ArticlePDF Available

Causality, Confounding, and Simpson’s Paradox

Authors:

Abstract and Figures

This is an introductory article which explains the importance of explicit consideration and modeling of causality, contrary to current econometric practice, in order to use data set for extraction of meaningful information. One of the easiest to understand approaches to causality is via Simpson’s paradox. We will use this paradox, framed in different real-world contexts, to provide an introduction to basic concepts of causality.
Content may be subject to copyright.
Zaman and Salahuddin-Causality, Confounding, and Simpson’s Paradox
50
Causality, Confounding, and Simpson’s Paradox
Asad Zaman and Taseer Salahuddin
Received: 11.01.2020
Accepted: 04.04.2020
Published: 30.04.2020
doi: 10.33818/ier.687042
ABSTRACT
This is an introductory article which explains the importance of explicit consideration and
modeling of causality, contrary to current econometric practice, in order to use data set for
extraction of meaningful information. One of the easiest to understand approaches to
causality is via Simpson’s paradox. We will use this paradox, framed in different real-world
contexts, to provide an introduction to basic concepts of causality.
Key words: Simpson’s Paradox, Causality, Econometrics, Confounders, Mediators
JEL Classifications: C0, C1
1. INTRODUCTION
Bitter fighting among Christian factions and immoral behavior among Church leaders led to a
transition to secular thought in Europe (see Zaman, 2018, for details). One of the consequences
of rejection of religion was the rejection of all unobservables. Empiricists like David Hume
rejected all knowledge which was not based on observations and logic. He famously stated that:
“If we take in our hand any volume; of divinity or school metaphysics; for instance, let us ask,
does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain any
experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the
flames: for it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion.” David Hume further realized that
causality was not observable. This means that it is observable that event Y happened after event
X, but it is not observable that Y happened due to X. The underlying mechanisms which connect
X to Y are not observable. In the early 20th Century, the philosophy of logical positivism which
says that human knowledge is based solely on observations and logic became widely accepted
and wildly popular. Disciplines like Statistics and Econometrics, which evolved during 20th
century, were built on positivist foundations. They only deal with measurable and observable
(numbers) and ignore immeasurable concepts like causality. A much more detailed discussion
of the philosophical background which led to these widespread misconceptions about human
knowledge is given in Zaman (2012).
Pearl et. al. (2016, Chapter 2) provide a history of how mistakes by the founders of the discipline
led to replacement of causality by correlation in statistics. Pearl and Mackenzie (2018, Chapter
5) provides the history of how causal information was dropped from econometric models.
Current econometric techniques do not allow us to distinguish between real and spurious
Asad Zaman, Professor of Economics, Former Vice Chancellor, Pakistan Institute of Development Economics,
Islamabad, Pakistan (email: asad.zaman@alumni.stanford.edu), Tel: +92 334 5164905.
Taseer Salahuddin, Assistant Professor of Economics, Government Sadiq College Women University,
Bahawalpur, Pakistan (email: salahuddin.taseer@gmail.com), Tel: +92 3036660871
International Econometric Review (IER)
51
relationships. Excellent and robust fits can be seen between totally unrelated variables like log
of number of newspapers published and life expectancy; there is no way to tell if a regression
is real or spurious. How do we differentiate between a regression of Turkish Consumption on
Turkish GDP, which has a strong causal basis, and one of GNP on Newspapers, which is purely
correlation without causation? Many examples like these are discussed in Zaman (2010), which
show serious confusions about causality in conventional econometrics, and resulting
consequences in terms of defective analysis.
This is an introductory article which explains the importance of explicit consideration and
modeling of causality, contrary to current econometric practice, in order to use data set for
extraction of meaningful information. One of the easiest to understand approaches to causality
is via Simpson’s paradox. We will use this paradox, framed in different real-world contexts, to
provide an introduction to basic concepts of causality.
2. THE BERKELEY ADMISSION CASE
Suppose there are two departments Engineering (ENG) and Humanities (HUM), which have
differing admissions policies. Due to these policies, 80% of female applicants to ENG are
admitted, while only 40% of the female applicants are admitted in HUM. To understand
Simpson’s Paradox, it is essential to understand the relation between these departmental
admissions rates, and the overall admit rate for females in Berkeley. Assuming, for simplicity,
that these are the only two departments, we ask: What is the OVERALL admission rate for
female applicants at Berkeley? The answer is that the overall admit ratio is the weighted average
of the two admission percentages (80% and 40%). Table 1.1 shows overall admit rate of females
with different number of applicants.
Engineering
Humanities
Situations
Applied
Admitted
% Admitted
Applied
Admitted
% Admitted
Applied
Admitted
% Admitted
A
1800
1440
80%
200
80
40%
2000
1520
76%
B
1500
1200
80%
500
200
40%
2000
1400
70%
C
1000
800
80%
1000
400
40%
2000
1200
60%
D
500
400
80%
1500
600
40%
2000
1000
50%
E
200
160
80%
1800
720
40%
2000
880
44%
Table 1.1 Overall admit rate for Female applicants.
If all females apply to HUM and none to ENG then overall admit rate is 40%. If all females
apply to ENG then overall admit rate for females will be 80%. The table shows that the overall
admit rate for females can vary from 40% to 80% depending upon proportions of females which
apply to the two departments.
Now suppose Berkeley systematically discriminates against males. For male applicants to ENG,
the admit ratio is only 60%, much lower than the 80% ratio for females. For male applicants to
HUM, the admit ratio is only 20%, much lower than the 40% for females. What will the overall
admit rate for males be? As before, this will be a weighted average of the two rates 20% and
60%, where the weights will be the proportion of male applicants to the two departments. The
Zaman and Salahuddin-Causality, Confounding, and Simpson’s Paradox
52
table below shows how the overall admissions ratio varies depending on how many males apply
to which department:
Engineering
Humanities
Situations
Applied
Admitted
% Admitted
Applied
Admitted
% Admitted
Applied
Admitted
% Admitted
A
1800
1080
60%
200
40
20%
2000
1120
56%
B
1500
900
60%
500
100
20%
2000
1000
50%
C
1000
600
60%
1000
200
20%
2000
800
40%
D
500
300
60%
1500
300
20%
2000
600
30%
E
200
120
60%
1800
360
20%
2000
480
24%
Table 1.2 Overall admit rate for male applicants.
The table shows that the overall admit rate for males can vary between 20% and 60% according
to how the applicants are distributed between ENG and HUM. We have already seen that overall
admit rates for females can vary between 40% and 80%. Now consider the scenario created by
the highlighted rows in the table. If 90% of the females apply to HUM, then the female admit
ratio will be 44%, close to the 40% admit ratio for females in HUM. If 90% of the males apply
to ENG then the admit ratio for males will be 56%, close to the 60% admit ratio for males in
ENG. Despite the fact that females are heavily favored in both ENG and in HUM, the overall
admit ratio for females (44%) will be much lower than the admit ratio for males (56%).
Someone who looks only at the overall admit ratio for males and females will come to the
conclusion that Berkeley discriminates against females, which is the opposite of the picture that
emerges when looking at departmental admit ratios. This is known as the Simpson’s Paradox.
Interestingly, this is not a hypothetical example. I have simplified the numbers to make the
analysis easier to follow, but the actual data for Berkeley admissions follows a similar pattern.
The overall admit rates appear to show bias against females. Bickel et. al. (1975) carry out a
standard statistical analysis of aggregate admissions data. They test the hypothesis of equality
of admit rates for males and females and conclude that males have significantly higher
admissions ratio than females. A causal analysis of data attempts to answer the “WHY”
question. Why is the admit rate for males higher? To try to learn why the male admit rate was
higher, Bickel et. al. (1975) looked at the breakdown by department. Note that the data
themselves furnish us with no clue as to what else we need to look at. It is our real-world
knowledge about colleges, admissions process, departments, which suggests that department-
wise analysis might lead to deeper insights. This shows how real-world knowledge, which goes
beyond the data, matters for data analysis. Doing the analysis on the departmental level leads
to an unexpected finding each department discriminates in favor of women. Philosophers call
this “counter-phenomenal”. The phenomena the observation at the aggregate level suggests
that Berkeley discriminates against women. But a deeper probe into reality reveals that the
opposite is true. This shows the necessity of going beyond the surface appearances, the
observations, to deeper structures of reality, in order to understand the phenomena. This is in
conflict with Empiricist ideas that observations by themselves are sufficient, and we do not
need to probe deeper. See Zaman (2020, Models and Reality, this issue) for a more detailed
discussion of the philosophical background.
International Econometric Review (IER)
53
When we discover a conflict between the phenomena and our exploration of the phenomena
the deeper and hidden structures of reality then we are faced with the necessity of explaining
this conflict. Because both departments discriminate against males, the explanation that
Berkeley admissions process discriminates against females is no longer acceptable. Bickel et.
al. (1975) do the data analysis and come up with the deeper explanation. ENG is easier to get
into, and HUM is more difficult. Females choose to apply to the more difficult department and
hence end up with lower admit ratios. Males choose to apply to the easier department, and hence
have higher admit ratios. The search for causal explanations does not stop here. We can then
ask: WHY do females choose humanities? We can also ask: WHY is ENG easier to get into,
and WHY is HUM more difficult to get into? For both of these questions, there are several
possible hypotheses which could be true, and which could be explored using data or qualitative
techniques. In the next section, we consider some other causal structures for admissions, which
lead to radically different answers to the WHY questions, even though the observed data
remains exactly the same.
Exercise 1: Even though causality concepts are relatively easy, lack of familiarity leads to
difficulties in grasping them. For this purpose, it is useful to grapple with them directly via
exercises. Suppose that there are two main hospitals A and B in a small city. For patients
admitted to hospital A, recovery rates are 44% - less than half recover. On the other hand, 56%
of the patients admitted to hospital B recover. On the basis of these numbers, it appears that
hospital B is the better of the two, with higher recovery rates. Think of a hidden factor which
might reverse this comparison. Create an example of Simpson’s Paradox by making up data
categorized along the hidden factor which shows the paradox.
2.1. Distinguishing Between Confounders and Mediators
Before the impact of changing causal structures on analysis can be understood two different
points need to be made. Firstly, as noted by Pearl and Mackenzie (2018) and Hoover (2004), a
major obstacle to development of causal thinking has been the lack of mathematical notation to
express causality. In particular, the “equal sign” in a regression model (C=a+bY) does not
give us a clue that Y is a cause of C, and encourages the mistaken algebra that Y=(C/b)(a/b),
which is not correct as a causal equation. One of the critical factors in the development of
understanding about causality has been the development of a natural language to express causal
relationships. This is the language of path diagrams, which we now introduce. The causal
structure of the explanation given by Bickel et. al. (1975) for Simpson’s Paradox in Berkeley
admissions can be depicted in the following path diagram (Figure 2.1).
Figure 2.1 Causal Map # 1A (Bickel)
Here gender affects both the choice of department and admit ratio. Department also affects
admit ratio. The causal path diagram is crucial in determining exogeneity and endogeneity.
These are key concepts used in Econometrics, but they remain confusing because they cannot
be defined correctly without understanding causality. Path diagrams are required to distinguish
between the two cases. Furthermore, as we will see later, this classification is not sufficient for
Department
Admit ratio
Gender
Zaman and Salahuddin-Causality, Confounding, and Simpson’s Paradox
54
analysis. Among endogenous variables we must distinguish between mediators and colliders,
as the two cases require different analysis. In this section, we will explain the difference
between exogenous variables and endogenous variables within the context of the Berkeley
Admissions case under discussion.
When we are studying the effect of gender on admissions, the above diagram shows that there
are two causal pathways. One is the direct effect of gender on admissions. This effect leads to
a 20% increase in chances of admissions over the admissions rate for males. The second is the
indirect affect which operates via the choice of department. ENG is easier to get into, and HUM
is harder. If gender influences choice of department, so that females choose the harder
department while male choose the easier one, then this will create an adverse impact on
admissions. The total effect will be the sum of the two effects, direct and indirect. In this causal
path diagram, the department is called the mediator; it acts a mediator of the effect of gender
on admissions.
In terms of econometrics, think about the Admit Ratio as the variable to be explained, and
Gender and Department as the explanatory variables. Modeling admissions via a function like
AR=f(G,D,GxD) will not correctly capture the causal relationships. The coefficients of
Gender, Department, and interaction terms will not correctly represent the impacts of the three
variables on the admissions rate, because these do not take into account the one-way causal
path between Gender and Department. Structural Equation Models (SEM) can capture such
relationships and potentially lead to the right analysis, although current practice does not utilize
SEM for causal modeling.
In this same diagram, we can also study how admissions policies vary across departments.
Gender affects both Department and Admissions. The causal path diagram is the same as the
previous one, but the question of interest is now different
Figure 2.2 Causal Map # 1B (Dept → Admissions)
The path diagram shows that Gender influences both Department choice and the admit ratio,
but it is NOT influenced by either of these variables. This makes Gender exogenous. To be
more precise: When we are studying the effect of department on the admission ratio, gender is
exogenous because it is not causally influenced by either of the two variables under study.
Statisticians say that Gender is a confounding variable, but are equally confused about the
meaning of confounding, because understanding it requires causality. To solve this problem of
confounding, we must CONDITION on gender. In the language of econometrics, exogeneity
means that we can condition on this variable, treating it as constant. Holding gender constant -
- i.e. separately calculating admit rates for both genders allows us to calculate the effect of
department choice on admit ratio, while preventing the confounding variable from changing,
so as to eliminate its effects.
Gender
Admit ratio
Department
International Econometric Review (IER)
55
Exercise 2: Consider the hospital example of exercise one. Suppose there are two types of
patients critical and non-critical. This has a direct impact on recovery rates, with critical
patients having lower recovery rates. Suppose hospital A is better equipped to deal with critical
patients, so whenever possible, critical patients choose to go to hospital A. Recovery rates are
different at hospitals A and B, and hospital A is better at dealing with both kinds of patients.
Nonetheless, overall recovery rates are higher at hospital B. Answer the following questions
1. Draw a causal path diagram connecting Patients (critical and non-critical) to recovery
rates. According to your diagram, is the hospital a mediator or a confounder? Give a
verbal explanation of the paradox using the conflict two factors which affect recovery
rates, or the two causal pathways.
2. Suppose we wish to evaluate the performance of the hospitals. Draw a diagram
connecting Hospital to Recovery Rates. Is the type of “patient” a mediator or a
confounder in this diagram? Explain how ignoring the confounder will lead to
misleading comparison of hospital performance. Also explain how conditioning on the
confounder leads to a correct analysis.
2.2. Calculating Probabilities on Decision Tree
Consider the problem of calculating the effects of Gender (G) and Department (D) on
Admissions Rates (AR). In regression terminology, both G and D are exogenous regressors,
while the dependent variable is AR. In regression methodology, there is no way to express the
fact that G influences D. Furthermore, the observed data distributions remain the same in the
three cases where G D, D G, and where both are independent. In the causal case under
consideration, where Gender influences choice of Department, calculating the effect of Gender
on admissions rate requires the use of a decision tree, as we now illustrate. On the other hand,
if we want to calculate the effect of department on admission rate, standard regression
methodology works well. In effect, regression methodology conditions on gender, and
calculates the partial effect of department on admission while holding gender constant. The
tabled numbers, which show 80% and 60% admissions rates for females and males in ENG,
and 40% and 20% in HUM, correctly display the impact of department on admissions holding
gender constant. On the other hand, these tables do not provide the right picture when we want
to calculate the effect of gender on the admissions rate. To calculate the impact of gender on
admissions, we must take into account both channels by which gender affects admissions. This
can be done conveniently via a decision tree diagram, as we now illustrate. Say for example
John and Jane apply to Berkeley. The following tree diagrams show how we can calculate the
probabilities of admissions for the two via separate tree diagrams.
Only 10% females choose Engineering, where they have 80% chances of admission and 90%
females choose Humanities but with only 40% chances of admission. Applying this past data,
we can estimate that Jane will apply to HUM with 90% probability and to ENG with 10%
probability. Using the admit rates for females in ENG and HUM, we can compute her chances
of getting admission as: 90% *40% + 10%*80% = 36% + 8% = 44%. This calculation is valid
under the assumption that the past history of admissions applies to Jane she is not
differentiated from the typical female applicant in ways which would make the history
irrelevant.
Zaman and Salahuddin-Causality, Confounding, and Simpson’s Paradox
56
Figure 2.3 Female Admit Probabilities Tree Diagram
For John, we have the same diagram, but the probabilities are different at each branch of the
tree for males.
Figure 2.4 Male Admit Probabilities Tree Diagram
John has a 10% chance of applying to HUM and a 90% chance of applying to ENG. In the two
departments, his admit probabilities are 20% and 60% respectively, so his overall admit
probability is 10% *20% + 90%*60% = 2% + 54% = 56%
These calculations show that the probability for females to get into Berkeley is only 44%, while
the probability for males is 56%. These aggregate numbers correctly reflect overall admit
probabilities categorized by Gender (without conditioning on the Department). On the other
hand, if the department choices for Jane and John are known, then entirely different
probabilities would apply. The question of when we should condition, and when we should not,
depends entirely on the research question we are trying to answer. There is considerable
confusion about this matter mainly because there is no way to explicitly take into account causal
information in conventional statistical and econometric analysis.
Exercise 3: Patients (critical and non-critical) choose hospitals, and this choice of hospitals
determines the recovery rates. Draw separate tree diagrams for critical and non-critical patients
showing probabilities of choice of hospitals, and recovery rates at each hospital, to get the
overall recovery rates for both types.
Females
Engineering
Humanities
Rejected
Accepted
Rejected
Accepted
90%
20%
80%
60%
40%
10%
Males
Engineering
Humanities
Rejected
Accepted
Rejected
Accepted
10%
40%
60%
80%
20%
90%
International Econometric Review (IER)
57
2.3. Changing Causal Structures
In the above given discussion, there is not one (gender) but two causal factors (gender and
difficulty level per department) that influence the admission rates. Being female is a positive
influencer in each department but applying to humanities is a strong negative influencer. As
men applied more to engineering their negative influencer (gender) was overwhelmed by their
positive influence of department choice (engineering). Bickel et. al. (1975) noted this paradox,
and provided this explanation. This explanation is just a conjecture about the causal factors
which affect admissions rates. It is possible that taking into account other causal factors (like
GPA) could lead to entirely different analysis of exactly the same data. For example, suppose
admissions policies at ENG and HUM are only based on GPA, but HUM is more difficult to
get into:
Admit Percent
Grade
ENG
HUM
A
90%
60%
B
70%
30%
C
50%
10%
If female applicant pool has better grades (i.e. 60% A’s, 30% B’s and 10% C’s) while male
applicant pool has significantly lower GPA’s (10% A’s, 30% B’s and 60% C’s), then exactly
same admission patterns will be observed. The original data appears to show gender bias
females are preferred. But deeper analysis reveals that there is no discrimination by gender. The
admissions criteria are the same for both genders, but more females get in because they have
higher grades. Now the causal question here would be why better male applicants do not apply
to Berkeley while better female applicants do? Answer may lie in availability of a good all-
male university which is not available for females. Or, one could construct examples where
females are better at English and males are better at math, and this provides the causal
explanation. Now these answers to the WHY questions do not come from numbers; we are
speculating about unobserved, real structural factors. This is the central point of the article:
numbers do not contain causal information, whereas understanding the numbers needs causal
understanding, which only comes from qualitative kinds of knowledge about deeper structures
of reality. Current econometric practices are deeply flawed because they can only be used to
describe correlations among observations, and do not take causal information into
consideration. Even worse, they encourage intellectual laziness among students, who are taught
to believe that running a regression yields reliable results without any considerations of causal
structures.
Exercise # 4: The discussion above sketches the possibility that admissions depend solely on
GPA, and female applicants have higher GPA, which is what accounts for apparent preference
for females. Create the statistics to go with this story, and complete the sketch of the data
provided in the first paragraph.
2.4. Policy Depends Upon Unobservable Causal Relations
As Hume realized a long time ago, observations cannot reveal the underlying causes. Studying
alternative hidden causal structures for the same data set could radically change the
interpretations discussed in previous sections. Understanding data REQUIRES understanding
causal structures which generate the data and these causal structures are not DIRECTLY
observable. Unfortunately, a strong intellectual tradition in the West supports a deeply mistaken
Zaman and Salahuddin-Causality, Confounding, and Simpson’s Paradox
58
understanding of scientific methodology. According to the empiricists, the surface appearances,
and the observations, are all that we have. We cannot go beyond them, and we should not go
beyond them to explore the causal structures of hidden reality. See Zaman (2012) and Zaman
(2020, this issue) for a more detailed discussion of this philosophical background. As we have
seen, taking causal structures into account can show us that the surface appearances are
deceptive. What appears to be discrimination against females is actually caused by females
choosing the more difficult department. This point can be understood more clearly by further
simplifying the causal structure. Suppose admission in departments is gender blind.
Engineering gives 60% admission to all applicants, male and female. Similarly, Humanities
admits 30% of all applicants, male and female. There is absolutely no difference in admissions
rate by gender in either department.
Figure 2.5 Causal Map # 2
Even though gender has no direct impact on the admit ratio, gender does affect department
choice, and department choice affects the admit ratio. Because of this causal chain, gender will
appear to affect the admit ratio. As an extreme example, if all females apply to Humanities and
all males to Engineering, then female admit ratio will be 30% and male admit ratio will be 60%,
providing strong evidence of apparent discrimination against females. This shows the
importance of the studying the MECHANISM. The data reveal that gender affects the admit
ratio, but they do not tell us HOW this happens. To study the causal chain, we must follow the
real-world process closely; in Freedman’s (1991) terminology, we must expend shoe leather to
learn about causes. As we follow the admissions process step-by-step, we will see that females
are mostly applying to HUM while males are applying to ENG. This would lead us to ask
whether the different admit ratio is due to different policies at the two departments, rather than
gender. The data can shed light on this question, and lead us to a rather different answer to the
WHY question. Females have lower admit rates because they apply mostly to HUM which is
more difficult to get into. This raises further WHY questions why is HUM more difficult to
get into? Perhaps it is because of limited funding which leads to a smaller department size and
hence more competition for fewer seats. Or many other factors could be causes. Searching for
causes requires looking at structures of external reality beyond what appears on the surface.
Causes do not reveal themselves in the observed statistics.
To drive home this point, we consider other causal structures, which can create outcomes
resembling original ones but with causes entirely different from those discussed above. Suppose
admission process is totally computerized and only dependent upon SAT scores. Suppose SAT
scores X leads to an X% chance of admission. As an artificial example, suppose female SAT
scores are only 80 and 40 while male SAT scores are only 60 and 20. Suppose all females with
80 SAT score apply to Engineering, while females with 40 SAT score apply to Humanities.
Similarly, all males with 60 SAT score apply to Engineering and those with 20 apply to
Humanities. While these numbers are cooked to make this easy to understand, it is easy to
construct more complex realistic examples which would create the same phenomena.
Gender
Department
Admit Ratio
International Econometric Review (IER)
59
Figure 2.6 Causal Map # 3
Using initial example proportions 200 females with 80 score and 1800 males with 60 scores
apply to Engineering while 1800 females with 40 score and 200 males with 20 score apply to
Humanities. This will create exactly the same results as Table 1.1, even though gender and
department have no effect on admissions as admissions are purely based on SAT scores.
The causal diagram portrays our assumptions about the causal structure. Each arrow represents
one of our causal assumptions. We have assumed that Gender affects SAT scores as females
have higher SAT scores. We have also assumed that Gender also affects department choice as
females overwhelmingly apply to Humanities. The SAT score also affects department choice
as males and females with high SAT opt for Engineering and with low SAT score opt for
Humanities. Finally, the admissions process depends ONLY on the SAT score; it does not
depend on department, and it does not depend on Gender. But the observed data from this
assumed causal structure will be exactly the same as in Table 1.1 showing Simpson’s paradox.
An analysis which ignores the causal structure, will come to several wrong conclusions. The
data will show that
A. Gender and department both affect admission rates.
B. Females are strongly preferred by both departments.
C. Engineering has higher admit rates and is easy to get into. Humanities has lower admit
rates and is more difficult to get into.
The assumed causal structure makes all three obvious and strong statistical relationship turn out
to be false. Gender does not affect admit ratios, only SAT scores do. The higher admit rates for
females at ENG and HUM result from higher SAT scores of the females, and not from
preference of females by the departments. The lower admit rates in HUM are not because it is
more difficult to get into HUM. It is because males and females with lower SAT scores apply
to HUM both departments have exactly the same admit policies. If the causal structure is as
hypothesized, then an analysis using SAT scores can be used to prove these counter-
phenomenal claims claims which contradict the surface appearances. All of the apparent
relationships A, B, and C, will disappear when we condition admit ratios on the SAT Scores.
Once we do this, we will see that there is no effect of gender and no effect of department on
admit ratios.
This analysis has disturbing implications. Given data on Gender, Department, and Admit
Ratios, the statistics strongly supports A, B, and C. How can we learn that this analysis is
wrong? There is NOTHING in the data which will give us a clue. If we have expended some
shoe leather walking around Berkeley, talking to faculty, learning about the admissions process,
Gender
Department
SAT score
Admit Ratio
Zaman and Salahuddin-Causality, Confounding, and Simpson’s Paradox
60
then we could come up with a causal structure. For example, if we learn that admission occurs
by a mechanical and computerized process which only looks at SAT Scores, then we would
realize that our hypothesized causal relationships represented by A, B, and C are wrong. Further
study could reveal the correct causal structure, leading us to gather data on SAT Scores, and
then to the right conclusions. Suppose on the other hand that the data about gender, department
and admissions comes from some remote and unknown university in Siberia, about we have no
further information, and no possibility of expending shoe leather to find out more. Then we
could tentatively assert that the data suggest conclusions A, B, and C, but we cannot be sure,
because we do not know the causal mechanisms.
Understanding causality is especially important for big data and machine learning, because
computers cannot expend shoe leather. Causal relationships are learnt from real world
experiences and knowledge. For example, if we know about how the applications process works
at Berkeley, we could rule out some causal sequences, and also assess plausibility of others.
But an abundance of data would not lead us to knowledge of these structures, and machines
could not discover those structures, because they are not present in the data.
Exercise 5: Continue from exercise 4. Create an example where the data, when analyzed by
gender and department, show that females are preferred by both departments, and that HUM is
more difficult to get into, while ENG is easier. Now introduce the hidden variable GPA, and
make it do the work of the SAT Score. Once we use GPA, the initial findings are all reversed.
We find that admissions policies are exactly the same at ENG and HUM neither department
is easy or difficult. We find that admission is gender blind same policy for males and females.
Explain why it appears that females are favored, and why it appears that HUM is more difficult
to get into, even though this is not really the case
3. BASEBALL SCORES: OVERALL AVERAGE OR STRATIFIED?
It is standard practice in statistical analysis to separate the role of the field expert from the
statistical consultant. The field expert has deep knowledge of the processes which generate the
numbers, while the statistician knows about the numbers, and has superficial knowledge of the
meaning of these numbers and where they come from. The assumption is that we can analyze
data without knowing about the background mechanisms which generate the data. To show that
this assumption is false, we will consider the same data of Berkeley admissions in Table 1.1
and give it very different real-world background. Suppose now that Tom and Frank are two
batters with batting averages of 56% and 44%. On the basis of only these numbers with no
knowledge of the field it appears that Tom is apparently the better one out of two. At a critical
moment for the team, coach needs to decide whom to send into the field for getting a hit. From
the overall averages, Tom seems to be the better choice. However, an analyst has heard that
Frank is a superstar against left-handed pitchers, but has difficulties when he faces right-handed
pitchers. Also, generally Frank has a much better reputation than Tom. Thus, the superiority of
Tom’s average puzzles the analyst. On the basis of real-world information, available to field
experts, but not to statisticians, the analyst decides to look deeper into the batting records.
Analyzing performance against left and right-handed pitchers, he finds that Frank had 80% hits
against left-handed pitchers while Tom had 60%. Also, Frank had 40% hits against right-handed
pitchers whereas Tom had only 20%. Thus, Frank is better than Tom against left-handed
Pitchers, and he is also better than Tom against right-handed pitchers. On the basis of this deeper
analysis, it seems that the Coach should send out Frank. This is because digging deeper into the
data provides a counter-phenomenal answer to the question of WHY did Tom (56%) have a
higher batting average than Frank (44%). The obvious answer would be that Tom is better than
International Econometric Review (IER)
61
Frank. The subdivided data shows that this is false. Frank is better than Tom, but both batters
perform better against left-handed pitchers, and worse against right-handed pitchers. So the
CAUSE of Frank’s poorer performance is that he faced far more left handed pitchers where his
batting average is 40%, while Tom faced far more right-handed pitchers where his batting
average is 60%. Given the same mix of pitchers, Frank would perform much better than Tom.
This analysis is captured by the following causal diagram. The batting average depends on
which batter, but it also depends on the proportion of left and right-handed pitchers.
According to the causal map, the left-right mix of pitchers is not caused by the batter or the
batting average, and hence is exogenous. In statistical terminology, it is a confounder. If we
want to correctly calculate batter performance, then we must condition on the confounder. This
means holding left and right-pitcher constant, and calculating separately for the two cases. One
the basis of this calculation, we would send out Frank, because he will perform better than Tom
against any arbitrarily chosen left/right mix of pitchers. Here the separate performance numbers
against left and right-handed pitchers are relevant, and the aggregate performance is misleading
because the two players did not face similar left/right mix. However, a different causal structure
can lead to the opposite conclusion, as we now discuss and demonstrate
Figure 3.7 Causal Map # 4
3.1. Coach is Aware of Exceptional Performance of Tom
Expending shoe leather, our analyst goes to have a talk with the coach of the opposing team.
The coach informs him that Frank is a superstar, and has an amazing batting average of 80%
against left-handed pitchers. However, his performance against right-handed pitchers is not so
good, and so, whenever he is sent to bat, the coach switches to right-handed pitchers as much
as possible. With this piece of causal information, which simply cannot be contained in any
kind of data, the causal picture changes to the following:
Figure 3.8 Causal Map # 5
Now the mix of left and right-handed pitchers is NOT exogenous, because the coach changes
the mix in response to Frank. When the mix is endogenous, then the batter’s influence on batting
average works through two channels. One channel favors Frank he is the better batter of the
Left-Right Mix
Batter
Batting Average
Batting Average
Left-Right Mix
Batter
Zaman and Salahuddin-Causality, Confounding, and Simpson’s Paradox
62
two. The other channel has a negative influence the coach changes the pitcher mix to make it
difficult for Frank. The overall effect is the sum of the two effects and is negative in the present
example. It is better to send Tom, even though he is weaker, if he will get a more favorable
left/right mix. So, depending on the causal chain, either Tom or Frank could be the better choice.
The causal chain cannot be learned from the data, but we can learn about it by expending shoe
leather and examining the real-world mechanisms in operation which create the numbers we
see. Some important points that we can learn from these examples are as follows:
1. The causal chain depends crucially on the unobservable intentions of the coach of the
opposing team. Will he respond to Frank by changing the mix of left/right batters? Or
is his choice of mix independent of which batter is chosen?
2. Even though this factor is unobservable, and we can never have 100% certainty about
it, we can still make intelligent guesses about it. So, even when causal factors can never
be known with certainty, we can make good and bad guesses about them, and the results
we get will depend on how well we can guess at unobservables.
Many philosophers (Hume, Kant, Wittgenstein, Logical Positivists) have maintained that we
should not speculate about unobservables, and that unobservables should not enter scientific
theories. The above example shows that, to the contrary, we must speculate about
unobservables, as they matter crucially for our decisions. Another widely accepted
philosophical principle is that use of the term “Knowledge” should be confined to those matters
about which we can be certain. Again, all of our examples show that we can only have guesses
about causal mechanisms, and we can never be certain that some new hidden variable or causal
effect may completely upset all our previous calculations. But despite this, we have no choice
but to try to do our best at making such guesses, without ever being certain that we are right.
Meaningful analysis cannot be done without causal structures, and yet, we can never be certain
that we have correctly discovered the causal structure. Wrong philosophies about the nature of
science and knowledge have prevented understanding of causality in statistics and econometrics
until recently.
Causal analysis cannot be applied mechanically. In making the decision about which batter to
send out, we must assess the relevance of the historical record to the current situation. Are the
observed batting averages and Left and Right-Handed pitchers reasonable estimates for
performance against the current field? The analysis that the overall average is better predictor
of performance, and Tom should be sent out, depends on several assumptions. We assume that
there is a normal standard left and right pitcher mix which has been chosen by the coach for
general use. For any given fixed left/right mix, Frank will do better than Tom. However, if the
Coach switches the mix in response to Frank his exceptional performance is the terror of
opponents then Frank will face an adverse mix. We also assume that Tom does not stand out
sufficiently from others, and the Coach will not optimize pitchers against him. With these
assumptions, all about unobservable causal chains, it would make sense to send Tom out to bat,
even though Frank is the better batter among the two. Changes in the mind of coach would
change causal structures, and change optimal decisions, so we must make guesses about this.
For example, if the coach decides to optimize pitcher against all incoming batters, then Frank
would be a better choice he would bat 40% against Tom’s 20% for the left-handed pitcher to
be chosen. If we have no direct clues about how the coach will choose, we may look at the
historical record. This record shows that in the past, Frank has faced a highly adverse field,
seemingly optimized against him, while Tom has not. So, there is a suggestion, a clue that
coaches tend to optimize against Frank, but not against Tom. This would lead to choosing Tom.
International Econometric Review (IER)
63
Exercise # 6: Construct a decision tree as follows. Coach A selects either Tom or Frank. Then
Coach B selects either a left-handed pitcher, or a right-handed pitcher. Use the probabilities PT
and PF=1PT for Coach A, and PL and PR=1PL for Coach B to calculate the probability
that Coach A gets a hit use other data as given above. Consider the following three cases:
1. Both coaches choose their probability separately and independently. Show that
regardless of how they choose, Tom is the better choice for coach A.
2. Coach A has a standard set of probabilities PL*=50% and PR*=50% which he generally
uses to choose pitchers. However, when Coach A sees Tom at bat, he responds by
changing to PL*=10% and PR*=90%. Show that in this case, Frank is the better choice.
3. Coach B knows the hit probabilities for Tom and Frank against left and right-handed
pitchers, and chooses to optimize that is, he chooses the type of pitcher against which
the batter has worst performance. Show that in this case, Tom is the better choice.
4. EFFECT OF DRUGS ON RECOVERY
Our final example considers the classical case of testing the effectiveness of a drug as a
treatment for a disease. It is standard to divide the population into two groups, and compare
recovery rates. The group which does not take the drug is called the control group. The group
which takes the drug is called the treatment group. If the percentage of people who recover
from the disease in the two groups is roughly the same, then the drug has no effect on recovery.
If the recovery rate in the treatment group is significantly higher than the recovery rate in the
control group, then the drug is effective. It is also possible that the drug is actually harmful, in
which case the recovery rate in the treatment group would be lower than that in the control
group. All this is under the assumption that the treatment group and control group are
sufficiently similar, so that the only difference between the two is that one group took the drug
while the other one did not. If there are other significant differences between the groups, then
the difference in outcomes could be due to the other factors, called confounders. For example,
if the treatment group is mostly female while the control group is mostly male, then gender is
a confounding factor. If the disease and drug act differently on different genders for example,
females are resistant to the disease and recover quickly with or without drug then what we
think is improved performance due to the drug would actually be improved performance due to
the fact that there were more females in the treatment group. Thus, the effect of the drug is
confounded with the effect of gender.
After establishing the basic terminology, we create an artificial data set parallel to Berkeley
admissions, and show how different causal chains lead to radically different interpretations of
exactly the same data. One source of confusion in this comparison is that in Berkeley, we were
comparing the effect of gender on admissions, while here we are comparing the effect of drug
treatment on recovery. So, being a female applicant to Berkeley corresponds to being in the
treatment group, while being a male applicant to Berkeley corresponds to being in the control
group. Also, in this comparison, the effect of gender corresponds to the effect of the department.
The department ENG corresponds to being female while the department HUM corresponds to
being male in the present setup. With this translation, we can now create a Simpson’s Paradox
for drug treatment as follows.
Zaman and Salahuddin-Causality, Confounding, and Simpson’s Paradox
64
The overall recovery rate in the treatment group is 56%, while it is 44% in the control group.
These figures appear to show that the drug is beneficial, and improves recovery rates by about
12%. However, expending shoe leather, we find a lot of complaints from patients about
apparently harmful effects of the drug. On this basis, we decide to investigate further. Noting
that recovery rates seem to differ by gender, we investigate recovery rates separately for males
and females. This leads to a surprise. We find that females who did not take the drug (female
controls) have recovery rates of 80%. However, females who take the drug (females in
treatment group) have much lower recovery rates of 60%. The drug is quite harmful, lowering
recovery rates by 20%. The drug is also harmful for males. The male control group has recovery
rates of 40%. However, the male treatment group, which takes the drug, has much lower
recovery rates of only 20%. How can it be that the drug harms males, and it harms females, but
it helps the general population? This is the Simpson’s Paradox.
The recovery rates for the CONTROLS (non-drug-takers) are 80% for females (ENG) and 40%
for males (HUM). The recovery rates for the TREATMENT GROUP (drug takers) are 60% for
females (ENG) and 20% for males (HUM). If 90% of the controls are males while 10% are
females, then the recovery rates for the non-drug-takers would be 10% x 80% + 90% x 40% =
8% + 36% = 44%. Similarly, if the treatment group is mostly (90%) females and has only 10%
males, then the recovery rate in the treatment group would by 90% x 60% + 10% x 20% = 54%
+ 2% = 56%. The overall figures show that among those who took the drug, recovery rate was
56%, while it was only 44% among those who did not. Now the causal picture is rather different
from the Berkeley admissions it can be graphed as follows
Figure 4.9 Causal Map # 6
In the Berkeley admissions, we wanted to study the effect of gender on admissions. The
department choices were affected by gender and so formed a second channel by which gender
affected admit ratios. Here we want to study the effect of taking the drug on recovery. Taking
the drug cannot affect gender. However, gender does affect drug taking since females
overwhelmingly take the drug, while males overwhelmingly avoid the drug. Since females have
higher recovery rates than males both with and without drugs, their heavy presence in the
treatment group creates a bias towards recovery. Males have lower recovery rates with and
without drugs, so their heavy presence in the control group creates a bias against recovery in
the control group. Together these biases overwhelm the genuine negative effect of the drug.
According to standard statistical analysis and terminology, gender is a confounding variable.
Alternatively, in econometric terminology, gender is exogenous. The effects of drug on
recovery are contaminated by the effects of gender, both on drug taking behavior and on
recovery rates. To eliminate this, we must condition on gender and hold it constant. When we
do that, we find the correct result that the drug is actually harmful to both females and males.
The overall figure gives us the wrong information because it ignores the confounding variable
Gender: Male/
Female
Treatment/ Control
(Drug/ No drug)
Recovery / No
recovery
International Econometric Review (IER)
65
of gender. The high rates of recovery in the treatment group come from the favorable effect of
being female, and the high proportion of females in the treatment group. This favorable effect
overwhelms the harmful effect of the drug on recovery. Several “Why?” questions arise in this
context. Why the treatment group is so heavily populated by females and why is the control
group so heavily populated by males? This means that the choice between treatment and control
could not have been random, because random choice would automatically balance the number
of males and females to roughly equal. Perhaps, because it was an experimental drug being
tested, patients were offered a choice to take the drug or not. In this case females
overwhelmingly chose to be treated, while males overwhelmingly chose not to take the drug,
creating a bias in favor of the drug. Why? There are many possible hypothesis and explanations
which could be explored and tested here. For a discussion of how causes are discovered in real
life examples, see Freedman (1991) on Statistical Models and Shoe Leather.
Exercise #7A: The standard method of avoiding confounders is to use randomization. Show
that if people are assigned to treatment or control groups at random, then the chances of an
imbalance like the one of the example with 90% females in one group and only 10% in the
other is almost zero. To be specific, suppose 100 patients are assigned at random to the
treatment group from the general population which is 50% female. Each patient has a 50%
chance of being male or female. Use the Binomial distribution to calculate a range of numbers
(L=50N,U=50+N) such that the P(L<F<U)=99%. The number of females should lie
within L and U with 99% probability. You will see that the number of females cannot deviate
very far from the 50% proportion, so that extreme bias of the kind used in the example cannot
arise in randomized controlled experiments.
Exercise #7B: There are many situations where randomized controlled trials are not possible.
For example, if we want to study the effects of one year of smoking on cancer rates, explain
why we cannot do randomized assignment to treatment and control groups. Similarly, if we
have an experimental drug of unknown efficiency, possibly harmful, we cannot ethically
randomize patients into treatment and control groups. Sketch a plausible causal scenario where,
if an experimental drug is offered for treatment, women overwhelming prefer to take it leading
to 90% females in the treatment group. At the same time, men overwhelming prefer not to take
it, leading to 90% males in the control group. Note that discovering causality is always an
exercise of the imagination coming up with stories which explain the patterns we see at levels
deeper than is revealed by the data themselves.
4.1. Blood Pressure as Exogenous Confounder
To see how changing causal sequencing changes the results completely, let us replace gender
in previous causal map with Blood pressure BP. Gender is exogenous and cannot be affected
by drugs and disease, but BP can be affected by disease and by drugs. This allows for a much
larger variety of causal paths, each of which leads to different ways of understanding the same
data set. Let us first consider the same causal structure as in the previous causal map #6,
replacing Gender with Blood Pressure as a confounder. To keep the analysis parallel, suppose
that there are only two types of BP: Low (LBP), and High (HBP). We will regard LBP as
normal, for simplicity in interpretation. With this switch from Gender to Blood Pressure, the
Simpson’s Paradox takes the following form. Overall recovery rates are 56% for the treatment
group and 44% for the control group, so that the drug appears to be beneficial. However, when
we subdivide the population into LBP (normal BP) and HBP (elevated BP), we find the opposite
results. In both subpopulations, the recovery rates of the control group are much higher than
recovery rates in the treatment group, which suggests that the drug is actually harmful. To be
Zaman and Salahuddin-Causality, Confounding, and Simpson’s Paradox
66
more precise, in the HBP group, recovery rate is 80% in the control group (without the drug),
and only 60% in the treatment group (with the drug). Similarly, in the LBP group, recovery rate
is 40% in the control group, and only 20% in the treatment group. In both groups, the drug
lowers the recovery rate by 20% and is obviously harmful. The paradox occurs because the
control group consists mostly of LBP (90%) with only 10% HBP patients. LBP patients have
low recovery rates of only 40% without the drug, so the presence of large numbers LBP patients
drives recovery rates down to 44%. The treatment group has the opposite composition with
90% being HBP and 10% being LBP. HBP have 60% recovery rates (reduced from 80% after
being given the drug). After mixing in the 10% LBP patients with only 20% recovery rates, we
get an average recovery rate of 56% in the treatment group.
How this data should be interpreted depends strongly on the causal chains, which are not
available from the data itself. One possible interpretation is that the higher recovery rate is not
due to the drug, which is harmful, but rather due to the large proportion of HBP patients, who
have higher recovery rates even after being given the drug. This is the picture shown by
recovery rates in the subgroups of low and high blood pressure patients. Which of the two
statistics, overall or subgroup, gives the correct picture? Should we use the drug to treat patients,
or should we discontinue its use? Is the drug harmful, or is it helpful? The answer to this very
real and very important medical question depends on the hidden and unobservable causal chains
which connect the three variables under consideration. Depending on the causal sequence either
one of the two answers can be correct. Also, if there are other hidden factors, neither of the two
answers may be correct. We first consider the simplest case, where blood pressure, like gender,
is an exogenous confounder.
Case 1: Exogenous Confounder Assume at first, or hypothesize, that the Blood Pressure
plays the same role as Gender in the previous Causal Map #6. Blood Pressure is not affected by
either the drug or the disease, but does affect both drug taking behavior and recovery outcomes.
If this assumption is correct then Blood Pressure is a confounder, and the correct analysis is
obtained by conditioning on this variable. The drug is harmful for both LBP and HBP, and
should not be given to anybody. Different questions arise here: Why does the control group
consist mainly of HBP patients, while the treatment group consists mainly of LBP patients?
Perhaps HBP patients have some sort of adverse reaction to the drug, which leads them to stop
taking the drug. Also: Why do HBP patients have much higher recovery rates, with and without
the drug? Perhaps High blood pressure helps in recovering from the disease. Both of these
hypotheses have real implications, and one could explore and experiment further to see if they
are valid. This is a KEY aspect of causal chains. Causality itself is not observable, but it always
has implications which can be explored and confirmed or rejected. Thus, indirect evidence is
often available for hypothesized causal effects.
When BP is an exogenous confounder, then conditioning on it gives the correct analysis.
However, when it is a mediator, conditioning will give a wrong analysis, as we now
demonstrate.
Exercise 8A: The standard way to handle confounders is via RCT randomized controlled trial.
Show that if we assign patients at random to treatment or control group, then both groups will
contain approximately the same proportion of LBP and HBP patients. Thus the effect of
confounding will be eliminated. Note that this will be true even if the experimenter is
UNAWARE that BP is a confounding factor. That is the beauty of randomization, that it
eliminates even hidden confounding factors.
International Econometric Review (IER)
67
Figure 4.10 Causal Map # 7 A
Exercise 8B: Suppose we do an RCT and find that there is a heavy concentration of High BP
in the Treatment Group, but not in the control group. Explain why we can reject the hypothesis
that BP is an exogenous confounder.
4.2. Blood Pressure as Mediator
Radically different analysis and interpretation of the data arise if Blood Pressure acts as a
mediator, rather than an exogenous confounder. It is to illustrate this possibility that we
switched from Gender to Blood Pressure, because Gender cannot be a mediator.
Case 2: BP is a mediator Gender cannot be affected by Drugs, but Blood Pressure can be.
There is a possibility that Blood Pressure acts as a mediator a channel through which the drug
works. The Low and High Blood Pressure may be one of the effects of the drug itself. If this is
so, then the causal map looks like the following:
Figure 4.11 Causal Map # 7 B
Now BP is not a confounder because it is not exogenous. It is affected by the drug. This causal
map suggests the following interpretation. High Blood Pressure is very helpful in recovering
from the disease. The drug itself is toxic, and lowers recovery rates of all patients by about 20%.
However, the drug causes an increase in blood pressure, which is very helpful in recovering
from the disease. As a result, when we take the sum of both effects, we find that the drug is
actually helpful. With this causal map, the drug is beneficial because of its indirect effect of
raising blood pressure, which helps in recovery, even though its direct effect is harmful.
Low/ High BP
Treatment/ Control
(Drug/ No drug)
Recovery / No
recovery
Low/ High BP
Treatment/ Control
(Drug/ No drug)
Recovery / No
recovery
Zaman and Salahuddin-Causality, Confounding, and Simpson’s Paradox
68
As we have noted earlier, all causal maps are actually guesses about hidden and unobservable
structures of external reality. The data does not provide direct evidence for or against them, and
all causal hypotheses are tentative, and remain tentative forever. As we demonstrated in the
Berkeley admissions case, another hidden factor (like SAT) may upset all of our conclusions.
However, our causal hypotheses are productive. That is they lead to additional hypotheses
which can be tested. If Causal Map #7 is actually valid, we can go and look for mechanisms
whereby high blood pressure helps in the recovery process from the disease. Finding this
mechanism would support our causal hypothesis and may lead to discovery of other ways to
help recovery which do not raise the BP. Similarly, we could look for the mechanism by which
the drug harms recovery. Search may lead to discovery of modifications of the drug which raise
the BP without other harmful side effects. Even though the causal hypotheses are about
unobservables, they have many observable implications which can be explored and tested to
provide indirect evidence for and against the hypothesis.
Exercise 9A: Show that when BP is a mediator, conditioning on BP to calculate the effects of
drug on recovery leads to the wrong results regarding the effect of the drug. In this situation,
the overall effect in both groups gives the correct result regarding recovery rates, while the
recovery rates in the separate groups of LBP and HBP give misleading results about the effect
of the drug. Explain intuitively why this is so.
Exercise 9B: Given this data set and this causal map, we could try to predict recovery rates for
people with HBP in the general population, who are not part of the experiment. What would
these rates be? If we could find a drug which raised blood pressure without having any other
side-effects, what would the recovery rates be for a group treated with this new drug which
raises blood pressure from normal LBP to High HBP with 90% probability?
4.3. Simple Analysis for Simple Chains
Better understanding of the complex causal chains required for Simpson’s Paradox arises from
considering a simple chain of causation, which we illustrate below. In simple chains, one factor
acts through the second only, and there are no multiple causal pathways. Understanding the
simple case serves as a basis for understanding the more complex cases.
Case 3: BP as mediator Acting on the hypothesis suggested by causal map #7, a detailed
analysis of effects of the drug on human body is carried out. It is discovered that there are two
compounds in the drug, one of which is toxic, while the other acts to increase blood pressure.
A modified drug is created by eliminating the toxic compound. In this case, the drug has no
direct effect on recovery, and ONLY acts to increase the Blood Pressure. However High Blood
Pressure does have a strong positive impact on recovery. The Causal Map now becomes the
following:
Figure 4.12 Causal Map # 8
Using the same numbers as before, suppose that in the LBP group, the disease is deadly with
only 40% recovery rate, but in HBP group recovery rate is very high at 80%. Suppose in normal
population 90% people are in LBP group and 10% in HBP group. Then the overall recovery
rate in normal population without drug will be 44% = 90% *40% + 10%*80% = 36% + 8%.
L/H BP
Recovery Rate
Drug / No-Drug
International Econometric Review (IER)
69
The new modified drug given to patients changes the BP profile so that 90% of patients now
have High Blood Pressure, and only 10% remain at Low Blood Pressure. Even though the drug
has no direct effect on recovery, this action of raising Blood Pressure helps recovery because
of the helpful effects of HBP on recovery. Under our hypotheses, the new recovery rate will be
76% = 90% *80% + 10%*40% = 72% + 4%. By eliminating the toxic effect of the drug, the
recovery rates in the treatment group will now soar to 76%.
Case 4: Drug as Mediator The causal sequence in map #8 could be reversed. It may be that
Blood Pressure governs whether or not the drug is taken, and has no direct effect on recovery.
Figure 4.13 Causal Map # 9
Suppose the drug is extremely helpful. Recovery rate in treatment groups (with the drug) is
80%, while recovery rate in the control groups (without the drug) is only 40%. Suppose the
drug sometimes causes an adverse reaction which causes mild discomfort, which discourages
people from continuing to take the drug. The adverse reaction occurs with very low probability
in High Blood pressure patients, and with very high probability in low Blood Pressure patients.
Depending on how the data is framed and presented, a statistician could easily come to the
conclusion that High Blood Pressure leads to recovery, and Low Blood Pressure does not.
Furthermore, if LBP is a large proportion of the population, the data could suggest that the drug
only has a small positive effect, because most LBP patients abandon the drug regime.
Exercise 10: Suppose the situation is as described in the previous paragraph. The statistician
creates a randomized controlled experiment dividing the population (which has 90% LBP and
10% HBP) into treatment and control groups at random. The treatment group is told to take the
drug, while the control group does not take the drug. The drug tastes very bitter to 90% of LBP
patients and they stop taking it after a while, but do not inform experimenter about their non-
compliance. The drug tastes bitter to only 10% of HBP patients, who stop taking the drug. The
experimenter does not know about the non-compliance. Calculate what his data will show about
the effect of the drug, given that he assumes that everyone in the treatment group actually took
the drug, and no one in the control group did.
4.4. Adding Confounder to Simple Chains
Simpson’s Paradox is not possible in simple chains like the ones discussed above, because we
need two pathways, one negative and one positive, for a reversal of effects. However, a
confounder added to the above Causal Map # 9 can lead to a Simpson’s Paradox:
In this map, we do not actually have two channels by which BP affects recovery. However, if
Gender affects BP, the two could be highly correlated, so that the data would have the
appearance of showing two channels, when in fact the hidden variable was doing the work
required for the second channel. This would lead to highly misleading interpretations of the
causal mechanism relating the observed variables. In this particular case, we know, from our
background knowledge of real-world mechanisms, that gender may affect BP, but the reverse
direction is impossible. The causal chain cannot run from BP to Gender. For other confounding
variables this may or may not be true.
Drug/No Drug
Recovery Rate
Low/High BP
Zaman and Salahuddin-Causality, Confounding, and Simpson’s Paradox
70
Figure 4.14 Causal Map # 10
Exercise 11A: Suppose that BP has no direct effect on recovery. However, 90% of HBP patients
continue to take the drug, while 10% stop taking drug because it tastes bitter. Among LBP
patients, 90% of patients stop taking the drug because it tastes bitter to them, and only 10%
continue to take the drug. In the general population, about 10% of the people are HBP and 90%
are LBP. Recovery rates without drug are 40% (for all patients, LBP and HBP). Recovery rates
for those who continue to take the drug are 80% for all patients LBP and HBP. Create a table
which shows what the statistician will see if he studies a treatment group and a control group
taken from the general population, but does not know about the fact that some people will stop
taking the drug within the treatment group. What will the statistician conclude about the
effectiveness of the drug on LBP and HBP patients?
Exercise 11B: Now suppose Gender is related to BP as follows. Among females, HBP is rare
and only 1% of females suffer from HBP. Among males, HBP is far more common and about
20% of males suffer from HBP. In the same situation as that of the previous exercise, create a
table for recovery rates by Gender in the treatment and control group. Ignore classification by
BP, only classify by gender. What will the statistician looking at this table conclude about the
effect of gender on recovery rates from the disease under treatment and without treatment?
4.5. Forks Lead to Correlation without Causation
There are a few more simple causal relationships which commonly occur among. One of them
is called the “fork”. Two possible fork relationships can be depicted as follows:
Figure 4.15 Causal Map # 11 A
Gender: Male/Female
Treatment/ Control
(Drug/ No drug) Recovery /
No recovery
Low/ High
BP
Hi/ Low BP
Drug/ No Drug
Recovery
International Econometric Review (IER)
71
Figure 4.16 Causal Map # 11 B
In the first causal map 11A, the Blood Pressure is the only factor which matters for recovery.
However, the Blood Pressure also affects whether or not the drug is taken; as before, the drug
may have a mild adverse effect on High or Low BP patients, creating differential patterns of
drug taking. Statisticians analyzing the relationship between drug taking and recovery rates
would come up with highly misleading conclusions if they were not aware of these causal
relationships. Similarly, in causal map 11B, the drug affects both recovery and Blood Pressure.
With this type of causal chain, almost any kind of relationship between Blood Pressure and
Recovery could be observed in the data, when there is none in reality.
Forks create correlations which are misleading. In the first map above, strong correlation
between drug taking and recovery would lead to the impression that drug taking has a strong
effect on recovery. In fact, there is no effect. Similarly, in the second map, recovery would be
highly correlated with recovery and yet neither factor causes the other. A Granger type causality
test between the two factors would lead to highly misleading results.
Exercise 12: Suppose that, as before, 90% of HBP patients in treatment group continue to take
the drug, while 10% stop taking the drug. Among LBP patients, 90% stop taking the drug while
10% continue to take it. Suppose that the drug has no effect on recovery, but HBP is a strong
positive factor. Among LBP patients, recovery rate is 40% with or without the drug. Among
HBP patients, recovery rate is 80% with or without the drug. Suppose both control group and
treatment group are chosen at random from the general population which has 90% LBP and
10% HBP. There is no effect of gender.
a) Calculate the overall recovery rates in treatment and control groups.
b) Calculate recovery rates among HBP and LBP separately in both treatment and control
group.
c) What are the conclusions that statisticians who analyze the data might come to, given
that they do not know the causal mechanism is a fork?
d) What kind of an experiment would reveal that the causal mechanism is a fork?
4.6. Do NOT Condition on Colliders
A final example of a simple causal relationship among the three variables is called the
“collider”. This type of causal relation is on the other side of the causal map from the
confounder. Whereas a confounder affects the variables under study, a collider is affected by
Hi/ Low BP
Recovery
Drug/ No Drug
Zaman and Salahuddin-Causality, Confounding, and Simpson’s Paradox
72
the variables under study. The significance of colliders lies in the fact that they require different
treatment from confounders. While one must condition on confounders for correct analysis, one
must NOT condition on colliders for correct analysis. In the example under study, there are two
possible colliders:
Figure 4.17 Causal Map # 12 A
In the map 12A, Recovery is a collider, which is affected by both BP and Drugs. A second
possibility for a collider map is the blood pressure, as picture in causal map 12B below:
Figure 4.18 Causal Map # 12 B
Note that the third possible collider is ruled out because Recovery cannot be a cause of taking
the Drug or not. Causal chains depend strongly on our knowledge of external reality we could
not rule this out if we were considering variables X, Y, Z without knowledge of what the
variables represent.
Causal Path 12A: The first collider is a case we have already encountered. In this the Hi/Lo
BP acts as a confounder in assessing the relationship between Drug Treatment and Recovery.
If the Blood Pressure is ignored, we can get entirely wrong assessments about this relationship.
Similarly, someone studying the relationships between Blood Pressure and Recovery without
considering causal effects of the Drug will arrive at the wrong conclusions. In the context of
regression models, this point has been emphasized in Zaman (2017) “Choosing the Right
Regressors” – omitting a significant regressor will lead to misleading regression results.
Causal Path 12B: This is an interesting case where recovery from the disease occurs naturally,
without drugs, but leaves some effect in terms of higher or lower Blood Pressure. The drug
treatment has no effect on the disease, but it also affects Blood Pressure. To consider an extreme
case, suppose all patients who recover end up with High Blood Pressure, and similarly all
patients who take the drug end up with High Blood Pressure. Analyzing the patients with HBP,
we will see that all patients took the drug and recovered. Analyzing patients with LBP we will
see the no one took the drug and no one recovered. So, we will conclude that the drug is highly
effective, even though it has absolutely no effect on recovery. Thus, conditioning on the collider
leads to a highly misleading analysis.
Exercise 13: Consider the causal path 12B and suppose that natural recovery rate from disease
is 60%, with or without the drug. In the general population, LBP is 90% and HBP is 10%.
Hi/Low BP
Drug/ No Drug
Recovery
Hi/Low BP
Recovery
Drug/ No Drug
International Econometric Review (IER)
73
However, the disease causes elevated blood pressure which persists even after recovery from
the disease. Among those who recover from the disease HBP is 80% while only 20% have LBP.
The drug has no effect on the disease, but it also has the same effect on the blood pressure.
Taking the drug leads to HBP in 80% of the patients and LBP in only 20%. Show that a
statistician who analyzed recovery rates in a randomized control group and treatment group
without taking BP into consideration will come to the right result. However, if he thinks that
BP is a confounder, and splits the treatment and control group by BP, he will get wrong results
about the impact of the drug.
5. CONCLUSIONS
From the last example we see that when analyzing the relationship between Drugs and Recovery
from disease, the Blood Pressure can play three different roles. It can be a confounder, which
affects both drug-taking and recovery, without being affected by either. In this case,
conditioning on BP leads to the correct conclusions about the effects of drugs on recovery. The
BP can also be a mediator, or a channel by which the drug affects recovery. In this case, BP is
endogenous and conditioning on it leads to the wrong results. The right analysis involves taking
into account both the direct effects of the drug, and the indirect effects via the BP channel. The
third possibility is that BP is affected by both Drugs and Recovery, but does not affect either of
the two. In this case, it is a collider, and should be ignored in the analysis. If we take it into
account, either as a confounder, or as a mediator, we will get wrong and misleading results.
Which of the three causal path diagram obtains is not possible to detect directly from the data.
This means that data analysis cannot be confined to the study of numbers, without considering
the underlying and hidden causal structures of external reality.
This discussion carries over to the regression context. Typical econometric studies involving
three variables X, Y, Z would only run one of the variables on other two. As we have seen, the
number of causal path relationships possible among the three is much larger. Even for standard
regression analysis, we first need to determine exogeneity among these variables. Now this is
not possible without understanding the real-world causal structures which generate the data.
Econometrics does not provide us with any formal language to represent causal relationships.
Causality can only be discussed qualitatively and informally, and cannot be represented
mathematically in the equations we write. This is why econometrics textbooks (and students)
are massively confused about this concept.
It is evident from the above given discussion that causal relationships in real life can actually
be very complex. The hard work involved in the process of searching for causes has been
described by Freedman (1991) in several real-world examples. Because econometricians are
not taught to think about causes, most of the regression relationships we write down are
spurious. Without additional information, unobservable real-life causal structures cannot be
understood and without understanding the causal structures, exogeneity of the variables cannot
be determined. The deficiency comes from a ‘positivist’ methodology which consciously limits
analysis only to observables. By excluding non-observable causal patterns from consideration,
econometric methodology prevents us from learning about causal relations. To make progress,
it is essential to discuss causal structures, which lie beyond the numbers, and depend on our
qualitative knowledge of external reality.
Zaman and Salahuddin-Causality, Confounding, and Simpson’s Paradox
74
REFERENCES
Bickel, P.J., E. A. Hammel and J.W. O'connell, (1975). Sex Bias in Graduate Admissions: Data
from Berkeley. Science. 187 (4175), 398-404.
Freedman, D. A. (1991) Statistical Models and Shoe Leather. Sociological Methodology, 21,
291-313.
Hoover, K. D. (2004). Lost Causes. Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 26 (2), 149-
164.
Pearl, J. and D. Mackenzie (2018). The Book of Why: The New Science of Cause and Effect.
New York: Basic Books.
Pearl, J., M. Glymour and N. P. Jewell (2016). Causal Inference in Statistics: A Primer. John
Wiley & Sons.
Zaman, A. (2010). Causal Relations via Econometrics. International Econometrics Review, 2
(1), 36-56.
Zaman, A. (2012). Methodological Mistakes and Econometric Consequences. International
Econometric Review, 4 (2),.99-122.
Zaman, A. (2017). Choosing the Right Regressors. Lessons in Econometric Methodology: The
Axiom of Correct Specification. International Econometrics Review. 9 (2), 50-68.
Zaman, A. (2018). European Transition to Secular Thought: Lessons for Muslims. https://sites
.google.com/site/azamanpublications/ie/islamic/european (accessed April 10, 2020).
Article
Full-text available
Economic models translate real problems to an artificial world, and calculate outcomes. The match between artificial worlds populated by rational robots, and the real world, is never assessed. Instead, models are judged on aesthetic grounds, involving conformity to preconceived principles of optimization and equilibrium. Despite methodological proclamations to the contrary, models are not judged by predictive performance. Economics models are formulated axiomatically, and never cross-checked against reality. Taking this (controversial) characterization of economic methodology for granted, this paper sketches trends in philosophy of science which led to a methodology which permits creation of mental models disconnected from reality. A key development was the separation of the observable phenomena from the underlying reality (noumena) which eventually allowed empiricist philosophers to jettison the underlying reality as part of what good models attempt to describe. The paper discusses contemporary methodologies for assessing models in economics and econometrics, and explains why these lead to models disconnected from reality.
Article
Full-text available
Econometric Methodology is based on logical positivist principles. Since logical positivism has collapsed, it is necessary to re-think these foundations. We show that positivist methodology has led econometricians to a meaningless search for patterns in the data. An alternative methodology which relates observed patterns to real causal structures is proposed.
Article
Full-text available
Applied econometric work takes a superficial approach to causality. Understanding economic affairs, making good policy decisions, and progress in the economic discipline depend on our ability to infer causal relations from data. We review the dominant approaches to causality in econometrics, and suggest why they fail to give good results. We feel the problem cannot be solved by traditional tools, and requires some out-of-thebox thinking. Potentially promising approaches to solutions are discussed.
Article
Often papers begin with an idea. Once the paper is written, sometimes little sometimes much effort goes into finding a title. This lecture worked the other way round. It started with the title, which I passed on to Roy Weintraub, my successor as President of the Society, when I still had but the vaguest idea ol what I would write. When Roy heardmy title he pointed me to a passage from C. Vann Woodward, that he hadhimself quotedin Stablizing Dynamics: Lost causes, especially those that foster loyalties and nostalgic memories are among the most prolific breeders of historiography. If survivors deem the cause not wholly lost andperhaps in some measure retrievable, the search of the past becomes more frantic and the books about it more numerous. Blame must be fixed, villains found, heroes celebrated, old quarrels settled, old dreams restored, and motives vindicated. Amid the ruins controversy thrives and books proliferate (quoted by Weintraub 1991, p. 125, from Vann Woodward 1986).
Article
Examination of aggregate data on graduate admissions to the University of California, Berkeley, for fall 1973 shows a clear but misleading pattern of bias against female applicants. Examination of the disaggregated data reveals few decision-making units that show statistically significant departures from expected frequencies of female admissions, and about as many units appear to favor women as to favor men. If the data are properly pooled, taking into account the autonomy of departmental decision making, thus correcting for the tendency of women to apply to graduate departments that are more difficult for applicants of either sex to enter, there is a small but statistically significant bias in favor of women. The graduate departments that are easier to enter tend to be those that require more mathematics in the undergraduate preparatory curriculum. The bias in the aggregated data stems not from any pattern of discrimination on the part of admissions committees, which seem quite fair on the whole, but apparently from prior screening at earlier levels of the educational system. Women are shunted by their socialization and education toward fields of graduate study that are generally more crowded, less productive of completed degrees, and less well funded, and that frequently offer poorer professional employment prospects.
Article
Regression models have been used in the social sciences at least since 1899, when Yule published a paper on the causes of pauperism. Regression models are now used to make causal arguments in a wide variety of applications, and it is perhaps time to evaluate the results. No definitive answers can be given, but this paper takes a rather negative view. Snow's work on cholera is presented as a success story for scientific reasoning based on nonexperimental data. Failure stories are also discussed, and comparisons may provide some insight. In particular, this paper suggests that statistical technique can seldom be an adequate substitute for good design, relevant data, and testing predictions against reality in a variety of settings.
The Book of Why: The New Science of Cause and Effect
  • J Pearl
  • D Mackenzie
Pearl, J. and D. Mackenzie (2018). The Book of Why: The New Science of Cause and Effect. New York: Basic Books.
Causal Inference in Statistics: A Primer Wiley
  • J Pearl
  • M Glymour
  • N P Jewell
Pearl, J., M. Glymour and N. P. Jewell (2016). Causal Inference in Statistics: A Primer. John Wiley & Sons.
European Transition to Secular Thought: Lessons for Muslims
  • A Zaman
Zaman, A. (2018). European Transition to Secular Thought: Lessons for Muslims. https://sites .google.com/site/azamanpublications/ie/islamic/european (accessed April 10, 2020).
The Book of Why? Basic Books
  • J Pearl