Content uploaded by Benjamin J. Bindewald
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Benjamin J. Bindewald on Jul 22, 2020
Content may be subject to copyright.
Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at
https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rept20
Educational Philosophy and Theory
ISSN: 0013-1857 (Print) 1469-5812 (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rept20
Speech and inquiry in public institutions of higher
education: Navigating ethical and epistemological
challenges
Benjamin Bindewald & Joshua Hawkins
To cite this article: Benjamin Bindewald & Joshua Hawkins (2020): Speech and inquiry in public
institutions of higher education: Navigating ethical and epistemological challenges, Educational
Philosophy and Theory, DOI: 10.1080/00131857.2020.1773794
To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/00131857.2020.1773794
Published online: 01 Jun 2020.
Submit your article to this journal
Article views: 2
View related articles
View Crossmark data
Speech and inquiry in public institutions of higher education:
Navigating ethical and epistemological challenges
Benjamin Bindewald
a
and Joshua Hawkins
b
a
Social Foundations of Education, Oklahoma State University, Stillwater, OK, USA;
b
Special Education,
Northwestern Oklahoma State University, Alva, OK, USA
ABSTRACT
How should those who value reasonable pluralism navigate ethical and
epistemological challenges related to speech and inquiry in higher edu-
cation? We propose the ethical pursuit of public knowledge as a guid-
ing vision for public colleges and universities with the understanding
that other institutions will serve different purposes. The ethical criterion
of mutuality calls for engagement across difference and reciprocal rec-
ognition of others’basic equality and liberty. To maintain epistemic
legitimacy, knowledge-production processes in these institutions should
elevate ideas warranted by public reasons that have withstood rigorous
critical scrutiny above those that have not. Some forms of speech—
including the expression of extremist views on both the Right and the
Left—will prove unreasonable and incompatible with the guiding vision
and should therefore be marginalized (but not necessarily suppressed)
within these institutions.
ARTICLE HISTORY
Received 21 April 2019
Revised 5 February 2020
Accepted 23 March 2020
KEYWORDS
Reasonable pluralism;
public knowledge;
mutuality; free speech;
higher education
Speech and inquiry in public institutions of higher education: navigating ethical
and epistemological challenges
In response to a ‘crisis of democratic institutions’in the present ‘post-Truth’era, the invitation
for submissions for this special issue raises questions about the scope and limitations of freedom
of expression in an ideal ‘open society’. It highlights concerns about the alt-Right’s exploitation
of ‘freedom of speech in liberal societies as a means of trading in ‘hate speech’and encouraging
others to adopt false and malicious ideas’. Referencing Foucault’s(1999) distinction between free
speech as license of tongue to say ‘the most stupid and dangerous things’and a privilege select-
ively granted to those speaking truth to power (2-5), it asks authors to consider the degree to
which speech should be regulated and how much it should ‘be encouraged and allowed in
schools and universities’. Recent calls from other leading outlets for educational scholarship
reflect a similar framing of these problems and their potential solutions.
We agree with the suggestion that there is a crisis of credibility facing democratic institutions,
that public discourse has become increasingly unreasonable, and that extremists on the Right
currently present some of the most pressing challenges for liberal democratic institutions. In our
judgment, however, the common framing in education is not particularly helpful for addressing
challenges specific to the particular context of public colleges and universities in the United
States (the focus of this article). That is, while threats to democracy and pluralism from the far-
CONTACT Benjamin Bindewald ben.bindewald@okstate.edu Social Foundations of Education, Oklahoma State
University, 213 Willard Hall, Oklahoma State University, Stillwater, OK, 74074.
ß2020 Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia
EDUCATIONAL PHILOSOPHY AND THEORY
https://doi.org/10.1080/00131857.2020.1773794
Right are mostly external to higher education, internal threats come most often from the far-Left.
But because people who lean to the Left are so far overrepresented in the academy, these ser-
ious problems receive far less scholarly attention than they deserve (Jussim, 2018).
We argue for an approach to speech and inquiry in higher education that offers a principled
framework through which to identify and challenge unreasonable views on both the Right and
Left and relegate them to the margins of academic discourse. To best serve diverse liberal,
democratic societies like the United States, we suggest, public institutions of higher education
should clarify their primary purposes and embrace norms of ethical and epistemic reciprocity.
Doing so would likely enhance their institutional credibility as well as their ability to effectively
challenge extremism and promote reasonable pluralism in the broader public sphere.
Theoretical framework
In the context of a deeply divided democratic society, a constructive response to diversity should
emphasize common interests while also allowing for the persistence of meaningful differences.
To effectively motivate engagement across such differences, it should offer reciprocal terms of
cooperation that reasonable people would accept. Such an approach could draw support away
from extremist movements and motivate a sufficiently large coalition of citizens with a wide
range of reasonable views to engage in more constructive public deliberations (More in
Common 2018). It could not, however, sustainably offer uncritical inclusion to those who reject
principles of reciprocity and basic equality or who would impose on others a narrow, dogmatic
conception of the good.
Pluralism
The Pluralism Project at Harvard University defines pluralism as ‘not diversity alone, but the ener-
getic engagement with diversity …’ This conceptualization of pluralism aims for ‘not just tolerance,
but the active seeking of understanding across lines of difference’.It calls for an ‘encounter of commit-
ments’through constructive dialogue, which involves ‘give and take, criticism and self-criticism …
both speaking and listening’. Rather than seeking universal agreement among everyone ‘at the
table’, this conceptualization of pluralism ‘involves the commitment to being at the table —with
one’s commitments …’ (Eck, 2006).
Constructive dialogue across difference is necessary for any well-functioning democratic insti-
tution. Engagement with others in good faith efforts to understand diverse perspectives is par-
ticularly important in the context of public institutions of higher education. In our view,
however, public colleges and universities should also encourage—in fact, they should put a pre-
mium on—epistemic justification and critical scrutiny of competing knowledge claims.
Distinguishing itself from an unsustainable form of radical relativism, our understanding of plural-
ism (at least within the particular context of public higher education) requires some overarching
‘metaperspective’to provide principled guidelines for engagement with diversity (Siegel,
2012, p.76).
On the one hand, to avoid merely replacing one variety of fundamentalism with another, the
overarching view cannot be overly determinant or exclusivist. On the other hand, any sustain-
able, principled framework would have to be, at least to some degree, exclusive. Thus, one is
confronted with what Karl Popper (1945, p. 581) called ‘the paradox of tolerance’—how can tol-
erant societies prevent intolerance from dominating without themselves having to exercise some
form of intolerance (i.e., an intolerance of intolerance)? As long as open societies can counter
intolerance and other challenges to pluralism ‘by rational argument and keep them in check by
public opinion’, he argued, ‘suppression would certainly be unwise’.
2 B. BINDEWALD AND J. HAWKINS
The challenge, then, for those who wish to promote pluralism in diverse societies is to make
the tent of inclusion as wide as possible without causing its legs to buckle under the weight of
its own contradictions. Rawls (1993) offers an ideal conception of reasonable pluralism guided by
principles of political liberalism, but he deals insufficiently with the facts of intolerance and dis-
engagement and does not have much to say about how education might address them. The
theory of mutuality offers additional tools for addressing these challenges.
Mutuality
Compatible with the understanding of pluralism described above, the theory of mutuality seeks
to motivate and develop ‘a will to relationship’or desire to engage across sustainable differences
(Creppell, 2008, p. 323). It aims to instill in citizens a commitment to ethical and epistemic reci-
procity. It is more ambitious than classical liberal tolerance, which merely prohibits individuals,
groups, or state agents from coercively suppressing speech or behavior they find objectionable.
Yet, it is less exacting than the radically relativistic (but often selectively applied) approach of
robust respect, which demands positive evaluation or affirmation of differences and romanticizes
diversity (Rosenblith & Bindewald, 2014).
Drawing from mutuality, the ethical component of our argument suggests that public institu-
tions should actively encourage recognition of the basic equality of all people, the universal right
to maintain differences, as well as a commitment to reciprocity and mutual respect for persons.
Informed by the ideal of mutuality, our understanding of pluralism encourages the free expres-
sion of a wide—but not unlimited—variety of views. As public institutions, however, state col-
leges and universities in the U.S. are accountable to the American people and legally obligated
to uphold constitutional laws pertaining to speech and expression.
Free speech and hate speech in the U.S
The First Amendment of the United States Constitution permits expression of an immense range
of diverse perspectives, including those that may be unreasonable, disrespectful, bigoted, and/or
potentially harmful. It protects vigorous criticism and peaceful protest of such views, as well,
which can contribute significantly to their social marginalization. Public officials are legally pro-
hibited from discriminating against individuals or groups based on their beliefs or coercively sup-
pressing speech on the basis of its political or religious content.
Short of granting blanket tolerance toward all forms of speech, however, the Constitution
requires that citizens refrain from engaging in forms of expression that directly and explicitly
incite violence, disorder, or lawlessness (e.g., Sunstein, 1995). For example, public demonstrations
that threaten to disturb the peace can be declared unlawful gatherings and dispersed by a
democratically sanctioned, lawful use of police force. It is also illegal for individuals ‘to make true
threats and incite imminent crimes against anyone …for any reason’or to use ‘fighting words’,
which include ‘face-to-face personal insults addressed to a specific person, of the sort that are
likely to start an immediate fight’(Volokh, 2015).
There is, however, ‘no ‘hate speech’exception to the First Amendment’(Volokh, 2015). We
understand hate speech to include forms of ‘expression whose dominant purpose is to insult or
denigrate members of a social group identified by such characteristics as race, ethnicity, religion,
or sexual orientation, or to arouse enmity or hostility against them’(Sumner, 2009, pp. 208–9).
Within this particular legal context, calls for more powerful institutional responses to potentially
harmful speech on campus draw our attention to important ethical and epistemological chal-
lenges. For example, such calls have prompted some institutions to implement speech codes,
bias response systems, unconscious bias training, and seminars designed to combat insensitive
EDUCATIONAL PHILOSOPHY AND THEORY 3
or insulting forms of expression that radical scholars identify as ‘microaggressions’(FIRE, 2017;
Snyder & Khalid, 2016; UCLA, 2014).
Advocates of free speech on both the Right and the Left have raised concerns about these
initiatives, which some critics consider little more than ‘a politically correct effort to prevent any-
one from voicing views that do not fall in line with a narrow ‘social justice’ideology’(Ben-
Porath, 2017, p. 11).
1
Critics of these efforts have argued that a substantial portion of reported
‘bias’or ‘hate’incidents on campus are more accurately described as expressions of mild disres-
pect, insensitivity, or mere political conflict (FIRE, 2017). Some have gone even further to chal-
lenge the narrative of ubiquitous hate speech on campus. For example, Wilfred Reilly (2019), an
African American scholar of race relations, concludes from an extensive study of over one hun-
dred high profile cases that, rather than facing an increase in the frequency or severity of hate
incidents, American colleges and universities are experiencing an epidemic of hate crime hoaxes.
Political terminology
We use the term ‘Left’in reference to anyone from moderate liberals and progressives who
mostly vote Democrat in the U.S. to radical socialists, anarchists, and allied identitarian move-
ments for historically marginalized groups. Similarly, we use the term ‘Right’to describe anyone
from classical liberals and moderate conservatives who mostly vote Republican to radical libertar-
ians, fascists, religious fundamentalists
2
, and allied identitarian movements for historically domin-
ant groups. We use the terms ‘radical’,‘far-Right’, and ‘far-Left’in reference to ‘those on the
extreme ends of this spectrum. Intolerance refers to an unwillingness to grant basic human rights
to those with whom one disagrees’, and, with the exception of radical libertarians, ‘the highest
levels of intolerance are usually at the extremes’(Jussim, 2018).
Reasonableness
In Living with Moral Disagreement, Moses (2016) suggests that, for democratic societies to func-
tion well, public deliberations must include a wide range of reasonable perspectives.
Paraphrasing Rawls (1993), she states, ‘The concept of ‘reasonable’herein excludes oppressive
and hateful views’(Footnote 12, p. 115). In an essay entitled, ‘Diversity of Thought on Campus –
To a Point’, she elaborates upon her position and considers how it applies within the particular
context of higher education. Focusing on bigoted forms of expression from far-Right political
activists like Richard Spencer and Milo Yiannopolis, she identifies white supremacist, sexist,
homophobic, transphobic, and any other ‘views that are indefensible or intimidating, especially
to marginalized groups’as beyond the limits of reasonableness (Moses, 2017, pp. 533–534).
We are sympathetic to the concerns reflected in the common framing and echoed in Moses’s
position—for one’s legal right to free speech is not the same thing as epistemic or ethical justifi-
cation for expressing hateful, intimidating, or malicious views. Overtly bigoted expressions that
serve no clear academic purpose are indeed unreasonable. However, stigmatizing labels lose
their power when used in a cavalier manner, and, as such, moralistic labels alone do not effect-
ively demonstrate a perspective’s unreasonableness or justify its exclusion from public delibera-
tions. By what processes and criteria, then, ought stakeholders in public colleges and universities
to make such judgments? How should they respond to people who express unreasonable views?
Answers to these questions have important ethical and epistemological implications for higher
education. Below, we consider two competing visions for public colleges and universities and
their distinctly different responses to these questions.
4 B. BINDEWALD AND J. HAWKINS
A radical vision for higher education
Critical theorist Herbert Marcuse, the intellectual leader of the New Left in the 1960s–1970s,
greatly influenced the radical shift in campus culture and politics that has taken place since that
time. His profound impact is clearly evident in the rhetoric and behavior of many of today’s cam-
pus activists (e.g., Sculos & Walsh, 2016). Rejecting the liberal values of reciprocal tolerance and
free speech, Marcuse (1965) called for ‘intolerance of movements from the Right, and toleration
of movements from the Left’(109). More specifically, he sought to justify ‘restraining the liberty
of the Right’with the goal of ‘strengthening the oppressed against the oppressors’(119-120).
The New Left thoroughly embraced discriminating (in)tolerance as a guide to militant, often
violent political action during the 1960s and 70s. Facing strong resistance from the federal gov-
ernment and wanting to distance themselves from communism’s spectacular failures and mass
atrocities (e.g., Courtois & Kramer, 2014), however, many former New Left activists settled into
academic positions. Securing control of campus culture and politics was a primary component of
the movement’s‘strategy of the long march through the institutions’in which a ‘militant minority’
(Marcuse, 1972, p. 55) would launch an aggressive campaign to ‘bend’the major social, cultural,
and political institutions ‘in the direction of socialism’(57).
Though advocates of discriminating (in)tolerance probably represent a numerical minority in
the academy, the threats to reasonable pluralism and the credibility of democratic institutions
that they present should not be minimized or ignored. As countless examples in history have
shown, an intolerant, militant minority can, in fact, exercise significant power and do great harm.
Many who sympathize with radical political aims do not endorse violence or intolerance, but
they often fail to adequately challenge those who do. Likewise, intellectual supporters like
Marcuse do not usually commit acts of violence or intolerance themselves, but they provide the-
oretical justification and rhetorical cover for those who do (Jussim, 2018). As a result, the far-Left
has a significant amount of power and influence in higher education that is disproportionate to
their numbers and the reasonableness of their ideas.
The academy’s‘critical turn’
Since taking a ‘critical turn’in the 1970s, radical politics and epistemology have become increas-
ingly mainstream in education, the social sciences, humanities, and other academic fields
(Gottesman, 2016). An especially noteworthy example, Foucault’s(1984) conceptualization of
knowledge/power provides radical scholar-activists a discursive strategy for accepting or rejecting
knowledge claims not primarily on the basis of their epistemological warrants but according to
whose political interests they potentially serve (Zhao & Bindewald, 2018). The ultimate goal of this
approach, then, is not to pursue ‘truth’in any normative sense—the traditional aim of scholar-
ship—by identifying the best warranted knowledge claims and elevating those above the rest.
Rather, by implicitly redefining ‘truth’in reference to forms of expression that support radical
political interests, it grants a sense of academic legitimacy to far-Left activism and delegitimizes
opposing arguments without regard to their epistemic warrants.
It is this reconceptualized meaning of the word ‘truth’that Foucault likely has in mind in his
suggestion that free speech should be reserved for those speaking ‘truth’to power. Presuming
to occupy the moral high ground, some proponents of this approach (e.g., Applebaum, 2003;
Boler, 2004; DiAngelo & Sensoy, 2014) assert a special right to determine who gets to speak, on
which issues, and by what standards their claims will be evaluated (Zhao & Bindewald, 2018).
Their radical interpretation of social justice demands that ‘dominant knowledge claims must be
silenced …’ so that marginalized perspectives can be advanced (DiAngelo & Sensoy 2014, pp. 3
and 4). In other words, regardless of epistemic warrants, perspectives favored by the far-Left and
allied identitarian movements should be treated as true/good and opposing views as false/bad
on the basis of whose political interests they purportedly serve. Toward that end, proponents of
EDUCATIONAL PHILOSOPHY AND THEORY 5
the radical vision selectively grant license of tongue and ‘epistemic privilege’to their allies
(Gottesman, 2016, p. 98).
From this perspective, violating the basic rights of political opponents (especially members of
so-called ‘oppressor’groups) is indefinitely justified as a means to the radical Left’s utopian ends:
Until all voices are recognized equally, we must operate within a context of historicized ethics which
consciously privileges the insurrectionary and dissenting voices, sometimes at the minor cost of silencing
those voices that have been permitted dominant status for the past centuries [emphasis added] (Boler,
2014, p. 13).
The most salient question to ask individuals who object to these practices, a proponent of
the radical vision suggests, ‘is not, are your democratic rights being violated, but rather, are you
suffering?’(Wahl, 2018, p. 532, paraphrasing Rorty, 1989, p. 198). In the spirit of Marcuse, these
scholars selectively demand robust respect for some, while explicitly justifying intolerance toward
others (Campbell, 2018).
It is, therefore, unreasonable to characterize the expression of such views as speaking truth to
power—particularly when they are articulated from positions of power. For example, consider
the case of Dr. Charles H. F. Davis III, who has explicitly endorsed violence against ‘Whiteness’
from his ‘Black Identity Extremist’Twitter account, which drew the attention of Right-wing media
(Rubbelke, 2017). Though he claims white supremacists have waged a campaign to have him
fired, he maintains his tenure-track faculty position and prestigious appointment as Chief
Strategy Officer and Director of Research for the Race and Equity Center at the University of
Southern California (Menahan, 2017).
Progressive campus communities’reluctance to challenge overreach from the far-Left allows
radical activists to excuse themselves from generally applicable scholarly standards. Some schol-
ars in identity-oriented fields, for instance, suggest that identity groups have their own distinct
‘ways of knowing’. Because inquiry paradigms that require justification of knowledge claims with
public reasons and evidence were developed primarily by white men, it follows, they have no
relevance to people outside of that group. Thus, when institutions of higher education require
members of historically marginalized groups to justify knowledge claims (whose validity the
claimants presumably expect others to accept) with so-called white/male standards of evidence,
they engage in a form epistemic injustice.
3
Matias and Diangelo’s(2013) peer reviewed article in Educational Foundations on ‘white neur-
osis and racial cray-cray’exemplifies major problems of the radical vision. The authors ‘employ
interdisciplinary approaches of critical Whiteness studies and critical race theory’(4) to determine
that ‘raising White children to be White is a form of child abuse’that produces the condition of
‘white neurosis’(11). ‘Not seeking therapy to address’, this pathology ‘forces upon People of
Color the need to placate the irrationality’of white colleagues (11-12). ‘In stopping the abuse,
White norms of rationality should not be the standard for which change is measured…’ (17).
For, if their psychiatric diagnosis and prescribed treatment for the pathology of whiteness must
be justified with public reasons and empirical evidence rather than appeals to ‘emo-cognitions’,
‘parables’, and ‘poetic letters’, the authors suggest, ‘we lose the only remedy we have to White
racial toxicity’(14).
‘Being Critical About Being Critical’
Protecting members of historically marginalized groups from arbitrary forms of discrimination
and recognizing their equal human rights are requirements of the vision of mutuality and rea-
sonable pluralism that we endorse. Suggestions that campus radicals should have ‘license of
tongue’to engage in overtly bigoted speech or that they have the authority to (perpetually?)
discriminate for political purposes (DiAngelo & Sensoy, 2014, p. 7; Boler, 2004, p. 3), however, are
not. The radical vision’s discriminatory approach is, at best, a nonstarter for the majority of
6 B. BINDEWALD AND J. HAWKINS
Americans (More in Common, 2018). At worst, it alienates potential allies, undermines progres-
sive aims, and exacerbates existing political and social conflict. Some influential philosophers of
education (e.g., Ben-Porath, 2017; Burbules, 2016; Hytten, 2015) have, however, argued for a
more measured approach to speech and inquiry in the academy.
Urging caution against the radical vision, for example, Burbules (2016) emphasizes the import-
ance of ‘being critical about being critical’. He notes that many scholars in the ‘critical’(i.e., rad-
ical) tradition take ‘a dichotomous view of conflict: Group A is always right, and group B is
always to blame; all conflict is the result of X, and if you can just transform or overthrow X,
everything will be better’(3). Alternatively, “there cannot be simple dualities of oppressor and
oppressed, and one’s theory of social change or transformation cannot be reduced to simply tak-
ing sides in advancing one group’s interests over another’s or overthrowing one particular sys-
tem and replacing it with something else”(3). A more constructive solution, he argues, ‘is an
ongoing, iterative process of critique, reform, and self-questioning’that includes thoughtful con-
sideration of ‘the history of idealism gone awry, of good intentions that end up yielding their
opposite, of absolutisms that end up creating their own oppressions …’ (3).
A Vision of Mutuality and Reasonable Pluralism in Higher Education
Toward a vision of mutuality and reasonable pluralism, we propose the ethical pursuit of public
knowledge as a guiding mission for public colleges and universities (with the understanding that
other institutions will have different primary purposes). The distinction between epistemologic-
ally warranted public knowledge (Kitcher, 2011) and ‘personal’(i.e., not necessarily warranted) pri-
vate belief, however, is an essential feature of this vision. Public institutions of higher education
should focus primarily on the production of public knowledge, calling on participants in such
processes to assume the role of public scholars.
Unlike preachers, lawyers, politicians, and professional activists, whose work often prioritizes
other interests, scholars, if that word means anything at all, should place a premium on epistemic
warrants. Scholars in/of public education, then, should justify their claims with public warrants—
that is, with reasons and evidence that can be subjected to critical scrutiny by a community of
competent professionals and justified to the public. Though this approach has necessary limits, it
should not be confused with positivism, scientism, identitarianism, or an overly restrictive meth-
odological fundamentalism (e.g., Denzin et al., 2006). To the contrary, publicly warranted scholar-
ship, in accordance with reasonable pluralism, would include a wide variety of reasonable
perspectives, regardless of their origins. It would consist of quantitative, qualitative, and mixed
methods approaches to empirical research as well as philosophical inquiries (and some studies
that contain elements of each).
When scholars make empirical or moral/political claims that they expect others to accept as
justified or legitimate, they assume these claims have normative force—that is, they imply that
others ought to also consider them valid and worthy of high epistemic status. If one expects
others in a context of great diversity of perspective to accept the legitimacy of or obligations
associated with one’s claims, then such claims require justification in the form of public reasons
and evidence. While appeals to private beliefs, subjective interests, or psychological experiences
may be personally meaningful and often serve as legitimate starting points for scholarly inquiry,
they are, by themselves, insufficient sources of epistemic justification for public knowledge.
To determine whether a public knowledge claim is warranted, one should first attempt to
understand and then critically evaluate its public reasons and evidence. By ‘critical’evaluation,
we mean applying tools of critical thinking to a knowledge claim and its epistemic warrants; not
accepting or rejecting the claim’s validity on the basis of its compatibility with the political com-
mitments of critical theories.
4
Values will, however, inevitably inform such judgments. Although
facts and values are not irrelevant to one another (e.g., empirically warranted claims could be
EDUCATIONAL PHILOSOPHY AND THEORY 7
used in support of ethically sound or unsound practices), participants in knowledge production
processes should carefully demarcate empirical from ethical/political claims and warrants to the
greatest extent possible (i.e., a claim could very well be epistemologically warranted and incom-
patible with one’s political commitments).
Values associated with reasonable pluralism and mutuality would play a significant role in the
knowledge production processes we envision. Except in extreme cases that involve individual
harm or threaten public safety, however, we argue that public institutions should generally
emphasize ‘epistemologically relevant values’(Phillips & Burbules, 2000, pp. 54 and 55).
Epistemologically relevant values include clarity and precision of language, logical coherence in
argumentation, commitments to justifying one’s claims with public warrants, ‘dedication to the
pursuit of truth, openness to counter evidence, receptiveness to criticism, accuracy of measure-
ments and observations, honesty and openness in reporting results, and the like’(Phillips &
Burbules, 2000, pp. 54 and 55).
As necessary (but, by themselves, insufficient) prerequisites for the ethical pursuit of public
knowledge, free speech and open inquiry are also, in important ways, epistemologically relevant
values. They contribute immensely to the institutional credibility, health, and sustainability of
public colleges and universities. Protecting free speech and open inquiry from coercive suppres-
sion promotes freedom of conscience and provides necessary checks against unjustified forms of
discrimination, authoritarian policies and practices, and the entrenchment of orthodoxy. These
institutions are accountable to the public, but protections of academic freedom should prevent
the public from coercively suppressing unpopular viewpoints in the academy. These protections
do not, however, require uncritical inclusion of unreasonable forms of expression.
When campus speech explicitly calls for or directly incites physical violence or lawlessness, it
should be suppressed by the appropriate, democratically sanctioned law enforcement authorities.
For example, the 2017 gathering of torch-wielding white nationalists at the University of Virginia
in Charlottesville drew upon violent imagery associated with Nazis and Klansmen, included pri-
vate militia armed with assault rifles, and clearly intended to threaten and intimidate political
opponents (Heim, 2017). As such, local police should have more swiftly declared the event an
unlawful assembly and dispersed the crowd. A more timely and forceful police intervention
would likely have prevented much of the street violence that followed, including, most signifi-
cantly, the murder of counter-protestor Heather Heyer.
Similarly justified is the use of police force against far-Left militants who harass, intimidate,
and attempt to violate the civil liberties of political opponents. Consider, for example, the 2017
student takeover of Evergreen State College. Angered by professor Bret Weinstein’s public objec-
tion to a racially segregated ‘day of absence/presence’in which white people were pressured to
absent themselves from campus, a mob of approximately 50 students disrupted his class, sur-
rounded and accosted him and his students, denounced him as a racist, and demanded that he
resign or be fired. The students then barricaded themselves and several administrators in the
library. Some can be seen on camera expressing racially chauvinist and bigoted sentiments and
menacing those who objected to their unreasonable speech and behavior. The college president
placated the mob and, in spite of multiple threats of violence, ordered campus police to stand
down. At least initially, faculty and administrators roundly condemned Weinstein’s alleged racism
and praised the militant students.
5
These are clear examples where intolerance should not have been tolerated and hate speech
should have been directly challenged and intentionally marginalized. When objectionable speech
does not warrant a coercive response but includes unreasonable, offensive, disrespectful, or big-
oted content, public institutions should call it what it is and respond to it directly (Lawrence,
2017). Beyond their important role in protecting free speech, public universities have additional
obligations that include subjecting ideas to critical scrutiny and calling for them to be justified
to the public. Some expressions will prove unreasonable and incompatible with the guiding pur-
pose, and should, therefore, be actively marginalized within these institutions. For example, if
8 B. BINDEWALD AND J. HAWKINS
extremists and provocateurs engage in unreasonable, disrespectful, or bigoted forms of expres-
sion, these views should be directly confronted with peaceful, lawful protests, reasonable coun-
terarguments, and formal institutional counter-messaging.
When a member of the campus community claims to have experienced harm or intimidation
from the expression of a particular viewpoint, such claims should be met with a presumption of
worth. Institutions have an ethical obligation to directly challenge and counter actual hate
speech, regardless of its source or target. No one should be expected to respectfully engage
with those who clearly and intentionally insult them, openly question their basic equality as
human beings, or suggest that it would be okay to violate their democratic rights. Whether from
the Right or Left, campus speech should be critically scrutinized, explicit incitements to violence
suppressed, and unreasonable expressions marginalized.
Epistemic processes, assessments, and the ways in which participants are treated do, however,
raise significant ethical considerations. Power plays a significant role in such processes, as Foucault
(1984) and many others have noted. As such, potential abuses of power ought to also be sub-
jected to critical scrutiny from a wide variety of perspectives (Siegel, 2012). Yet, contrary to
Foucault, warranted knowledge claims and arbitrary assertions of power are not the same thing.
Claims are not reasonable or unreasonable simply because they are uttered by a particular group
of people or because they serve specific political interests. Instead, knowledge claims made by all
people, from all groups, should be granted an initial presumption of worth and should, therefore,
be taken seriously enough to scrutinize according to public principles of reason.
Assessment of a claim is not the same thing as an evaluation of the human worth of the
claimant, although it could be subjectively experienced that way. We treat others with respect as
persons by taking their views seriously—not by granting them automatic, uncritical acceptance.
It is possible, however, that after giving due consideration we can justifiably determine that
some claims do not have normative force or warrant the same epistemic status as others. If pub-
lic institutions do away with reciprocal obligations to justify public knowledge claims with public
reasons and evidence, they become unable to credibly marginalize unreasonable views or effect-
ively establish that purported victims of injustice are actually victims, for such claims would also
require some sort of publicly assessible, reasoned justification (Siegel, 1995).
We acknowledge that there will be individuals and groups who express views at odds with mutu-
ality and reasonable pluralism. Public institutions should marginalize these views. If people wish to
establish free associations guided by and committed to the promotion of unreasonable views in the
private sphere, however, they should be permitted to do so. Private institutions are not bound by
the same First Amendment constraints as public institutions, and they can legally promote sectarian
views and limit or restrict speech inconsistent with their guiding mission and values (FIRE, 2015).
Conclusion
Highlighted in the common framing in education, extremists on the Right indeed exploit free
speech protections and ‘post-Truth’conditions to spread falsehoods, denigrate historically margi-
nalized groups, and advance narrow identitarian interests. Scholars of education are justified in
their efforts to challenge these significant threats to pluralism and liberal democracy. De-empha-
sized in our field, however, are the far-Left’s probable contributions to the chaotic ethical and
epistemological conditions in which their counterparts on the far-Right presently thrive. The
aggressive campaign to bend higher education and other liberal, democratic institutions in the
direction of socialism has, in our judgment, come at a significant cost to institutional legitimacy
and credibility.
A recent PEW Research Center survey found that 61% of American adults believe higher edu-
cation is headed in the wrong direction, and strong majorities of both Democrats and
Republicans prioritize free speech on campus even when some students find particular view-
points upsetting (PEW, 2018). Along with the arguments presented above, these facts suggest to
EDUCATIONAL PHILOSOPHY AND THEORY 9
us that the type of responses hinted at in the common framing are ill advised. In our judgment,
doubling down on discriminating (in)tolerance, identity politics, and radical epistemology in the
academy would further undermine institutional credibility, inflame intolerant movements on the
far-Right, and intensify ongoing public divestment from higher education.
Specifically, suppressing dissenting views and selectively distributing ethical and epistemic
privileges on the basis of political perspective or group identity—even when done in the
euphemistic language of social justice or as a supposed corrective to past and present injust-
ice—erodes trust and disincentivizes good faith engagement across difference. Alternatively,
more substantive critiques of unreasonable views and behavior from the far-Left inside the acad-
emy could give institutions of higher education a boost in credibility needed to more effectively
confront external threats to reasonable pluralism and democracy from the far-Right. Rather than
mirroring the forms of injustice, discrimination, and unreasonableness that often characterize the
broader world, the ethical and epistemic norms of public colleges and universities should model
those most of us would like to extend to it.
Disclosure statement
No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).
Notes
1. Here, Ben-Porath is merely framing the debate about free speech on campus and is not endorsing this view.
2. In the West, rightwing religious fundamentalists primarily include dogmatic believers in the Judeo-Christian
traditions, whereas other fundamentalists, including Islamist extremists, often ally with the far-Left
(Walzer 2015).
3. See, e.g., Phillips (2012) for a critical review of several influential examples from this body of literature.
4. See Burbules and Berk (1999) for a clearly articulated distinction between these two uses of ‘critical’.
5. See links to videos in Heying and Weinstein (2017).
Notes on contributors
Benjamin Bindewald is former secondary social studies teacher who completed his Ph.D. in curriculum and instruc-
tion with a focus in social foundations of education at Clemson University. He is now an assistant professor of
social foundations at Oklahoma State University. His primary scholarly interests include tolerance and its limits in
pluralist, democratic societies and the epistemological and ethical challenges such considerations present for public
schools and universities.
Joshua Hawkins is a former K-12 teacher and administrator who earned a Ph.D. in educational psychology from
Oklahoma State University. He is now an assistant professor of special education at Northwestern Oklahoma State
University. His primary scholarly interests include retention, resilience, and relationships in special education, and
philosophical and psychological foundations of education.
References
Applebaum, B. (2003). Social justice, democratic education and the silencing of words that wound. Journal of Moral
Education,32(2), 151–162. https://doi.org/10.1080/0305724032000072924
Ben-Porath, S. (2017). Free speech on campus. University of Pennsylvania Press.
Boler, M. (2004). Democratic dialogue in education: Troubling speech, disturbing silence. Peter Lang.
Burbules, N. (2016). Being critical about being critical. A response to toward a transformative criticality for demo-
cratic citizenship education. Democracy and Education,24(2), 1–5.
Burbules, N., & Berk, R. (1999). Critical thinking and critical pedagogy: Relations, differences, and limits. In
Thomas S. Popkewitz and Lynn Fendler (Eds.). Critical theories in education, Routledge.
Campbell, B. (2018). Sarah Jeong and the victimhood motte and bailey. The Victimhood report. http://victimhoodcul-
ture.com/index.php/2018/08/07/sarah-jeong-and-the-victimhood-motte-and-bailey/
10 B. BINDEWALD AND J. HAWKINS
Courtois, S., & Kramer, M. (2014). The black book of communism: Crimes, terror, repression. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press. https://doi.org/10.1086/ahr/68.4.1044
Creppell, I. (2008). Toleration, politics, and the role of mutuality. In Toleration and its limits, Melissa S. Williams and
Jeremy Waldron (Eds.). New York University Press.
Denzin, N., Lincoln, Y., & Giardina, M. (2006). Disciplining qualitative research. International Journal of Qualitative
Studies in Education,19(6), 769–782. https://doi.org/10.1080/09518390600975990
Eck, D. (2006). What is pluralism? The pluralism project. Accessed October 24, 2019. http://pluralism.org/what-is-
pluralism/
Foucault, M. (1984). Truth and power. In P. Rabinow (Ed.), The Foucault reader (pp. 51–75). Pantheon Books. https://
doi.org/10.1086/ahr/84.3.763
Foucault, M. (1999). The meaning and evolution of the word parrhesia –six lectures given by Michel Foucault at
the University of California at Berkeley, Oct–Nov. 1983 in Discourse & Truth: the Problematization of Parrhesia.
Foundation for Individual Rights in Education (FIRE) (2017). Bias response team report 2017. https://www.thefire.
org/first-amendment-library/special-collections/fire-guides/bias-response-team-report-2017/
Foundation for Individual Rights in Education (FIRE) (2015). FIRE’s Guide to first-year orientation and thought reform
on campus. https://d28htnjz2elwuj.cloudfront.net/wp-content/uploads/2015/07/29150208/FIRE-Guide-Orientation-
and-Thought-Reform.pdf
Gottesman, I. (2016). The critical turn in education: From Marxist critique to poststructuralist feminism to critical theo-
ries of race. Routledge.
Heim, J. (2017, August 14). Recounting a day of rage, hate, violence and death: How a rally of white, tragic week-
end. Washington Post. Accessed November 9, 2019. https://www.washingtonpost.com/graphics/2017/local/char-
lottesville-timeline/
Heying, H., Weinstein, B. (December 12, 2017). Bonfire of the academies: Two professors on how leftist intolerance
is killing higher education. Washington Examiner.https://www.washingtonexaminer.com/bonfire-of-the-academ-
ies-two-professors-on-how-leftist-intolerance-is-killing-higher-education
Hytten, K. (2015). Ethics in teaching for democracy and social justice. Democracy & Education,23(2), 1–10.
Jussim, L., Areo (2018). The reality of the rise of an intolerant and radical Left on campus. Accessed March 17, 2018.
https://areomagazine.com/2018/03/17/the-reality-of-the-rise-of-an-intolerant-and-radical-left-on-campus/
Kitcher, P. (2011). Public knowledge and its discontents. Theory & Research in Education,9(2), 103–124.
Lawrence, F. (2017). Free Speech 101: The assault on the First Amendment on college campuses. Senate
Committee on the Judiciary. Accessed June 20, 2017. https://www.judiciary.senate.gov/imo/media/doc/06-20-
17%20Lawrence%20Testimony.pdf
Marcuse, H. (1965). A critique of pure tolerance. Beacon Press.
Marcuse, H. (1972). Counterrevolution and revolt. Beacon Press.
Matias, C., & DiAngelo, R. (2013). Beyond the face of race: Emo-cognitive explorations of white neurosis and racial
cray-cray. Educational Foundations. Summer–Fall 2013.
Menahan, C. (2017). USC prof: ‘Whiteness’must be ‘by any and all means, destroyed’, Information Liberation. http://
www.informationliberation.com/?id=57563%255C
More in Common (2018). ‘Hidden tribes’report. https://hiddentribes.us/pdf/hidden_tribes_report.pdf
Moses, M.C. (2016). Living with moral disagreement: The enduring controversy about affirmative action. University of
Chicago Press.
Moses, M.C. (2017). From the editor: Diversity of thought on campus—to a point. Educational Theory,67(5),
531–536.
PEW (2018). Most Americans say higher ed is heading in wrong direction, but partisans disagree on why. Pew
Research Center. https://www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2018/07/26/most-americans-say-higher-ed-is-heading-in-
wrong-direction-but-partisans-disagree-on-why/
Phillips, D. C., & Burbules, N. (2000). Postpositivism and educational research. Rowman & Littlefield.
Phillips, D. C. (2012). A critical review of representative sources on multicultural epistemology. In C. Ruitenberg &
D.C. Phillips (Eds.), Education, culture and epistemological diversity: Mapping a disputed terrain (pp. 11–38),
Springer.
Popper, K. (1945). The open society & its enemies (Vol. 1). University Press.
Reilly, W. (2019). Hate crime hoax: How the left is selling a fake race war. Regnery Publishing.
Rawls, J. (1993). Political liberalism. Columbia University Press.
Rosenblith, S., & Bindewald, B. (2014). Between mere tolerance and robust respect: Mutuality as a basis for civic
education in pluralist democracies. Educational Theory,64(6), 589–606. https://doi.org/10.1111/edth.12085
Rorty, R. (1989). Contingency, irony, and solidarity. Cambridge University Press.
Rubbelke, N. (2017). USC professor defends tweet promoting violence against whiteness, The college fix.https://
www.thecollegefix.com/post/38304/
Sculos, B., & Walsh, S. (2016). The counterrevolutionary campus: Herbert Marcuse and the suppression of student
protest movements. New Political Science,38(4), 516–532. https://doi.org/10.1080/07393148.2016.1228580
EDUCATIONAL PHILOSOPHY AND THEORY 11
Siegel, H. (1995). Radical’pedagogy requires ‘conservative’epistemology. Journal of Philosophy of Education,29(1),
33–46. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9752.1995.tb00339.x
Siegel, H. (2012). Epistemological diversity and education research: Much ado about nothing much?. In Ruitenberg
& Phillips (Eds.), Education, culture and epistemological diversity: mapping a disputed terrain (pp. 65–84). Springer.
Snyder & Khalid, (2016). The rise of bias response teams on campus. New Republic.https://newrepublic.com/article/
132195/rise-bias-response-teams-campus
Sumner, L. (2009). Incitement and the regulation of hate speech in Canada. In I. Hare & J. Weinstein (Eds.), Extreme
speech and democracy (pp. 204–220). Oxford University Press.
Sunstein, C. (1995). Is violent speech a right? Advocacy of illegal violence to kill people is not necessarily constitu-
tionally protected speech. The American Prospect, Summer 1995. http://prospect.org/article/violent-speech-right
UCLA (2014). Tool: Recognizing microaggressions and the messages they send. Diversity in the Classroom, UCLA
Diversity & Faculty Development. https://academicaffairs.ucsc.edu/events/documents/Microaggressions_
Examples_Arial_2014_11_12.pdf
Volokh, E. (2015, May 7). No, there’sno‘hate speech’exception to the First Amendment. The Washington Post.
Wahl, R. (2018). Balancing goods, intellectual honesty, and transcendent principles: A response to ‘Tolerance and
free speech in education: A Habermasian perspective. Philosophy of Education 2018, University of Illinois Press.
Walzer, M. (2015). Islamism and the left. Dissent Magazine. https://www.dissentmagazine.org/article/islamism-and-
the-left
Zhao, G., & Bindewald, B. (2018). Tolerance and free speech in education: A Habermasian perspective. Philosophy of
Education 2018. University of Illinois Press.
12 B. BINDEWALD AND J. HAWKINS