitive theories about the relationship between color and object kind, blind and sighted people
77
would make similar inferences about color consistency, even while disagreeing on associative
78
facts (i.e., the particular colors of objects). For example, blind individuals might share with the
79
sighted the intuition that polar bears but not cars have a consistent color, despite showing low
80
agreement that polar bears are white. Alternatively, the experience of seeing that most polar bears
81
4
are white but that cars come in many different colors might be required to learn the different
82
importance of color for natural kinds and artifacts.
83
To test nuanced intuitions about the causal mechanisms that lead artifacts to have the
84
colors they do, we included a third object category: artifacts with functional colors (e.g. stop-sign,
85
paper, coin). Artifacts vary according to how much and in what way color relates to their function.
86
For some (e.g., mugs), color is not related to function (holding liquid), while for others (e.g., stop
87
signs) it is integral (e.g. stop signs are consistently red for visibility and recognizability). If sighted
88
and blind people appreciate how color relates to artifact function, they should judge stop signs to
89
have more consistent colors than mugs.
90
The ability to support generalization to novel instances is a key test of whether knowledge
91
is inferentially-rich (e.g., 28, 31). In Experiment 2, we thus asked participants to make inferences
92
about color consistency for novel objects (natural kinds, artifacts with function-relevant color, and
93
artifacts with function-irrelevant color) in an imaginary island scenario (Fig. 1). If abstract
94
knowledge about the origins and causes of color is shared, then blind and sighted participants
95
should be able to make systematic judgments about color consistency on the basis of object
96
category (e.g., kind of fruit, creature, gem, or household item, gadget, coin) alone. Finally, in
97
Experiment 3, we elicited open-ended explanations for why objects have their colors (e.g., “Why
98
is a carrot orange?”). This allowed us to probe the specific nature of blind and sighted people’s
99
knowledge of the causal mechanisms that give rise to object colors.
100
101
102
103
5
104
Fig1. Experimental conditions and trials for color consistency inference. Participants were asked
105
about color and usage consistency for real (Experiment 1) and novel (Experiment 2) objects. In both
106
experiments, color trials asked about natural kinds, artifacts with non-functional colors, and artifacts with
107
functional colors, while usage trials asked about natural kinds and artifacts. Different items were used in
108
every trial. For Experiment 1, all items used are listed, and for Experiment 2, one sample trial (an Appendix
109
with full list of trials can be found in Supplementary Materials).
110
Results
111
Knowledge of specific object colors among sighted and blind participants
112
Blind and sighted participants were asked to name a common color of 54 real objects
113
(Experiment 1, 30; Experiment 3, 24, collapsed for the current analysis) (Figure 2A). Objects were
114
chosen from three larger types: natural kinds (NK) (e.g. lemons), artifacts with non-functional
115
colors (A-NFC) (e.g. cars) and artifacts with functional colors (A-FC) (e.g. stop-signs). Color
116
naming agreement was quantified for each object using Simpson’s Diversity Index (SDI) (32), and
117
log-transformed SDIs were modeled using linear mixed effects regression (see Methods for
118
details). For both sighted and blind groups, color naming agreement was higher for natural kinds
119
6
(e.g. lemon) than for artifacts with non-functional colors (e.g. car), but similar to artifacts with
120
functional colors (e.g. stop signs) (Figure 2B; SDI for sighted NK: M=0.86, SD=0.2; A-NFC:
121
M=0.49, SD=0.29; A-FC: M=0.74, SD=0.29; blind NK: M=0.5, SD=0.25; A-NFC: M=0.24,
122
SD=0.09; A-FC: M=0.48, SD=0.26). Naming agreement was substantially higher for sighted
123
compared to blind participants across all object types, and there was no group-by-object kind
124
interaction (result of regression, effect of group:   , p<0.0001, 
 ; effect of
125
object type:   , p<0.0001,
  ; object-type-by-group interaction:    ,
126
p=0.5).
127
128
Fig 2. Object color naming agreement. Blind and sighted participants were asked to name common
129
colors of real objects (Experiments 1 and 3). (A) Stacked bars show the frequency of the 8 most frequent
130
colors provided for each object. Frequency for each unique color word is shown as a proportion of all words
131
provided for an object. (B) Bar graph showing naming agreement (Simpson’s Diversity Index calculated for
132
individual objects). Mean +/- SEM (across objects). (C) Correlation of ratings from Amazon Mechanical
133
Turk participants (n=20) for artifact colors’ relevance to function with blind and sighted participants’ color
134
consistency judgments.
135
136
7
Color consistency inferences in blind and sighted individuals: real objects
137
Sighted and blind participants judged the likelihood that two objects (e.g. two lemons),
138
randomly chosen from the same object category, would have the same color for 10 natural kinds
139
(NK e.g. lemon), 10 artifacts with non-functional colors (A-NFC e.g. car) and 10 artifacts with
140
functional colors (A-FC e.g. stop sign) (henceforth color consistency judgment). Participants rated
141
consistency likelihood on a scale of 1 to 7 (1: not likely, 7: very likely). As a control, participants
142
judged the likelihood that two people chosen at random would do the same thing with an object
143
(e.g. a leaf vs. a car) (henceforth usage consistency judgment). Usage consistency was tested
144
for 10 natural kinds (NK) and 10 artifacts.
145
146
Fig 3. Inferences about color and usage consistency across instances of an object. Consistency
147
judgments for real (Experiment 1) and novel (Experiment 2) objects. Bars are mean +/- SEM.
148
149
8
Sighted participants judged natural kinds (e.g. lemons) to have lower usage consistency
150
but higher color consistency, relative to artifacts (with non-functional colors, e.g. cars) (Fig. 3;
151
sighted usage NK: M=3.67, SD=1.59; usage A: M=5.66, SD=1.49, Wilcoxon matched-pairs
152
signed rank test for usage NK vs. A, two-tailed: z=-3.82, p=0.0001, r=0.88; color NK: M=6.2,
153
SD=1.12, color A-NFC: M=3.34; SD=1.72; color NK vs. A-NFC, z=3.78, p=0.0002, r=0.87).
154
Sighted participants’ color consistency ratings for artifacts with functional colors (e.g. stop-signs)
155
were higher than those for artifacts with non-functional colors and lower than those of natural
156
kinds (color A-FC: M=5.17, SD=1.81, comparing A-FC vs. A-NFC: z=3.8, p=0.0002, r=0.87; A-FC
157
vs. NK: z=-3.66, p=0.0003, r=0.84). For all artifacts, we obtained ratings of an object color’s
158
relevance to the its function from a separate group of sighted Amazon Mechanical Turk
159
participants. These function relevance judgments for artifacts were positively correlated with
160
sighted participants’ color consistency judgments (Spearman’s rank correlation: rho=0.61,
161
p<0.0001; Fig. 2C).
162
The same effect of object type on color and usage consistency judgments was observed
163
in the blind group. Blind participants again judged natural kinds to have lower usage consistency
164
but higher color consistency, compared to artifacts (blind usage NK: M=3.87, SD=1.61; A:
165
M=6.19, SD=1.15; Wilcoxon matched-pairs test for usage NK vs. A: z=-3.92, p<0.0001, r=0.88;
166
color NK: M=5.66, SD=1.52; A-NFC: M=3.32, SD=1.47; NK vs. A-NFC: z=3.92, p<0.0001,
167
r=0.88). Artifacts with functional colors were judged to have higher color consistency than artifacts
168
with non-functional colors, but lower than natural kinds (color A-FC: M=5.38, SD=1.81; comparing
169
A-FC vs. A-NFC: z=3.92, p<0.0001, r=0.88; A-FC vs. NK: z=-1.98, p=0.049, r=0.44). Blind
170
participants’ consistency judgments for artifacts were positively also correlated with MTurk
171
participants’ ratings of color’s relevance to object function (Spearman’s rho=0.61, p<0.0001; Fig.
172
2c).
173
When groups were compared directly to each other, object kind and trial type did not
174
interact with group (mixed ordinal logistic regression, group (blind vs. sighted) x trial type (color
175
9
vs. usage) x object kind (NK vs. A-NFC), with sighted group, usage trial, and A-NFC treatment
176
coded as baselines, no three-way interaction (=-0.24, SE=0.38, z=-0.63, p=0.53). We also
177
analyzed color judgments separately (group (blind vs. sighted) x object kind (NK vs. A-NFC vs.
178
A-FC), with sighted and A-NFC as baseline). There was no significant interaction between group
179
and object kind when comparing artifacts with functional color to artifacts with non-functional color
180
(=0.45, SE=0.27, z=1.65, p=0.099), although the interaction was significant when comparing
181
natural kinds to artifacts with non-functional color (=-1.02, SE=0.27, z=-3.78, p=0.0002).
182
Color consistency inferences in blind and sighted individuals: Novel objects
183
For real familiar objects, blind and sighted individuals could have made color consistency
184
judgments based on knowledge of their actual color frequencies (e.g., learned from seeing or
185
hearing that bananas are often yellow but that cars can be red, blue, black, etc.). Alternatively,
186
people might have a more general understanding of the relationship between object kind (e.g.
187
natural kind vs. artifact) and color. To distinguish between these possibilities, we collected color
188
consistency judgments for novel objects, for which neither blind nor sighted participants could
189
have directly experienced their color. Participants were presented with “explorer on an island”
190
scenario and judged the consistency of color and usage for novel natural kinds (e.g. gem, plant)
191
(5 objects), novel artifacts with non-function-relevant colors (e.g. cleaning-gadget, speaking
192
device) (5 objects), and novel artifacts with function-relevant colors (e.g. coin, ceremonial
193
clothing) (5 objects).
194
As with real objects, both groups judged artifacts to be more likely to have consistent
195
usage than natural kinds (sighted usage NK: M=2.76, SD=1.42; A: M=5.64, SD=1.38; Wilcoxon
196
matched-pairs signed rank test for NK vs. A: z=-3.82, p=0.0001, r=0.88; blind usage NK: M=3.25,
197
SD=1.73; A: M=5.77, SD=1.58; NK vs. A: z=-3.92, p<0.0001, r=0.88). For color trials, consistency
198
was again judged to be higher for natural kinds than for artifacts with non-functional color by both
199
groups (sighted color NK: M=5.67, SD=1.12; A-NFC: M=3.73, SD=1.5; NK vs. A-NFC: z=3.81,
200
p=0.0001, r=0.84; blind color NK: M=5.74, SD=1.42; A-NFC: M=3.95, SD=1.74; NK vs. A-NFC, z
201
10
= 3.72, p<0.0001, r=0.85). For both groups, artifacts with functional colors were judged as likely
202
to have consistent colors as the natural kinds but more likely compared to artifacts with non-
203
functional colors (for sighted color A-FC: M=5.55, SD=1.43; NK vs. A-FC: z=-0.65, p=0.52; A-
204
NFC vs. A-FC: z=3.78, p=0.0002, r=0.87; for blind color A-FC: M=5.92, SD=1.50; NK vs. A-FC: z
205
=1.03, p=0.3; A-NFC vs. A-FC: z=3.9, p<0.0001, r=0.87).
206
The interaction between group, question type, and object kind was non-significant (mixed
207
ordinal logistic regression, three-way interaction: =-0.15, SE=0.93, z=-0.16, p=0.88). The group-
208
by-condition interaction for color trials only were also not significant (for NK vs. A-NFC: =-0.07,
209
SE=0.36, z=-0.18, p=0.86, for A-FC vs. A-NFC: =0.52, SE=0.39, z=1.39, p=0.17). In sum, blind
210
and sighted people have similar understanding of the relationship between object kind and color.
211
Blind and sighted people’s causal explanations of object color (Experiment 3)
212
In Experiment 3, blind and sighted participants were asked to explain why each object has
213
its particular color. The explanations were coded according to what type of information they
214
appealed to: process, depends on…, just is that way, material, social, maker of the object, visibility
215
and cultural convention (see Supplementary Materials for coding details). Both blind and sighted
216
participants provided rich and coherent explanations of the cause of object color (Figure 4). Both
217
groups tended to provide different explanations for natural kinds, artifacts with non-functional
218
colors, and artifacts with functional colors. For natural kinds, both groups most often said “it just
219
is that way” (sighted: 33%, blind: 36%) or appealed to a process that give the object its color
220
(sighted: 32%, blind: 31%). For example, participants often described how the process of
221
photosynthesis makes plants green. By contrast for artifacts with non-functional colors (e.g. cars)
222
both blind and sighted participants appealed to people’s social and esthetic preferences (sighted:
223
64%, blind: 44%), and referred to the material of which the object was made (sighted: 18%, blind:
224
13%). For example, people frequently stated “personal preference” as a cause for cars, and for
225
cup, mentioned that they could be different colors depending on whether they are made of plastic,
226
porcelain, or metal. For artifacts with functional colors, participants most often appealed to cultural
227
11
convention (sighted: 57%, blind: 51%) and visibility (sighted: 24%, blind: 23%). For example, for
228
school bus, participants frequently mentioned tradition and history, and for stop sign, that the color
229
makes it easy to see.
230
We examined how similar explanations were across groups by computing Spearmans
231
correlation across groups within object kind. The frequencies of explanations by type were highly
232
correlated across groups for all three kinds of objects (natural kind: rho=0.99, p<0.0001; artifacts with
233
non-functional color: rho=0.72, p=0.03; artifacts with functional color: rho=0.97, p<0.0001).
234
Correlations across object kinds within each group were comparatively much lower (within sighted
235
group: natural vs. A-NFC: rho=-0.31, p=0.4; natural vs. A-FC: rho=-0.27, p=0.5; A-NFC vs. A-FC:
236
rho=0.78, p=0.01; within blind group: natural vs. A-NFC: rho=-0.02, p=1; natural vs. A-FC: rho=-
237
0.37, p=0.3; A-NFC vs. A-FC: rho=0.28, p=0.5).
238
239
Fig 4. Explanations about object color. Explanation types were coded by 5 different coders
240
who were blind to group and object. Stacked bar shows the frequency of each explanation type
241
12
as a proportion of all explanations provided for an object (within object type) across participants
242
(within a group). A detailed key of explanation types can be found in Supplementary Materials.
243
244
Discussion
245
A straightforward idea is that we acquire color knowledge through seeing. Consistent with
246
this, we find that people who have never seen are less likely to agree with each other and with
247
sighted people about associative color facts: although 100% of blind participants generate the
248
label ‘white’ for snow, only 50% say ‘yellow’ for bananas (see also 20, 21). This observation
249
suggests that when it comes to learning associative color facts, direct visual access is more
250
effective than linguistic communication.
251
By contrast, we find that inferentially rich color knowledge is shared among blind and
252
sighted individualsblind and sighted participants alike judge that two instances of a natural kind
253
(e.g. two bananas or two gems) are more likely to have the same color than two instances of an
254
artifact (e.g. two cars or two mugs). Blind and sighted people also provide similar explanations of
255
why real objects have the colors that they do, and these explanations vary systematically across
256
natural kinds and artifacts. For natural kinds, both blind and sighted appeal to an objects’ intrinsic
257
nature (e.g., “that’s just how it is”, “that’s nature”) or describe processes such as photosynthesis,
258
growth, or evolution. For artifacts, participants consistently cite individual or groups of people’s
259
needs and intentions (e.g., culture, aesthetic preference, visibility). Blind individuals produce
260
coherent explanations for object color even when they do not agree with the sighted about the
261
typical color of that particular object type. For example, while both groups’ explanations for the
262
color of polar bears mention their arctic habitat, almost all sighted participants explain that their
263
white fur allows camouflage in the snow while some blind participants explain that they are black
264
to absorb heat in the cold. (Interestingly, polar bears indeed have black skin underneath their
265
transparent fur, and these features are thought to have evolved for both camouflage and heat
266
13
absorption) (33). Such cases provide an illustration of causal understanding of color that is
267
independent of knowing object-color associations.
268
Blind and sighted people’s intuitions about the relationship between kind and color go
269
beyond the natural kind/artifact distinction (34). Among artifacts, ratings of how important color is
270
to an artifact’s function are highly correlated with blind and sighted participants’ ratings of color
271
consistency. Explanations produced by sighted and blind adults also vary systematically by
272
artifact type. For household and personal items such as mugs and cars, participants appeal to
273
aesthetic preferences. For institution-related objects like police uniforms and dollar bills,
274
participants cite social need for recognition. For stop signs, participants appeal to visibility (e.g.,
275
“red because red jumps out and warns people to stop”). Across artifacts, sighted and blind alike
276
appeal to a range of causes such as camouflage, recognizability, cultural convention, symbolism,
277
history, and aesthetic preference.
278
Finally, sighted and blind people make similar color consistency inferences for novel
279
objects with which neither group has visual or linguistic experience. For example, both blind and
280
sighted participants judge that two instances of a novel gem (natural kind) would be more likely
281
to have the same color than two instances of a novel household gadget (artifact). Blind and
282
sighted people also make distinctions within novel artifacts, intuiting which are most likely to have
283
functionally relevant and therefore consistent colors (e.g. coins, toxic waste containers). Together,
284
this evidence suggests that people living in the same culture, regardless of their visual experience,
285
develop similar intuitive theories of color and use these theories to make inferences that go
286
beyond the data.
287
While the present evidence suggests that blind and sighted people alike have a coherent
288
and causal understanding of color, this understanding is likely to differ in substantial ways from
289
formal scientific color theories (35, 36, 12). Participants’ explanations of object colors did
290
sometimes cite scientifically studied processes (e.g., photosynthesis), but more commonly
291
consisted of informal justifications lacking mechanistic detail (e.g., “that’s just how it grows”, “it’s
292
14
nature”, “God made it that way”, “manufacturer decided to paint it that way”, “the material it’s made
293
of”). When more specific causes and processes are mentioned, they are often social and
294
historical, and unlikely to be taught through formal education (e.g., both blind and sighted
295
participants mentioned personality of the owner for cars and “the patriarchy” for the color of
296
wedding dresses). During development, sighted children’s beliefs about color depart
297
systematically from scientific knowledge. Children mistakenly believe that an object will continue
298
to have the same color even when the lighting source is changed, that objects emit their own
299
shadows, and that a green object will have a green shadow (37-39; see also 40). Children's
300
explanations about such phenomena omit crucial components, such as the source and nature of
301
light illuminating an object (37). Similar inconsistencies between scientific and intuitive theories
302
have been observed in numerous other knowledge domains (e.g., physics: 41, 1983; biology: 42;
303
psychology: 43). Even when educated adults and experts report strong confidence in their own
304
understanding, their explanations for how things work are coarse and incomplete (44). Future
305
work is needed to understand the ways in which intuitive theories of color among sighted and
306
blind people share features with and depart from scientific color theories.
307
Open questions remain about how blind and sighted people acquire causal intuitions about
308
color. Linguistic communication likely plays a crucial role. From a young age, children use
309
testimony as well as more implicit linguistic cues (e.g., labeling) to inform intuitive theories of
310
physical, biological, and mental phenomena (45, 1, 46). For many previously studied domains of
311
knowledge, language-induced learning could in principle piggyback on pre-existing structured
312
knowledge built through sensory observation. For example, learning that the earth is round might
313
piggyback on learning roundness through vision and touch (47). Even in the case of mental
314
phenomena, simulation of one’s own feelings and thoughts has been offered as a source of “first-
315
person” information about others’ minds (48, 49). Analogously, a sighted person might construct
316
a representation of a novel animal described as blue and large by referencing physical knowledge
317
previously built up through sensory experience of color and size (20). In the case of color
318
15
knowledge among blind individuals, there is no directly pertinent sensory information.
319
Nevertheless, inferentially rich knowledge is constructed through linguistic communication from
320
the ground up.
321
Recent text corpus analyses also find that language is a rich source of semantic
322
information, including that of physical appearance. Associative algorithms are able to extract
323
semantic information using word co-occurrence and word neighborhood statistics (e.g., 50-52,
324
22-23). The available evidence suggests, however, that people’s learning of appearance from
325
language differs in important respects from the statistical tracking used by current text analysis
326
algorithms. For example, in the case of animal appearance, people born blind know more about
327
shape, texture, and size, than what is extracted by co-occurrence tracking algorithms (22, 53).
328
People born blind appear to use taxonomy and habitat to infer physical characteristics rather than
329
relying purely on explicit statements about appearance (20). In the case of object color
330
consistency, it is not clear how tracking word co-occurrence alone would provide the correct
331
information. Analyses of object and color label co-occurrence suggest that object-color label co-
332
occurrence consistency does not line up with real-life object-color consistency, nor with sighted
333
people’s intuitions about the object’s actual color (23). For example, ‘crow’ co-occurs with ‘black’
334
and ‘white’ with similar frequencies. Nevertheless, we find that blind and sighted people’s
335
intuitions about color consistency are similar. Moreover, blind participants generate canonical
336
colors (i.e. black for crow) more often than non-canonical ones (i.e. white for crow), even when
337
the canonical and non-canonical colors are equally likely to co-occur with the object in text (23,
338
54).
339
One source of information blind individuals could use to arrive at color consistency is
340
generic language (e.g. tomatoes are red). Generics provide evidence that a property is pervasive
341
to an object, as opposed to specific to a particular instance of that object (e.g., 26, 55-57). For
342
example, hearing “this car is red,” as opposed to “tomatoes are red” and stop signs are red” could
343
provide evidence with respect to which objects tend to have a consistent color. Generic language
344
16
could also facilitate learning which of two possible color labels is the canonical one (e.g. this crow
345
is white vs. crows are black). Generic language alone cannot, however, explain how blind and
346
sighted people make similar judgments about novel objects, which they have not heard being
347
described in a generic sentence, or how people born blind generate coherent explanations of
348
color. Linguistic cues such as generic language, must make contact with early-emerging intuitive
349
theories and the inferential machinery to transform these theories in light of the linguistic evidence
350
(57-59). We hypothesize that people born blind use linguistic cues, such as generics, to fill in the
351
color-specific elements of intuitive theories about objects and their physical properties. For
352
example, hearing people talk about “favorite colors”, together with evidence that a particular
353
personal item (e.g. cars) varies in color, might lead one to conclude that personal items are
354
sometimes colored according to the preferences of the owner. Future work is needed to uncover
355
precisely how blind and sighted people use language as a source of information when
356
constructing intuitions about color. One important direction for future research is testing the
357
acquisition of such knowledge by blind and sighted children. Such studies would reveal exactly
358
when, how, and with what information such intuitions are constructed.
359
In summary, we find that blind and sighted individuals alike possess theory-like,
360
inferentially rich knowledge about the relationship between objects and their colors. These
361
intuitive theories of color support consistent generalizations in the face of limited information (e.g.,
362
for novel objects), invoke deep causes (e.g., object function), support the generation of
363
sophisticated explanations, apply to broad categories (e.g., all plants) as well as to specific
364
instances (e.g., polar bears), and are specific to color. Interestingly, such structured and
365
inferentially rich color knowledge appears to be more resilient to the lack of first-person sensory
366
experience than knowledge of associative color facts. This observation directly contradicts the
367
common intuition that blind people’s knowledge of color consists of meaningless arbitrary facts.
368
Language appears to support the updating of causal models much more robustly than it does the
369
acquisition of arbitrary facts.
370
17
371
Methods
372
373
Participants
374
375
Twenty congenitally blind (14F/6M, age: M=30.85, SD=10.59, years of education: M=15.4,
376
SD=2.23) and nineteen sighted (14F/5M, age: M=31.21, SD=11.21, years of education M=15.79,
377
SD=1.82) participants took part in the study (participant table can be found in Supplemental
378
Materials, Table S1). All blind participants reported no experience with color, shape, or motion,
379
and had at most minimal light perception. All blind participants were tested at the 2018 National
380
Federation of the Blind Convention in Orlando, Florida. Subtests of the Woodcock Johnson III
381
Tests of Achievements (Word ID, Word Attack, Synonyms, Antonyms, and Analogies) were
382
administered to sighted and blind participants, and anyone scoring below two SDs from their own
383
group’s mean was excluded from further analyses. This resulted in one sighted participant
384
(participant 20) being excluded. The study consisted of three experiments administered to all
385
participants within the same session. Experimental procedures were approved by the Johns
386
Hopkins Homewood Institutional Review Board, and all participants provided informed consent.
387
388
Experimental Procedures Overview
389
Experiment 1 and 3 queried knowledge of and inferences about the colors of real objects
390
(30 objects in Experiment 1, 24 in Experiment 3). In Experiment 2, participants made color
391
inferences about 15 novel objects. Experiment 2 was always administered first to prevent the real
392
object judgments from influencing inferences made about novel objects. Within each experiment,
393
two different trial orders were used, one for half of the participants within each group.
394
Experimenters read aloud instructions and trials, and participant answers were audio-recorded
395
and later transcribed for scoring. The full list of stimuli and instructions can be found in the
396
Appendix (Supplemental Materials).
397
18
Experiment 1: Knowledge of Real Object Colors
398
In each trial of Experiment 1, participants were asked two questions about an everyday
399
object (Fig. 1). Three types of questions were asked: color consistency (30 objects), usage
400
consistency (20 objects), and fillers (20 objects). Objects used for color trials were either natural
401
(10 objects) or manmade (20 objects), and manmade artifacts could have function-relevant color
402
(FC, 10 objects) or non-function-relevant color (NFC, 10 objects). Usage trials consisted of 10
403
natural kinds and 10 artifacts. On filler trials, participants were asked questions about non-color
404
features (size, shape, and texture). Filler trials consisted of 5 natural kinds and 15 artifacts in
405
order to balance the overall number of natural kind and manmade trials. The full list of items used
406
in color and usage trials can be found in main Figure 1.
407
On color trials, participants were first asked, “What is one common color of (a) [object
408
name]?”, followed by, “If you picked two [object name]s at random, how likely are they to be the
409
same color? Rate on a scale of 1 to 7 (1: ‘unlikely’, 3: ‘somewhat likely’, 5: ‘likely’, 7: ‘very likely’).”
410
411
For usage trials, the questions were, “What is one common thing you can do with (a/some)
412
[object name]?” and, “If you picked two people at random and asked them each to do something
413
with (a/some) [object name], how likely are they to do the same thing, on a scale of 1 to 7?” Usage
414
trials served as a control condition to ensure blind and sighted participants showed equivalent
415
performance and were willing to rate artifacts as having some consistent properties.
416
Experiment 2: Color inferences about novel objects
417
In Experiment 2, in order to elicit inferences about novel objects parallel to in Experiment
418
1, participants were first presented an “Explorer on an Island” scenario:
419
“Imagine that you’re an explorer, and on your travels, you’ve discovered an island in a
420
remote corner of the world… You learn that the people on this island call themselves Zorkas…
421
The Zorka people appear to have a highly advanced culture. They have their own language, tools,
422
machines, buildings, vehicles, foods, customs, and so on. The ecology on this island is also
423
19
different from what we’re used to: it has its own plant and animal life, unusual rocks, minerals,
424
and so on. You’re trying to learn about how things work on this island....”
425
Participants then heard 35 short vignettes, each of which described an encounter with a
426
novel object (natural kind, artifacts with functional color, and artifacts with non-functional color;
427
Fig. 1). In each trial, several appearance features were noted (e.g., “green gem that is spiky and
428
the size of a hand”). The object was then named (e.g., “The miners tell you that this gem is called
429
an Enly.”).
430
As in Experiment 1, participants were next asked to rate the likelihood that another
431
instance of the same object would have the same color (e.g., “How likely is it that the next time
432
you come across another Enly, it is also green?). In usage trials, the question asked the likelihood
433
that the novel object would be used in the same way if encountered at another time (e.g., “How
434
likely is it that the next time you come across another Irve, it is also being ripped out of the
435
ground?”). In addition, there were 10 filler trials (7 natural kind, 3 manmade objects), in which
436
participants were asked about the likely repeat occurrence of a non-color feature (e.g., shape,
437
texture, size).
438
Color trials consisted of 5 natural kinds (plant, algae, gem, liquid from a plant, fruit), 5
439
artifacts with function-relevant color (coin, road symbol, toxic waste container, ceremonial
440
clothing, clear substance being used to build a wall), and 5 artifacts with function-irrelevant color
441
(an odor-emitting gadget, roof cleaning machine, two devices with ambiguous functions).
442
Usage trials consisted of 5 natural kind (creature, boulder, stone, flower, plant) and 5
443
artifacts (machine that makes square holes, storage device, toy, machine that turns stones into
444
goo, and one contraption with ambiguous function).
445
Filler trials contained 7 natural kind (fruit, two creatures, rock, two plants, gem) and 3
446
artifacts (game device, type of pool, one contraption with ambiguous function).
447
Experiment 3: Explanations about the cause of object color
448
20
For an additional list of 24 real objects (8 natural kind, 9 manmade with functional color, 7
449
function-irrelevant color), we asked participants to report their common colors (as in Experiment
450
1). Common color reports for these 24 objects are collapsed with those from Experiment 1 in main
451
Figure 2. For these objects, we additionally asked why objects had the particular color (or colors)
452
that the participant provided: Why are [object name]s that/those color[s]?” Participants were
453
instructed to provide whatever explanation felt right to them. Participants were also asked whether
454
the object has different colored parts, and if an object’s color varies across instances, to report
455
the other colors. The answer to these questions were not analyzed for the present study.
456
Quantifying color naming agreement for real objects
457
Across Experiments 1 and 3, participants named the color of 54 objects (Fig. 1)
458
(Experiment 1: 30 objects, “What is one common color of…?” and Experiment 3: 24 objects,
459
“What is the most common color of…?”). For each object, we quantified naming agreement by
460
using the Simpson’s Diversity Index (SDI) (32, 20). For unique color words (1 to R) provided for
461
each object across all participants within a group (blind or sighted), a naming agreement score
462
was calculated according to the equation below. N is the total number of words used across
463
participants for each object, and n is the number of times each unique word (1 to R) was
464
provided. The index ranges for 0 to 1, where 0 indicates that the same color word was never
465
used by two participants (i.e., low color naming agreement), and 1 suggests all participants
466
provided the same color (i.e., high naming agreement).
467
    

  
468
Although participants were instructed to provide one color, a few participants provided
469
multiple colors (at most three, e.g., “red, white, and blue”). All of these colors were included in
470
the analysis. Further, a small proportion of participants said “I don’t know” or provided words
471
that were not typical color terms (dark, light, beige, neon). These responses were treated the
472
same as color terms (“I don’t know” was counted as one word, coded “IDK”). Since SDIs were
473
21
not normally distributed, they were log-transformed. To examine differences in color naming
474
agreement across groups, we then performed linear mixed effects regression on log-
475
transformed SDIs, using lmer in R (60), with objects as random effects.
476
Color consistency inference analysis
477
Consistency likelihood judgments were analyzed using ordinal logistic regression using
478
the ordinal (61) package in R. Participants and objects were always included as random effects,
479
and separate models were used in each analysis described (e.g., for real vs. novel objects).
480
We first compared group differences for natural kinds and artifacts with non-functional
481
color only, since artifacts with functional color are a special category. This also allowed us to
482
look at a group (blind vs. sighted) x object kind (natural vs. artifact) x trial type (color
483
vs. function) three-way interaction. Baselines were coded as sighted group, usage trial, and
484
artifact. We then compared across groups for color trials only, this time including all three kinds
485
of objects (natural, artifact with functional color, artifact with non-functional color), with sighted
486
group and artifact with non-functional color as the baseline.
487
Correlation with functional relevance of color for artifacts
488
We obtained ratings from Amazon Mechanical Turk (n=20) for the functional relevance
489
of color to artifacts. Participants were asked “How important is the color of a [object] to its
490
function?” and had to rate on a scale of 1 to 7 (not at all to very relevant). Artifacts designated
491
as ‘artifacts with functional colors’ were those that received an average rating of 4 or above,
492
and artifacts ‘non-functional colors’ all had ratings below 3 (Table S2). We correlated the
493
average functional relevance ratings for each object with the average color consistency
494
judgments, for blind and sighted groups separately (Spearman correlation).
495
Analysis of explanations
496
Explanation types were decided by the experimenters based on examining all the
497
explanations (while blind to group and object). We decided on 9 types of explanations: ‘process’,
498
22
‘depends on’, ‘just is’, ‘material’, ‘social/aesthetic’, ‘maker’, ‘visibility’, ‘convention’, and ‘I don’t
499
know’. A key of explanations can be found in Supplemental Materials (Table S3).
500
Explanations were coded by four coders who did not know which object or group each
501
explanation came from. Note, however, that in a small number of instances participants said
502
the object’s name in their explanations, and at other times, it was fairly easy to discern the
503
object from the explanation.
504
There was large variability in how many words participants used in their explanations
505
(range=1 to 165 words, M=13 words). This meant that each explanation (i.e., what one
506
participant said for one object) could contain multiple explanation types. For example, a
507
participants’ answer that the color of a wedding dress is due to “symbolism, or personal style”,
508
was coded as containing ‘convention’ (for symbolism) and ‘social/aesthetic’ (for personal style)
509
explanations. However, the same word or phrase (e.g., personal style) was never coded for
510
more than one explanation type.
511
Some participants gave lengthier explanations than others, without necessarily providing
512
additional information (e.g., often telling anecdotal stories to make a point). For wedding dress,
513
for instance, another participant explained: “well, there’s something about tradition, and white
514
being associated with purity and virginity and all that, but beyond that it’s just a matter of demand,
515
if you want a baby barf green wedding dress that’s your problem”. This explanation was also
516
coded with ‘convention’ and ‘social/aesthetic’.
517
Coding was then filtered according to the criteria that at least three out of four coders
518
have to agree. The first author (5th coder) made some additional changes, again keeping group
519
and objects blind, and overruled tagging for <5% explanations. After this process, the number
520
of explanation types per explanation (again, a single explanation from one participant for one
521
object) only ranged from 1-3 (mean=1.26).
522
We compared explanations across groups within each object kind. Within a group and
523
kind (e.g., sighted group, natural kinds), we calculated how frequently participants (across all
524
23
participants within group) used each of the 9 explanation types. The counts were then calculated
525
as a percentage of all explanations (within group and object kind). We then computed
526
Spearman’s correlations over the percentages (for 9 types) across groups, as well as across
527
object kinds within groups.
528
529
530
531
532
References
533
1. Gelman, S. A. (2009). Learning from others: Children's construction of concepts. Annual review
534
of psychology, 60, 115-140.
535
2. Lombrozo, T. (2019). “Learning by Thinking” in Science and in Everyday Life. In The scientific
536
imagination. Oxford University Press.
537
3. Barsalou, L. W. (1999). Perceptual symbol systems. Behavioral and brain sciences, 22(4), 577-
538
660.
539
4. Prinz, J. J. (2005). The return of concept empiricism. In Handbook of categorization in cognitive
540
science (pp. 679-695). Elsevier Science Ltd.
541
5. Machery, E. (2006). Two dogmas of neoempiricism. Philosophy Compass, 1(4), 398-412.
542
6. Spelke, E. S. (1998). Nativism, empiricism, and the origins of knowledge. Infant Behavior and
543
Development, 21(2), 181-200.
544
7. Carey, S. (2009). The origin of concepts. Oxford university press.
545
24
8. Meltzoff, A. N., & Gopnik, A. (2013). Learning about the mind from evidence: Children’s
546
development of intuitive theories of perception and personality. Understanding other
547
minds, 3, 19-34.
548
9. Locke, J. (1924). 1690. An essay concerning human understanding, 1.
549
10. Hume, D. (1938). An Abstract of a Treatise of Human Nature, 1740. CUP Archive.
550
11. Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal qualia. The Philosophical Quarterly (1950-), 32(127), 127-
551
136.
552
12. Jackson, F. (1986). What Mary didn't know. The Journal of Philosophy, 83(5), 291-295.
553
13. Dennett, D. C. (1993). Consciousness explained. Penguin uk.
554
14. Tye, M. (2000). Knowing what it is like: The ability hypothesis and the knowledge argument.
555
Protosociology, Collection of Essays for David Lewis.
556
15. Chalmers, D. J. (2004). 13 Phenomenal Concepts and the Knowledge Argument. There's
557
Something About Mary: Essays on phenomenal consciousness and Frank Jackson's
558
knowledge argument, 269.
559
16. Gleitman, L., & Landau, B. (1985). Language and experience: Evidence from the blind child.
560
17. Shepard, R. N., & Cooper, L. A. (1992). Representation of colors in the blind, color-blind, and
561
normally sighted. Psychological Science, 3(2), 97-104.
562
18. Marmor, G. S. (1978). Age at onset of blindness and the development of the semantics of
563
color names. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 25(2), 267278.
564
https://doi.org/10/dpdnkw
565
19. Saysani, A., Corballis, M. C., & Corballis, P. M. (2018). Colour envisioned: Concepts of colour
566
in the blind and sighted. Visual Cognition, 26(5), 382392. https://doi.org/10/ggmt29
567
25
20. Kim, J. S., Elli, G. V., & Bedny, M. (2019a). Knowledge of animal appearance among sighted
568
and blind adults. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 116(23), 11213-
569
11222.
570
21. Connolly, A. C., Gleitman, L. R., & Thompson-Schill, S. L. (2007). Effect of congenital
571
blindness on the semantic representation of some everyday concepts. Proceedings of the
572
National Academy of Sciences, 104(20), 8241-8246.
573
22. Lewis, M., Zettersten, M., & Lupyan, G. (2019). Distributional semantics as a source of visual
574
knowledge. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 116(39), 19237-19238.
575
23. Ostarek, M., Van Paridon, J., & Montero-Melis, G. (2019). Sighted people’s language is not
576
helpful for blind individuals’ acquisition of typical animal colors. Proceedings of the
577
National Academy of Sciences, 116(44), 21972-21973.
578
24. Keil, F. C., Smith, W. C., Simons, D. J., & Levin, D. T. (1998). Two dogmas of conceptual
579
empiricism: Implications for hybrid models of the structure of knowledge. Cognition, 65(2-
580
3), 103-135.
581
25. Keil, F. C. (1992). Concepts, kinds, and cognitive development. mit Press.
582
26. Gelman, S. A. (2003). The essential child: Origins of essentialism in everyday thought. Oxford
583
University Press, USA.
584
27. Greif, M. L., Nelson, D. G., & Kemler, K. FC, & Gutierrez, F.(2006). What do children want to
585
know about animals and artifacts, 455-459.
586
28. Gelman, S. A. (1988). The development of induction within natural kind and artifact categories.
587
Cognitive psychology, 20(1), 65-95.
588
29. Bloom, P. (1996). Intention, history, and artifact concepts. Cognition, 60(1), 1-29.
589
26
30. Springer, K., & Keil, F. C. (1991). Early differentiation of causal mechanisms appropriate to
590
biological and nonbiological kinds. Child development, 62(4), 767-781.
591
31. Gerstenberg, T., & Tenenbaum, J. B. (2017). Intuitive theories. Oxford handbook of causal
592
reasoning, 515-548.
593
32. Majid, A., Roberts, S. G., Cilissen, L., Emmorey, K., Nicodemus, B., O’grady, L., ... & Shayan,
594
S. (2018). Differential coding of perception in the world’s languages. Proceedings of the
595
National Academy of Sciences, 115(45), 11369-11376.
596
33. Grojean, R. E., Sousa, J. A., & Henry, M. C. (1980). Utilization of solar radiation by polar
597
animals: an optical model for pelts. Applied Optics, 19(3), 339-346.
598
34. Keil, F. C., Greif, M. L., & Kerner, R. S. (2007). A world apart: How concepts of the constructed
599
world are different in representation and in development. Creations of the mind: Theories
600
of artifacts and their representation, 231-245.
601
35. Conceptual differences between children and adults. Mind & Language, 3(3), 167-181.
602
36. Keil, F. C. (2010). The feasibility of folk science. Cognitive science, 34(5), 826-862.
603
37. Feher, E., & Meyer, K. R. (1992). Children's conceptions of color. Journal of research in
604
Science Teaching, 29(5), 505-520.
605
38. Naranjo Correa, F. L., Martinez Borreguero, G., Perez Rodriguez, A. L., Suero Lopez, M. I.,
606
& Pardo Fernandez, P. J. (2016). A new online tool to detect color misconceptions. Color
607
Research & Application, 41(3), 325-329.
608
39. Anderson, C. W., & Smith, E. L. (1986). Children's Conceptions of Light and Color:
609
Understanding the Role of Unseen Rays. Research Series No. 166.
610
40. Cohen, J., & Nichols, S. (2010). Colours, colour relationalism and the deliverances of
611
introspection. Analysis, 70(2), 218-228.
612
27
41. McCloskey, M. (1983). Intuitive physics. Scientific american, 248(4), 122-131.
613
42. IInagaki, K., & Hatano, G. (2006). Young children's conception of the biological world. Current
614
Directions in Psychological Science, 15(4), 177-181.
615
43. Malle, B. F., Knobe, J. M., & Nelson, S. E. (2007). Actor-observer asymmetries in explanations
616
of behavior: New answers to an old question. Journal of Personality and Social
617
Psychology, 93(4), 491.
618
44. Rozenblit, L., & Keil, F. (2002). The misunderstood limits of folk science: An illusion of
619
explanatory depth. Cognitive science, 26(5), 521-562.
620
45. Harris, P. L., Koenig, M. A., Corriveau, K. H., & Jaswal, V. K. (2018). Cognitive foundations of
621
learning from testimony. Annual Review of Psychology, 69, 251-273.
622
46. Gelman, S. A., & Roberts, S. O. (2017). How language shapes the cultural inheritance of
623
categories. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 114(30), 7900-7907.
624
47. Vosniadou, S., & Brewer, W. F. (1992). Mental models of the earth: A study of conceptual
625
change in childhood. Cognitive psychology, 24(4), 535-585.
626
48. Gordon, R. M. (1986). Folk psychology as simulation. Mind & language, 1(2), 158-171.
627
49. Gallese, V., & Goldman, A. (1998). Mirror neurons and the simulation theory of mind-reading.
628
Trends in cognitive sciences, 2(12), 493-501.
629
50. Bruni, E., Boleda, G., Baroni, M., & Tran, N. K. (2012, July). Distributional semantics in
630
technicolor. In Proceedings of the 50th Annual Meeting of the Association for
631
Computational Linguistics: Long Papers-Volume 1 (pp. 136-145). Association for
632
Computational Linguistics.
633
28
51. Grand, G., Blank, I. A., Pereira, F., & Fedorenko, E. (2018). Semantic projection: recovering
634
human knowledge of multiple, distinct object features from word embeddings. arXiv
635
preprint arXiv:1802.01241.
636
52. Rubinstein, D., Levi, E., Schwartz, R., & Rappoport, A. (2015, July). How well do distributional
637
models capture different types of semantic knowledge?. In Proceedings of the 53rd Annual
638
Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics and the 7th International Joint
639
Conference on Natural Language Processing (Volume 2: Short Papers) (pp. 726-730).
640
53. Kim, J. S., Elli, G. V., & Bedny, M. (2019b). Reply to Lewis et al.: Inference is key to learning
641
appearance from language, for humans and distributional semantic models alike.
642
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 116(39), 19239-19240.
643
54. Kim, J. S., Elli, G. V., & Bedny, M. (2019c). Reply to Ostarek et al.: Language, but not co-
644
occurrence statistics, is useful for learning animal appearance. Proceedings of the
645
National Academy of Sciences, 116(44), 21974-21975.
646
55. Cimpian, A., Brandone, A. C., & Gelman, S. A. (2010). Generic statements require little
647
evidence for acceptance but have powerful implications. Cognitive science, 34(8), 1452-
648
1482.
649
56. Tessler, M. H., & Goodman, N. D. (2019). The language of generalization. Psychological
650
review, 126(3), 395.
651
57. Brandone, A. C., & Gelman, S. A. (2009). Differences in preschoolers’ and adults’ use of
652
generics about novel animals and artifacts: A window onto a conceptual divide. Cognition,
653
110(1), 1-22.
654
58. Csibra, G., & Gergely, G. (2009). Natural pedagogy. Trends in cognitive sciences, 13(4), 148-
655
153.
656
29
59. Shafto, P., Goodman, N. D., & Frank, M. C. (2012). Learning from others: The consequences
657
of psychological reasoning for human learning. Perspectives on Psychological Science,
658
7(4), 341-351.
659
60. Bates D, Mächler M, Bolker B, Walker S (2015). “Fitting Linear Mixed-Effects Models Using
660
lme4.” Journal of Statistical Software, 67(1).
661
61. Christensen RHB (2019). “ordinal—Regression Models for Ordinal Data .” R package version
662
2019.12-10. https://CRAN.R-project.org/package=ordinal.
663
Acknowledgments: We thank the National Federation of the Blind convention, the blind
664
community, and all of our participants for making this research possible; Funding: This work was
665
supported by the National Institutes of Health (R01 EY027352 to M.B.) and the Johns Hopkins
666
University Catalyst Grant (to M.B.); J.S.K was funded by the William Orr Dingwall Dissertation
667
Fellowship; Author contributions: J.S.K, B.A, V.M, and M.B. designed research; J.S.K, B.A, and
668
V.M, performed research, J.S.K analyzed data, and J.S.K and M.B. wrote the paper; Competing
669
interests: Authors declare no competing interests; and Data and materials availability: All data,
670
code, and materials used in the analysis are available in the repository:
671
https://github.com/judyseinkim/Intuitive-Theories-of-Color and a detailed description of analyses
672
can be found in the following document: https://rpubs.com/judyseinkim/color_theory .
673
... How precisely word co-occurrence drives knowledge is still a matter of debate, with strong arguments supporting both a 'lower level' associative learning component alongside a 'higher level' inferential one (Lewis et al., 2019;Kim et al., 2019a, b). Blind individuals also demonstrate sophisticated understanding of color stability (Kim et al., 2020). In one task, blind and sighted participants were asked about color consistency (e.g., "If you picked two lemons/cars at random, how likely are they to be the same color?"). ...
... Although blind individuals demonstrate rich, detailed knowledge of the color or appearance of common objects (Kim et al., 2020;Kim et al., 2019a, b;Landau and Gleitman, 1985), they appear to weigh this information less heavily than sighted individuals in, e.g. semantic similarity judgments. ...
... What should be surprising is not that blind individuals (who by definition have never had direct perceptual access to visual properties like color) perform less well on tasks of visual property knowledge than sighted ones, but that they perform surprisingly similarly to sighted adults given only indirect access to visual information. As reviewed above, blind individuals have acquired visual knowledge about associations between properties (e.g., that cold is blue; Saysani et al., 2021), the appearance of many objects and animals (Kim et al., 2019a, b;Kim et al., 2020), and how stable object color is for different categories (Kim et al., 2020). This in turn raises the possibility that sighted individuals too rely to a great degree on indirect routes like language co-occurrence statistics and inferences licensed by language in concert with directly perceivable input to build their color knowledge. ...
Article
The present article provides a narrative review on how language communicates sensory information and how knowledge of sight and sound develops in individuals born deaf or blind. Studying knowledge of the perceptually inaccessible sensory domain for these populations offers a lens into how humans learn about that which they cannot perceive. We first review the linguistic strategies within language that communicate sensory information. Highlighting the power of language to shape knowledge, we next review the detailed knowledge of sensory information by individuals with congenital sensory impairments, limitations therein, and neural representations of imperceptible phenomena. We suggest that the acquisition of sensory knowledge is supported by language, experience with multiple perceptual domains, and cognitive and social abilities which mature over the first years of life, both in individuals with and without sensory impairment. We conclude by proposing a developmental trajectory for acquiring sensory knowledge in the absence of sensory perception.
Article
Significance We learn in a variety of ways: through direct sensory experience, by talking with others, and by thinking. Disentangling how these sources contribute to what we know is challenging. A wedge into this puzzle was suggested by empiricist philosophers, who hypothesized that people born blind would lack deep knowledge of “visual” phenomena such as color. We find that, contrary to this prediction, congenitally blind and sighted individuals share in-depth understanding of object color. Blind and sighted people share similar intuitions about which objects will have consistent colors, make similar predictions for novel objects, and give similar explanations. Living among people who talk about color is sufficient for color understanding, highlighting the efficiency of linguistic communication as a source of knowledge.
Article
Full-text available
Maximum likelihood or restricted maximum likelihood (REML) estimates of the parameters in linear mixed-effects models can be determined using the lmer function in the lme4 package for R. As for most model-fitting functions in R, the model is described in an lmer call by a formula, in this case including both fixed- and random-effects terms. The formula and data together determine a numerical representation of the model from which the profiled deviance or the profiled REML criterion can be evaluated as a function of some of the model parameters. The appropriate criterion is optimized, using one of the constrained optimization functions in R, to provide the parameter estimates. We describe the structure of the model, the steps in evaluating the profiled deviance or REML criterion, and the structure of classes or types that represents such a model. Sufficient detail is included to allow specialization of these structures by users who wish to write functions to fit specialized linear mixed models, such as models incorporating pedigrees or smoothing splines, that are not easily expressible in the formula language used by lmer.
Chapter
This chapter introduces “learning by thinking” (LbT) as a form of learning distinct from familiar forms of learning through observation. When learning by thinking, the learner gains genuinely new insight in the absence of novel observations “outside the head.” Scientific thought experiments are canonical examples, but the phenomenon is much more widespread, and includes learning by explaining to oneself, through analogical reasoning, or through mental simulation. The chapter argues that episodes of LbT can be re-expressed as explicit arguments or inferences but are neither psychologically nor epistemically reducible to explicit arguments or inferences, and that this partially explains the novelty of the conclusions reached through LbT. It also introduces a new perspective on the epistemic value of LbT processes as practices with potentially beneficial epistemic consequences, even when the commitments they invoke and the conclusions they immediately deliver are not themselves true.
Article
Language provides simple ways of communicating generalizable knowledge to each other (e.g., "Birds fly," "John hikes," and "Fire makes smoke"). Though found in every language and emerging early in development, the language of generalization is philosophically puzzling and has resisted precise formalization. Here, we propose the first formal account of generalizations conveyed with language that makes quantitative predictions about human understanding. The basic idea is that the language of generalization expresses that an event or a property occurs relatively often, where what counts as relatively often depends upon one's prior expectations. We formalize this simple idea in a probabilistic model of language understanding, which we test in 3 diverse case studies: generalizations about categories (generic language), events (habitual language), and causes (causal language). We find that the model explains the gradience in human endorsements that has perplexed previous attempts to formalize this swath of linguistic expressions. This work opens the door to understanding precisely how abstract knowledge is learned from language.
Article
Imagine you were born completely blind, what would your understanding of colour be? Here we address this question, which hitherto has had no substantive answer. We asked samples of congenitally blind, adventitiously blind, and normally sighted (trichromatic) adults to rate the dissimilarities of pairs of colour terms. We then used multidimensional scaling to generate perceptual maps based on these dissimilarity ratings. The resulting maps were strikingly similar across groups. All groups were able to organize both basic and descriptive colour terms into a pattern resembling the trichromatic colour space, with only minor differences between the maps generated by the congenitally blind group and those generated by the adventitiously blind and sighted groups. These results suggest that the semantic associates of colour can exert a profound influence on how the blind understand colour terms and relationships. Furthermore, they also suggest that colour memory is well preserved in the adventitiously blind, despite prolonged blindness.
Article
Humans acquire much of their knowledge from the testimony of other people. An understanding of the way that information can be conveyed via gesture and vocalization is present in infancy. Thus, infants seek information from well-informed interlocutors, supply information to the ignorant, and make sense of communicative acts that they observe from a third-party perspective. This basic understanding is refined in the course of development. As they age, children’s reasoning about testimony increasingly reflects an ability not just to detect imperfect or inaccurate claims but also to assess what inferences may or may not be drawn about informants given their particular situation. Children also attend to the broader characteristics of particular informants—their group membership, personality characteristics, and agreement or disagreement with other potential informants. When presented with unexpected or counterintuitive testimony, children are prone to set aside their own prior convictions, but they may sometimes defer to informants for inherently social reasons. Expected final online publication date for the Annual Review of Psychology Volume 69 is January 4, 2018. Please see http://www.annualreviews.org/page/journal/pubdates for revised estimates.
Article
It is widely recognized that language plays a key role in the transmission of human culture, but relatively little is known about the mechanisms by which language simultaneously encourages both cultural stability and cultural innovation. This paper examines this issue by focusing on the use of language to transmit categories, focusing on two universal devices: labels (e.g., shark, woman) and generics (e.g., "sharks attack swimmers"; "women are nurturing"). We propose that labels and generics each assume two key principles: norms and essentialism. The normative assumption permits transmission of category information with great fidelity, whereas essentialism invites innovation by means of an open-ended, placeholder structure. Additionally, we sketch out how labels and generics aid in conceptual alignment and the progressive "looping" between categories and cultural practices. In this way, human language is a technology that enhances and expands the categorization capacities that we share with other animals.
Article
Discussion sur la nature de la " psychologie populaire " (folk psychology). L'A. se concentre sur le probleme de la prediction d'un comportement (de soi-meme, et des autres) et examine, dans cette optique, le raisonnement hypothetico-deductif, ainsi que sur le probleme de l'attribution des croyances. L'A. soutient que meme si la psychologie populaire n'est pas une theorie mais une capacite de raisonnement pratique, elle demeure une alternative