Conference PaperPDF Available

A Quantitative Reasoning Framing of Concept Construction

Authors:

Abstract and Figures

Researchers are producing a growing number of studies that illustrate the importance of quantitative and covariational reasoning for students' mathematical development. These researchers' contributions often are in the context of learning of specific topics or developing particular reasoning processes. In both contexts, researchers are detailed in their descriptions of the intended topics or reasoning processes. There is, however, a lack of specificity relative to generalized criteria for the construction of a concept. We address this lack of specificity by introducing the construct of an abstracted quantitative structure. We discuss the construct, ideas informing its development and criteria, and empirical examples of student actions that illustrate its use. We also discuss potential implications for research and teaching.
Content may be subject to copyright.
A Quantitative Reasoning Framing of Concept Construction
Kevin C. Moore Biyao Liang Irma E. Stevens
University of Georgia University of Georgia University of Georgia
Halil I. Tasova Teo Paoletti Yufeng Ying
University of Georgia Montclair State University University of Georgia
Researchers are producing a growing number of studies that illustrate the importance of
quantitative and covariational reasoning for students’ mathematical development. These
researchers’ contributions often are in the context of learning of specific topics or developing
particular reasoning processes. In both contexts, researchers are detailed in their descriptions of
the intended topics or reasoning processes. There is, however, a lack of specificity relative to
generalized criteria for the construction of a concept. We address this lack of specificity by
introducing the construct of an abstracted quantitative structure. We discuss the construct, ideas
informing its development and criteria, and empirical examples of student actions that illustrate
its use. We also discuss potential implications for research and teaching.
Keywords: Quantitative reasoning, Covariational reasoning, Abstraction, Concept.
Steffe and Thompson enacted and sustained research programs that have characterized
students’ (and teachers’) mathematical development in terms of their conceiving and reasoning
about measurable or countable attributes (see Steffe & Olive, 2010; Thompson & Carlson, 2017).
Thompson (1990, 2011) formalized such reasoning into a system of mental operations he termed
quantitative reasoning. Over the past few decades, other researchers have adopted quantitative
reasoning to investigate students’ and teachers’ meanings in various ways. Some researchers
have adopted quantitative reasoning to characterize individuals’ meanings within specific topical
or representational areas including exponential relationships (Castillo-Garsow, 2010; Ellis,
Özgür, Kulow, Williams, & Amidon, 2015), graphs or coordinate systems (Frank, 2017; Lee,
2017; Lee, Moore, & Tasova, 2019), and function (Oehrtman, Carlson, & Thompson, 2008;
Paoletti & Moore, 2018). Other researchers have adopted quantitative reasoning to characterize
types of individuals’ reasoning. A predominant example is reasoning about quantities changing
in tandem, or covarying (e.g., Carlson, Jacobs, Coe, Larsen, & Hsu, 2002; Johnson, 2012, 2015b;
Saldanha & Thompson, 1998; Stalvey & Vidakovic, 2015).
We introduce the construct abstracted quantitative structure that marries and extends these
two research themes by offering framing criteria for concept construction. Defined generally, an
abstracted quantitative structure is a system of quantitative operations a person has interiorized to
the extent they can operate as if it is independent of specific figurative material. That person can
thus re-present this structure in several ways including to accommodate to novel experiences
permitting the associated quantitative operations. As we illustrate in this paper, an abstracted
quantitative structure is a type of quantitative reasoning that has implications for an individual’s
meanings within specific topical or representational areas, and her or his engagement in other
related forms of reasoning. In what follows, we first discuss background information on
quantitative (and covariational) reasoning that underpins the abstracted quantitative structure
construct. We then provide a more formal definition for an abstracted quantitative structure and
data to illustrate both indications and contraindications of individuals having constructed such a
structure. We close with its implications for research and teaching.
Background
Quantitative Reasoning
Thompson (2011) defined quantitative reasoning as the mental operations involved in
conceiving a context as entailing measurable attributes (i.e., quantities) and relationships
between those attributes (i.e., quantitative relationships). A premise of quantitative reasoning is
that quantities and their relationships are idiosyncratic constructions that occur and develop over
time (e.g., hours, weeks, or even years). A researcher or a teacher cannot take quantities or their
relationships as a given when working with students or teachers (Izsák, 2003; Moore, 2013;
Thompson, 2011). Furthermore, and reflecting one implication of the present work, a researcher
or teacher should not assume a student has constructed a system of quantities and their
relationships based on actions within only one context (e.g., situation, graph, or formula).
Thompson (Smith III & Thompson, 2008; Thompson, 1990) distinguished between
quantitative operations/magnitudes and arithmetic operations/measures to differentiate between
the mental actions involved in constructing a quantity via a quantitative relationship and the
actions used to determine a quantity’s numerical measure. Following Thompson (1990), we
illustrate these distinctions using a comparison between two heights. Thompson (1990) described
that an additive comparison requires one to construct an image of the measurable attribute that
indicates by how much one height exceeds the other height (Figure 1). Constructing such a
quantity through the quantitative operation of comparing two other quantities additively does not
depend on having numerical measures, nor does it require executing a calculation; an important
aspect of Thompson’s quantitative reasoning is that it foregrounds constructing and operating on
magnitudes (i.e., amount-ness) of quantities in the context of figurative material (e.g., coordinate
systems and phenomena) that permit those operations. Arithmetic operations, on the other hand,
are those operations between numerical measures such as addition, subtraction, multiplication,
etc. that one uses to determine a quantity’s measure, and are often in the context of inscriptions
or glyphs that signify quantities but do not provide the perceptual material to operate on
quantitatively (Moore, Stevens, Paoletti, Hobson, & Liang, online).
Figure 1. An image of an additive comparison based in magnitudes
Covariational Reasoning
A form of quantitative reasoning involves constructing relationships between two quantities
that vary in tandem, or covariational reasoning (Carlson et al., 2002; Saldanha & Thompson,
1998; Thompson & Carlson, 2017). Researchers have conveyed that covariational reasoning is
critical for key concepts of K–16 mathematics including function (Carlson, 1998; Oehrtman et
al., 2008), modeling dynamic situations (Carlson et al., 2002; Johnson, 2012, 2015b; Paoletti &
Moore, 2017), and calculus (Johnson, 2015a; Thompson, 1994; Thompson & Silverman, 2007).
Researchers have also illustrated that covariational reasoning is critical to constructing function
classes (Ellis, 2007; Lobato & Siebert, 2002; Moore, 2014).
Carlson et al. (2002), Confrey and Smith (1995), Ellis (2011), Johnson (2015a, 2015b), and
Thompson and Carlson (2017) are researchers who have detailed covariation frameworks and
mental actions. Due to space constraints and the empirical examples we use below, we narrow
our focus to a mental action (or operation) identified by Carlson et al. (2002). A critical mental
action, especially for differentiating between various function classes, is to compare amounts of
change (Figure 2, MA3). MA3 is also important for understanding and justifying that a graph
and its curvature appropriately model covarying quantities of a situation (Figure 3) (Stevens &
Moore, 2016). Furthermore, and as we illustrate in more detail below, such reasoning enables
understanding invariance among different representations of quantities’ covariation (Moore,
Paoletti, & Musgrave, 2013), which is the foundation for an abstracted quantitative structure.
Mental Action
Descriptions of Mental Actions
MA1
Coordinating the value of one variable with changes in the other
MA2
Coordinating direction of change of one variable with changes in the other variable
MA3
Coordinating amount of change of one variable with changes in the other variable
MA4
Coordinating the average rate-of-change of the function with uniform increments of change
in the input variable
MA5
Coordinating the instantaneous rate of change of the function with continuous changes in the
independent variable for the entire domain of the function
Figure 2. Carlson et al. (2002, p. 357) covariational reasoning mental actions.
Figure 3. For equal increases in arc length from the 3 o’clock position, height increases by decreasing amounts.
Figurative and Operative Thought
Piagetian notions of figurative and operative thought (Piaget, 2001; Steffe, 1991; Thompson,
1985) also inform our characterization of an abstracted quantitative structure. These two
constructs enable differentiating between thought based in and constrained to figurative material
(e.g., perceptual objects and sensorimotor actions)—termed figurative thought—and thought in
which figurative material is subordinate to logico-mathematical operations, their re-presentation,
and possibly their transformations—termed operative thought. Quantitative and covariational
reasoning are examples of operative thought due to their basis in logico-mathematical operations
(Steffe & Olive, 2010). To illustrate the figurative and operative distinction, Steffe (1991)
characterized a child’s counting scheme as figurative if his counting required re-presenting
particular sensorimotor actions and operative if it entailed unitized records of counting that did
not require the child to re-present particular perceptual material or sensorimotor experience. As
another example, Moore et al. (online) illustrated figurative graphing meanings in which
prospective secondary teachers’ graphing actions were constrained to particular perceptual
features (e.g., drawing a graph solely left-to-right) even when they perceived those features as
constraining their graphing of a conceived relationship. In contrast, Moore et al. (online)
described that a prospective secondary teacher’s graphing meaning is operative in the event that
the perceptual and sensorimotor features of their graphing actions are persistently dominated by
the mental operations associated with re-presenting quantitative and covariational operations
across various attempts to construct graphical re-presentations.
Abstracted Quantitative Structure
Our notion of an abstracted quantitative structure draws on the aforementioned constructs to
apply and extend von Glasersfeld’s (1982) definition of concept to the area of quantitative and
covariational reasoning. von Glaserfeld defined a concept as, “any structure that has been
abstracted from the process of experiential construction as recurrently usable…must be stable
enough to be re-presented in the absence of perceptual ‘input’” (p. 194). In the introduction, we
defined an abstracted quantitative structure as a system of quantitative (including covariational)
operations a person has interiorized to the extent he or she can operate as if it is independent of
specific figurative material. Using von Glaserfeld’s framing, an abstracted quantitative structure
is a system of quantitative operations that an individual has interiorized so that it:
1. is recurrently usable beyond its initial experiential construction;
2. can be re-presented in the absence of available perceptual material including that in
which it was initially constructed;
3. can be transformed to accommodate to novel contexts permitting the associated
quantitative operations, see generalizing assimilation (Steffe & Thompson, 2000);
4. is anticipated as re-presentable in any figurative material that permits the associated
quantitative operations.
Clarifying 2., an individual having constructed an abstracted quantitative structure can re-
present it in thought and through the regeneration of previous experiences. Clarifying 3., a
feature of an abstracted quantitative structure is that it can accommodate novel contexts through
additional processes of experiential construction within the context of figurative material in
which such construction has not previously occurred. This action is a hallmark of operative
thought because it entails an individual transforming and using operations of their quantitative
structure to accommodate to novel quantities and associated figurative material, as opposed to
having fragments of figurative activity dominate their thought (Thompson, 1985). This action is
also a hallmark of quantitative reasoning because it enables conceiving mathematical
equivalence in a context differing figuratively from that in which a quantitative structure has
been previously constructed (Moore et al., 2013). Clarifying 4., an abstracted quantitative
structure’s mathematical properties (e.g., quantities’ covariation) are anticipated independent of
any particular instantiation of them, thus understood as not tied to any particular quantities and
associated figurative material. It is in this way that the quantitative operations of an abstracted
quantitative structure are abstract; the individual not only understands that the operations are re-
presentable in previous experiences, but she also anticipates that the operations could be relevant
to novel but not yet had experiences (e.g., some coordinate system not yet experienced).
We next use empirical examples to illustrate the extent students have constructed an
abstracted quantitative structure. Each example is drawn from a study that either used clinical
interview (Ginsburg, 1997) or teaching experiment (Steffe & Thompson, 2000) methodologies to
build second-order models of student thinking (Ulrich, Tillema, Hackenberg, & Norton, 2014). It
was in our reflecting on these second-order models (and those developed during other studies)
that we identified themes in their reasoning, one of which is the notion of an abstracted
quantitative structure. We acknowledge the way we have defined abstracted quantitative
structure presents an inherent problem in attempts to characterize a student as having or having
not constructed such. First, it is impossible to investigate a student’s reasoning in every context
in which an abstracted quantitative structure could be relevant. Second, to characterize a
students’ quantitative reasoning necessarily involves focusing on their enactment of operations in
the context of particular figurative material. No conceptual structure is truly representation free,
as “operations have to operate on something and that something is the figurative material
contained in the operations, figurative material that has its origin in the construction of the
operations” (L. P. Steffe, personal communication, July 24, 2019). For this reason, we find it
necessary to use the criteria above to discuss a student’s actions in terms of indications and
contraindications of her or him having constructed an abstracted quantitative structure.
A Contraindication of Re-Presentation
Critical criteria of an abstracted quantitative structure are the ability to re-present that
structure in the absence of available perceptual material and the ability to transform its
operations to accommodate to novel contexts. As a contraindication of these criteria, consider
Lydia’s actions during a teaching experiment focused on trigonometric relationships and re-
presentation (Liang & Moore, 2018). Prior to the actions presented here, Lydia had constructed
incremental changes compatible with those presented in Figure 3 (left). We took her actions to
indicate her reasoning quantitatively and subsequently presented her the Which One? task. The
task (Figure 4, left) presented numerous red segments that varied in tandem as the user varied a
horizontal (blue) segment, which represented the rider’s arc length traveled along the circle. We
asked her to choose the red segment that covaried with the blue segment in a way compatible
with the vertical height and arc length of the rider. We conjectured this would help determine the
extent she could re-present her previous actions in a similar context with less perceptual material
available (i.e., the circle) and novel material (i.e., the red and blue segments).
Lydia became perturbed as to whether or not the horizontal red segment should vary at a
changing rate with respect to the horizontal blue segment. After much effort, she abandoned
considering the segments in the horizontal orientation and re-oriented them vertically. She chose
the correct segment by checking whether the heights matched pointwise within the displayed
circle (Figure 4, middle). Both her questioning how the red segments should vary with respect to
the blue segment and her requiring re-orienting the red segments were a contraindication of her
having constructed an abstracted quantitative structure. We thus returned her to the question of
whether the chosen red segment and blue segment entailed the same quantitative relationship as
she identified in her previous activity (see Figure 3, left; from Liang and Moore (2018)):
Lydia: Not really…Um, I don’t know. [laughs] Because that was just like something that I
had seen for the first time, so I don’t know if that will like show in every other
case…Well, for a theory to hold true, it like – it needs to be true in other occasions, um,
unless defined to one occasion.
TR.: So is what we’re looking at right now different than what we were looking at with the
Ferris wheel?
Lydia: No. It’s – No…Because I saw what I saw, and I saw that difference in the Ferris
wheel, but I don’t see it here, and so –
TR.: And by you “don’t see it here,” you mean you don’t see it in that red segment?
Lydia: Yes.
As the interaction continued, Lydia expressed uncertainty as to how to determine if the blue
segment and her chosen red segment entailed the same relationship as she had illustrated in her
previous activity, although she knew the segments were correct pointwise. As a further
contraindication of her having constructed an abstracted quantitative structure, it was only after
much subsequent teacher-researcher guiding and their introducing perceptual material using their
pens (Figure 4, right) that she was able to conceive the red and blue segments’ covariation as
compatible with the relationship she had constructed in the Ferris wheel situation.
Liang and Moore (2018) illustrated Lydia’s repeated engagement in quantitative and
covariational reasoning eventually led to her re-presenting quantitative operations including
transforming those operations in novel contexts. This enabled her to conceive mathematical
equivalence across numerous contexts including situations, oriented segments, and Cartesian
graphs. As indication of having constructed abstracted quantitative structures, Lydia re-presented
particular quantitative operations in contexts without given perceptual material (Lee et al., 2019).
Figure 4. (left) Which One?, (middle) Lydia checking segment pointwise, and (right) Lydia attempting to re-present
a quantitative structure with assistance.
An Indication of Re-Presentation and Accommodation
We turn to two prospective secondary teachers’—Kate and Jack—actions when asked to
determine a formula for an unnamed polar coordinate system graph (Figure 5, which is r =
sin(q); see Moore et al. (2013) for the detailed study). After investigating a few points, Kate and
Jack conjectured that r = sin(q) is the appropriate formula and drew a Cartesian sine graph to
explore their conjecture (from Moore et al., 2013, p. 468). Important to note, Kate and Jack were
not familiar with graphing the sine relationship in the polar coordinate system.
Figure 5. Kate and Jack covary quantities with respect to the given graph (from Moore et al., 2013, p. 467).
Kate: This gets us from zero to right here is zero again [tracing along Cartesian horizontal
axis from 0 to π]. So, we start here [pointing to the pole in the polar coordinate system].
Jack: Ya, and you’re sweeping around because [making circular motion with pen], theta’s
increasing, distance from the origin increases and then decreases again [Jack traces along
Cartesian graph from 0 to π as Kate traces along corresponding part of the polar graph].
TR.: OK, so you’re saying as theta increases the distance from the origin does what?
Jack: It increases until pi over 2 [Kate traces along polar graph] and then it starts decreasing
[Kate traces along polar graph as Jack traces along Cartesian graph].
TR.: And then what happens from like pi to two pi.
Kate: It’s the same.
Jack: Um, same idea except your, the radius is going to be negative, so it gets more in the
negative direction of the angle we’re sweeping out [using marker to sweep out a ray from
π to 3π/2 radians – see Figure 5] until three pi over two where it’s negative one away and
then it gets closer to zero [continuing to rotate marker].
TR.: OK, so from three pi over two to two pi, can you show me where on this graph [pointing
to polar graph] we would start from and end at?
Kate: This is the biggest in magnitude, so it’s the furthest away [placing a finger on a ray
defining 3π/2 and a finger at (1, π/2)], and then [the distance from the pole] gets smaller
in magnitude [simultaneously tracing one index finger along an arc from 3π/2 to 2π and
the other index finger along the graph – see Figure 5].
Kate and Jack’s actions indicate their having constructed (or constructing) an abstracted
quantitative structure associated with the sine relationship. They transformed and re-presented
the quantitative and covariational operations they associated with a Cartesian graph to
accommodate to a polar coordinate system displayed graph. This re-presentation enabled them to
conceive two graphs as representing equivalent quantitative structures despite their perceptual
differences, which is a contraindication of their reasoning being dominated by figurative aspects
of thought. We note that Kate and Jack did not provide evidence related to criteria 4. Such
evidence would involve their identifying the potential of not yet experienced coordinate systems
and associated graphs that enable re-presenting the same quantitative structure.
Discussion and Implications
We envision the construct of an abstract quantitative structure as useful in several ways.
First, it provides criteria to research and distinguish between students’ meanings in terms of their
foregrounding figurative material and activity and their foregrounding logico-mathematical
operations such as a quantitative structure. In our description of Lydia’s activity, we underscore
that she did not encounter much difficulty assimilating the figurative material; she was able to
assimilate the segments and their variation to quantitative operations. Rather, Lydia struggled to
accommodate the relationship she constructed with previous figurative material in a way that she
could re-present it with novel figurative material. Seeing how difficult it was for Lydia to re-
present a relationship within a circular context further demonstrates how powerful Kate and
Jack’s reasoning was because not only did they re-present a quantitative structure in a novel
context, but they abstracted the associated operations such that they could identify the same
relationship within a perceptually different representational system. We, therefore, call for
researchers and educators to attend not only to students’ meanings for various representations
(e.g., Cartesian coordinate system, polar coordinate system, formulas, tables, etc.), but also to the
quantitative structures students construct and the extent they can re-present (and potentially
transform) those structures. In doing so, we can obtain more detailed insights to the extent
students construct mental operations in which figurative material is a consequence of those
operations including how those operations enable accommodating to novel contexts.
Second, we hypothesize that students’ abstracted quantitative structures play an important
role in their productive generalization (Ellis, 2007) and transfer (Lobato & Siebert, 2002).
Researchers have recently characterized the role of different forms of abstraction in
generalization (Ellis, Tillema, Lockwood, & Moore, 2017). Researchers have also recently
characterized different forms of transfer including how a student’s novel activity can result in
cognitive reorganizations regarding their previous activity (Hohensee, 2014; Lobato,
Rhodehamel, & Hohensee, 2012). We envision students’ construction of abstracted quantitative
structures to be a province of each, and we argue that future research should explore these
potential relationships as it relates to students’ mathematical development.
Acknowledgments
This material is based upon work supported by the National Science Foundation under Grants
No. DRL-1350342, No. DRL-1419973, and No. DUE-1920538.
References
Carlson, M. P. (1998). A cross-sectional investigation of the development of the function
concept. In E. Dubinsky, A. H. Schoenfeld, & J. J. Kaput (Eds.), Research in collegiate
mathematics education, III. Issues in Mathematics Education (Vol. 7, pp. 114-162).
Carlson, M. P., Jacobs, S., Coe, E., Larsen, S., & Hsu, E. (2002). Applying covariational
reasoning while modeling dynamic events: A framework and a study. Journal for Research
in Mathematics Education, 33(5), 352-378.
Castillo-Garsow, C. (2010). Teaching the Verhulst model: A teaching experiment in
covariational reasoning and exponential growth. Ph.D. Dissertation. Arizona State
University: USA.
Confrey, J., & Smith, E. (1995). Splitting, covariation, and their role in the development of
exponential functions. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 26(66-86).
Ellis, A. B. (2007). The influence of reasoning with emergent quantities on students'
generalizations. Cognition and Instruction, 25(4), 439-478.
Ellis, A. B. (2011). Generalizing-promoting actions: How classroom collaborations can support
students' mathematical generalizations. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education,
42(4), 308-345.
Ellis, A. B., Özgür, Z., Kulow, T., Williams, C. C., & Amidon, J. (2015). Quantifying
exponential growth: Three conceptual shifts in coordinating multiplicative and additive
growth. The Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 39, 135-155.
Ellis, A. B., Tillema, E., Lockwood, E., & Moore, K. C. (2017). Generalization across domains:
The relating-forming-extending framework. In E. Galindo & J. Newton (Eds.), Proceedings
of the 39th annual meeting of the North American Chapter of the International Group for the
Psychology of Mathematics Education (pp. 677-684). Indianapolis, IN: Hoosier Association
of Mathematics Teacher Educators.
Frank, K. (2017). Examining the development of students' covariational reasoning in the context
of graphing. Ph.D. Dissertation. Arizona State University: USA.
Ginsburg, H. P. (1997). Entering the child's mind: The clinical interview in psychological
research and practice. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
Hohensee, C. (2014). Backward Transfer: An Investigation of the Influence of Quadratic
Functions Instruction on Students’ Prior Ways of Reasoning About Linear Functions.
Mathematical Thinking and Learning, 16(2), 135-174. doi:10.1080/10986065.2014.889503
Izsák, A. (2003). "We want a statement that Is always true": Criteria for good algebraic
representations and the development of modeling knowledge. Journal for Research in
Mathematics Education, 34(3), 191-227.
Johnson, H. L. (2012). Reasoning about variation in the intensity of change in covarying
quantities involved in rate of change. The Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 31(3), 313-330.
Johnson, H. L. (2015a). Secondary students’ quantification of ratio and rate: A framework for
reasoning about change in covarying quantities. Mathematical Thinking and Learning, 17(1),
64-90.
Johnson, H. L. (2015b). Together yet separate: Students’ associating amounts of change in
quantities involved in rate of change. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 1-22.
Lee, H. Y. (2017). Students’ construction of spatial coordinate systems. Ph.D. Dissertation.
University of Georgia: USA.
Lee, H. Y., Moore, K. C., & Tasova, H. I. (2019). Reasoning within quantitative frames of
reference: The case of Lydia. The Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 53, 81-95.
Liang, B., & Moore, K. C. (2018). Figurative thought and a student's reasoning about "amounts"
of change. In A. Weinberg, C. Rasmussen, J. Rabin, M. Wawro, & S. Brown (Eds.),
Proceedings of the Twenty-First Annual Conference on Research in Undergraduate
Mathematics Education (pp. 271-285). San Diego, CA: San Diego State University.
Lobato, J., Rhodehamel, B., & Hohensee, C. (2012). "Noticing" as an alternative transfer of
learning process. Journal of the Learning Sciences, 21(3), 433-482.
Lobato, J., & Siebert, D. (2002). Quantitative reasoning in a reconceived view of transfer. The
Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 21, 87-116.
Moore, K. C. (2013). Making sense by measuring arcs: A teaching experiment in angle measure.
Educational Studies in Mathematics, 83(2), 225-245. doi:10.1007/s10649-012-9450-6
Moore, K. C. (2014). Quantitative reasoning and the sine function: The case of Zac. Journal for
Research in Mathematics Education, 45(1), 102-138.
Moore, K. C., Paoletti, T., & Musgrave, S. (2013). Covariational reasoning and invariance
among coordinate systems. The Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 32(3), 461-473.
Moore, K. C., Stevens, I. E., Paoletti, T., Hobson, N. L. F., & Liang, B. (online). Pre-service
teachers’ figurative and operative graphing actions. The Journal of Mathematical Behavior.
Oehrtman, M., Carlson, M. P., & Thompson, P. W. (2008). Foundational reasoning abilities that
promote coherence in students' function understanding. In M. P. Carlson & C. L. Rasmussen
(Eds.), Making the connection: Research and teaching in undergraduate mathematics
education (pp. 27-42). Washington, D.C.: Mathematical Association of America.
Paoletti, T., & Moore, K. C. (2017). The parametric nature of two students’ covariational
reasoning. The Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 48, 137-151.
Paoletti, T., & Moore, K. C. (2018). A covariational understanding of function: Putting a horse
before the cart. For the Learning of Mathematics, 38(3), 37-43.
Piaget, J. (2001). Studies in reflecting abstraction. Hove, UK: Psychology Press Ltd.
Saldanha, L. A., & Thompson, P. W. (1998). Re-thinking co-variation from a quantitative
perspective: Simultaneous continuous variation. In S. B. Berensen, K. R. Dawkings, M.
Blanton, W. N. Coulombe, J. Kolb, K. Norwood, & L. Stiff (Eds.), Proceedings of the 20th
Annual Meeting of the North American Chapter of the International Group for the
Psychology of Mathematics Education (Vol. 1, pp. 298-303). Columbus, OH: ERIC
Clearinghouse for Science, Mathematics, and Environmental Education.
Smith III, J. P., & Thompson, P. W. (2008). Quantitative reasoning and the development of
algebraic reasoning. In J. J. Kaput, D. W. Carraher, & M. L. Blanton (Eds.), Algebra in the
Early Grades (pp. 95-132). New York, NY: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Stalvey, H. E., & Vidakovic, D. (2015). Students’ reasoning about relationships between
variables in a real-world problem. The Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 40, 192-210.
Steffe, L. P. (1991). The learning paradox: A plausible counterexample. In L. P. Steffe (Ed.),
Epistemological foundations of mathematical experience (pp. 26-44). New York: Springer-
Verlag.
Steffe, L. P., & Olive, J. (2010). Children's Fractional Knowledge. New York, NY: Springer.
Steffe, L. P., & Thompson, P. W. (2000). Teaching experiment methodology: Underlying
principles and essential elements. In R. A. Lesh & A. E. Kelly (Eds.), Handbook of research
design in mathematics and science education (pp. 267-307). Hillside, NJ: Erlbaum.
Stevens, I. E., & Moore, K. C. (2016). The Ferris wheel and justifications of curvature. In M. B.
Wood, E. E. Turner, M. Civil, & J. A. Eli (Eds.), Proceedings of the 38th annual meeting of
the North American Chapter of the International Group for the Psychology of Mathematics
Education (pp. 644-651). Tucson, AZ: The University of Arizona.
Thompson, P. W. (1985). Experience, problem solving, and learning mathematics:
Considerations in developing mathematics curricula. In E. A. Silver (Ed.), Teaching and
learning mathematical problem solving: Multiple research perspectives (pp. 189-243).
Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Thompson, P. W. (1990). A cognitive model of quantity-based algebraic reasoning. Paper
presented at the Annual Meeting of the American Educational Research Association, San
Francisco, CA.
Thompson, P. W. (1994). Images of rate and operational understanding of the fundamental
theorem of calculus. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 26(2-3), 229-274.
Thompson, P. W. (2011). Quantitative reasoning and mathematical modeling. In S. Chamberlin,
L. L. Hatfield, & S. Belbase (Eds.), New perspectives and directions for collaborative
research in mathematics education: Papers from a planning conference for WISDOM^e (pp.
33-57). Laramie, WY: University of Wyoming.
Thompson, P. W., & Carlson, M. P. (2017). Variation, covariation, and functions: Foundational
ways of thinking mathematically. In J. Cai (Ed.), Compendium for Research in Mathematics
Education (pp. 421-456). Reston, VA: National Council of Teachers of Mathematics.
Thompson, P. W., & Silverman, J. (2007). The concept of accumulations in calculus. In M. P.
Carlson & C. L. Rasmussen (Eds.), Making the connection: Research and teaching in
undergraduate mathematics (pp. 117-131). Washington, DC: Mathematical Association of
America.
Ulrich, C., Tillema, E. S., Hackenberg, A. J., & Norton, A. (2014). Constructivist model
building: Empirical examples from mathematics education. Constructivist Foundations, 9(3),
328-339.
von Glasersfeld, E. (1982). Subitizing: The role of figural patterns in the development of
numerical concepts. Archives de Psychologie, 50, 191-218.
... A quantitative construct or structure plays an important role in the way that generalizations are formed and applied, according to Moore et al. (2020), in that they are part of the process that results in abstraction or the process of extracting the underlying patterns or properties of concepts so that they have wider applications. According to Moore et al. (2020), an abstracted quantitative construct or structure is a body of specific mathematical knowledge that an individual has that is not limited to the situation that it was initially found and can be relevant to new scenarios. ...
... A quantitative construct or structure plays an important role in the way that generalizations are formed and applied, according to Moore et al. (2020), in that they are part of the process that results in abstraction or the process of extracting the underlying patterns or properties of concepts so that they have wider applications. According to Moore et al. (2020), an abstracted quantitative construct or structure is a body of specific mathematical knowledge that an individual has that is not limited to the situation that it was initially found and can be relevant to new scenarios. The development of an abstracted quantitative structure is a mental act that will eventually lead to the recognition that a mathematical process can be applied to unfamiliar scenarios (Moore et al., 2020). ...
... According to Moore et al. (2020), an abstracted quantitative construct or structure is a body of specific mathematical knowledge that an individual has that is not limited to the situation that it was initially found and can be relevant to new scenarios. The development of an abstracted quantitative structure is a mental act that will eventually lead to the recognition that a mathematical process can be applied to unfamiliar scenarios (Moore et al., 2020). According to Ellis (2007aEllis ( , 2007b, action generalizations are a path to conclusive reflection generalizations. ...
Article
Developing mathematical and geometric thinking provides access to mathematics and promotes independent problem-solving skills, an essential life skill in the ever-changing job market. The process of building mathematical thinking and mathematical knowledge relies heavily on generalizations, which extend a range of knowledge or reasoning to a new situation. Promoting generalization among high school students helps develop problem-solving skills that allow for independent solving of non-routine problems or problems that students have not experienced before. This research identified the generalizations of general principles of strategies, patterns, and rules high school geometry students exhibited during inquiry-based lessons and then applied those generalizations to solve non-routine problems. This qualitative case study identified the application of generalizations through a thematic analysis, a generalization taxonomy, and collecting data from sixteen students through observations, journaling, and interviews while covering the topics of geometric transformations and trigonometry. The findings of this research show students used general principle reflection generalizations to solve non-routine problems on both geometric transformations and trigonometry. Additionally, students used prior knowledge to solve the trigonometry non-routine problems. The findings showed how the generalization taxonomy can be used for lesson development and how the generalization taxonomy can be applied to communicate the demonstration of geometric habits of mind. This research is an example of how classroom educators can promote generalizations and solving non-routine problems.
... However, a single instantiation of the same symbol may signify incompatible quantitative referents at the same time for a modeler. In Merik's work, we infer that his quadratic template held a mix of situationally relevant quantitative referents associated with objects and their attributes in the scenario, and situation-general quantitative referents (Moore et al., 2019) that were associated with his conception of quadratics, equations, graphs, and coordinates upon Cartesian planes. ...
Article
Full-text available
Mathematical modelling is endorsed as both a means and an end to learning mathematics. Despite its utility and inclusion as a curricular objective, one of many questions remaining about learners’ modelling regards how modelers choose relevant situational attributes and express mathematical relationships in terms of them. Research on quantitative reasoning has informed the field on how individuals quantify attributes and conceive of covariational relationships among them. However, this research has not often attended to modelers’ mathematization in open modelling tasks, an endeavor that invites further attention to theoretical and methodological details. To this end, we offer a synthesis of existing theories to present a cognitive account of mathematical model construction through a quantity-oriented lens. Second, we use empirical data to illustrate why it is productive for theories of modelling to attend to and account for students’ quantitative reasoning while modelling. Finally, we identify remaining challenges to coordinating different theoretical accounts of model construction.
Conference Paper
Full-text available
This paper discusses a student coordinating changes in covarying quantities. We adopt Piaget’s constructs of figurative and operative thought to describe her partitioning activity (i.e., mental and physical actions associated with constructing incremental changes) in terms of the extent that it is constrained to carrying out particular sensorimotor actions on perceptually available material, and we relate such descriptions to her thinking about quantitative amounts of change. We conclude the paper by discussing how characterizing these nuances in her partitioning activity contributes to current literature on covariational reasoning and concept construction.
Conference Paper
Full-text available
This report discusses the results of semi-structured clinical interviews with ten prospective secondary mathematics teachers who were provided with dynamic images of Ferris wheels. We asked the students to graph the relationship between the distance a rider traveled around the Ferris wheel and the height of the rider from the ground. We focus on the different quantitative and non-quantitative ways of thinking in which students engaged to justify the curvature of their drawn graphs. We also discuss how these ways of thinking relate to reasoning covariationally about directional change and amounts of change.
Chapter
Full-text available
Recent research in cognitive psychology and artificial intelligence (collectively called cognitive science) has made impressive progress in revealing the varieties and intricacies of mathematical problem solving. However, the connections between studies of mathematical problem solving and the practice of teaching mathematics are not always clear. That is to be expected. Due to the very nature of scientific inquiry, studies of problem solving must focus on questions of limited scope with simplified hypotheses, if only to provide a filter with which to separate signal from noise. Also, cognitive scientists tend to focus on what is in the world of mathematical problem solving, which is essential. But mathematics educators have an equal charge to consider what ought to be and how it might be achieved. With this in mind, it is clear that research in cognitive science on mathematical problem solving can inform mathematics educators of the current state of affairs and can even suggest constructs that promise powerful ways of thinking about teaching problem solving, but it cannot dictate mathematics curricula or methods of teaching. To improve mathematics teaching and learning, mathematics educators must consider the students' passage through an entire curriculum. Thus, those involved in curriculum development will of necessity always be traveling untrodden terrain, always working beyond established databases. My purpose in this paper is to discuss an attempt at developing mathematics curricula that draws from research on problem solving and mathematical cognition, but goes beyond it in addressing issues unique to mathematics education—primary among them, mathematics education's concern with the learner throughout a mathematical program. By itself, a collection of models of problem solving on relatively restricted problem sets is insufficient as a basis for designing a mathematics curriculum. A curriculum developer must augment it with some sort of model of a learner passing through the curriculum. As I have noted, cognitive science has developed a wealth of constructs that have powerful implications for mathematics curriculum development. I wish to make clear from the start, however, that I am writing from the perspective of a practicing mathematics educator. The examples that will be given come largely from my experience as a teacher of mathematics, albeit one who is fairly well informed of the methods and constructs of cognitive science. Perhaps another caveat is necessary. Ideas are significant only within the context of an overriding universe of discourse. The significance for mathematics education of much of recent research on mathematical problem solving can be appreciated only when we consider the aims of mathematics education. If one thinks of learning mathematics as tantamount to memorizing mathematical "facts," or an accretionary building of elaborate sets of behaviors, then much of what follows will be irrelevant. If, however, one accepts that the aim of mathematics education is to promote mathematical thinking, then this paper will be of interest. A predominant theme of this paper, as one would guess from the title, is that learning 1 The author wishes to express his gratitude to the Department of Mathematical Sciences, San Diego State University, for its support in preparing the materials reported in this paper.
Article
We report on semi-structured clinical interviews to describe U.S. pre-service secondary mathematics teachers’ graphing meanings. Our primary goal is to draw on Piagetian notions of figurative and operative thought to identify marked differences in the students’ meanings. Namely, we illustrate students’ meanings dominated by fragments of sensorimotor experience and compare those with students’ meanings dominated by the coordination of mental actions in the form of covarying quantities. Our findings suggest students’ meanings that foreground operative aspects of thought are more generative with respect to graphing. Our findings also indicate that students can encounter perturbations due to potential incompatibilities between figurative and operative aspects of thought.
Article
Researchers have argued that covariational reasoning is foundational for learning a variety of mathematics topics. We extend prior research by examining two students’ covariational reasoning with attention to the extent they became consciously aware of the parametric nature of their reasoning. We first describe our theoretical background including different conceptions of covariation researchers have found useful when characterizing student reasoning. We then present two students’ activities during a teaching experiment in which they constructed and reasoned about covarying quantities. We highlight aspects of the students’ reasoning that we conjectured created an intellectual need that resulted in their constructing a parameter quantity or attribute, a need we explored in closing teaching episodes. We discuss implications of these results for perspectives on covariational reasoning, students’ understandings of graphs and parametric functions, and areas of future research.
Chapter
In the summer of 1985, Carl Bereiter published an article in the Review of Educational Research titled Toward a Solution of the Learning Paradox. Ever since, it has been my intention to provide a counterexample to the paradox. Fodor (1980b), who is credited by Bereiter as clearly stating the learning paradox, views learning as being necessarily inductive. “Let’s assume, once again, that learning is a matter of inductive inference, that is, a process of hypothesis formation1 and confirmation” (p. 148). Given his view of learning, Fodor states the learning paradox in the following way.
Article
This paper reports on part of an investigation of fifteen second-semester calculus students' understanding of the concept of parametric function. Employing APOS theory as our guiding theoretical perspective, we offer a genetic decomposition for the concept of parametric function, and we explore students' reasoning about an invariant relationship between two quantities varying simultaneously with respect to a third quantity when described in a real-world problem, as such reasoning is important for the study of parametric functions. In particular, we investigate students' reasoning about an adaptation of the popular bottle problem in which they were asked to graph relationships between (a) time and volume of the water, (b) time and height of the water, and (c) volume and height of the water. Our results illustrate that several issues make reasoning about relationships between variables a complex task. Furthermore, our findings indicate that conceiving an invariant relationship, as it relates to the concept of parametric function, is nontrivial, and various complimentary ways of reasoning are favorable for developing such a conception. We conclude by making connections between our results and our genetic decomposition.
Article
> Context . This paper outlines how radical constructivist theory has led to a particular methodological technique, developing second-order models of student thinking, that has helped mathematics educators to be more effective teachers of their students. > Problem . The paper addresses the problem of how radical constructivist theory has been used to explain and engender more viable adaptations to the complexities of teaching and learning. > Method . The paper presents empirical data from teaching experiments that illustrate the process of second-order model building. > Results . The result of the paper is an illustration of how second-order models are developed and how this process, as it progresses, supports teachers to be more effective. > Implications . This paper has the implication that radical constructivism has the potential to impact practice.
Book
Children's Fractional Knowledge elegantly tracks the construction of knowledge, both by children learning new methods of reasoning and by the researchers studying their methods. The book challenges the widely held belief that children's whole number knowledge is a distraction from their learning of fractions by positing that their fractional learning involves reorganizing not simply using or building upon their whole number knowledge. This hypothesis is explained in detail using examples of actual grade-schoolers approaching problems in fractions including the schemes they construct to relate parts to a whole, to produce a fraction as a multiple of a unit part, to transform a fraction into a commensurate fraction, or to combine two fractions multiplicatively or additively. These case studies provide a singular journey into children's mathematics experience, which often varies greatly from that of adults. Moreover, the authors' descriptive terms reflect children's quantitative operations, as opposed to adult mathematical phrases rooted in concepts that do not reflect-and which in the classroom may even suppress-youngsters' learning experiences. Highlights of the coverage: Toward a formulation of a mathematics of living instead of beingOperations that produce numerical counting schemes Case studies: children's part-whole, partitive, iterative, and other fraction schemes Using the generalized number sequence to produce fraction schemes Redefining school mathematics This fresh perspective is of immediate importance to researchers in mathematics education. With the up-close lens onto mathematical development found in Children's Fractional Knowledge, readers can work toward creating more effective methods for improving young learners' quantitative reasoning skills. © Springer Science+Business Media, LLC 2010 All rights reserved.