ArticlePDF Available

Commentary on Corradi et al.’s (2019) new conception of aesthetic sensitivity: Is the ability conception dead?

Authors:

Abstract

Corradi et al. (British Journal of Psychology, 2019) argue that their new conception of visual aesthetic sensitivity (as responsiveness to aesthetic features in one’s preferences) presents several advantages in comparison with the current ability view of aesthetic sensitivity, usually defined as the ability to judge aesthetic stimuli in accordance with standards (The Journal of Psychology, 1964, 57 and 49). Although the measure they propose is interesting and presents advances to the field, we point to important issues. Notably, the authors conveniently base their comparison between the two conceptions on psychometric double standards, discard a century of research on aesthetic sensitivity by focusing on Eysenck’s speculations, and disguise an extension of already existing aesthetic preference tests (e.g., The Journal of Psychology, 1952, 33 and 199; Empirical Studies of the Arts, 2005, 23 and 165) as a redefinition of aesthetic sensitivity. We conclude that both aesthetic preference and aesthetic sensitivity research are legitimate objects of study, that the authors present interesting ideas to further the study of aesthetic preferences, but that their approach is not new and that its proposed renaming only adds confusion to the field.
Commentary on Corradi et al.’s (2019) new conception of aesthetic sensitivity: is the ability
conception dead?
Nils Myszkowski
Pinar Çelik
Martin Storme
Note : This is a pre-print version of the accepted paper. The full paper is available at
https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1111/bjop.12440
Myszkowski, N., Çelik, P., & Storme, M. (2020). Commentary on Corradi et al.’s (2019) new
conception of aesthetic sensitivity: Is the ability conception dead? British Journal of
Psychology. https://doi.org/10.1111/bjop.12440
COMMENTARY ON CORRADI ET AL. (2019) 2
Abstract
Corradi et al. (2019) argue that their new conception of visual aesthetic sensitivity (as
responsiveness to aesthetic features in one’s preferences) presents several advantages in
comparison with the current ability view of aesthetic sensitivity, usually defined as the ability
to judge aesthetic stimuli in accordance with standards (Child, 1964). Although the measure
they propose is interesting and presents advances to the field, we point to important issues.
Notably, the authors conveniently base their comparison between the two conceptions on
psychometric double standards, discard a century of research on aesthetic sensitivity by
focusing on Eysenck’s speculations, and disguise an extension of already existing aesthetic
preference tests (e.g., Barron & Welsh, 1952; Wilson & Chatterjee, 2005) as a redefinition of
aesthetic sensitivity. We conclude that both aesthetic preference and aesthetic sensitivity
research are legitimate objects of study, that the authors present interesting ideas to further
the study of aesthetic preferences, but that their approach is not new and that its proposed
renaming only adds confusion to the field.
Keywords: Aesthetic sensitivity, good taste, aesthetic ability, aesthetic preferences, individual
differences, psychometrics
COMMENTARY ON CORRADI ET AL. (2019) 3
Commentary on Corradi et al.’s (2019) “new” conception of aesthetic sensitivity: is
the ability conception dead?
Corradi et al. (2019) propose that the current conception of aesthetic sensitivity as
the ability to identify aesthetic quality in conformity with external standards (e.g. expert
consensus) needs replacement into a new conception: aesthetic sensitivity should be
redefined as the extent to which certain features of a stimulus are used to form a subjective
aesthetic judgment. Although their proposed approach has merits, their (unnecessary)
comparison is biased in several ways. In the present commentary, we critically review some
of the key arguments used to build their case against the ability conception of aesthetic
sensitivity.
Are existing measures of aesthetic sensitivity so bad?
A key argument of the authors against the ability conception of aesthetic sensitivity is
the alleged poor psychometric properties of existing tests. Certainly, measures of aesthetic
sensitivity are largely imperfect, but most of the authors claims here are inaccurate or
obsolete. The Visual Aesthetic Sensitivity Revised for example presents good internal
consistency, unidimensionality and structural validity (e.g., Myszkowski & Storme, 2017).
Combining its qualities with previous research on the original test, we may add that there is
encouraging evidence of cultural measurement invariance as well (e.g., Chan, Eysenck, &
Götz, 1980). The authors also point to the correlations between the VAST and other
constructs (specifically intelligence) as problematic. We agree that they are not in line with
Eysenck’s speculations, but they remain a non-issue, because 1) aesthetic sensitivity and
intelligence in the visual aesthetic are both part of the same nomological network
(Myszkowski, Çelik, & Storme, 2018) next to such constructs like figural creativity and
openness-related traits 2) such relations are consistent across tests (Myszkowski et al.,
2018), 3) sensory perception tasks in general are correlated with intelligence, and 4) the
COMMENTARY ON CORRADI ET AL. (2019) 4
correlations remain weak to moderate at best thus maintaining discriminant validity. As a
comparison, creativity is often found to hold relations of the same magnitude with
intelligence and openness should we infer from Corradi et. al.’s logic that creativity
research should also be abandoned?
More importantly, the authors’ attacks severely contrast with their own empirical
inquiry. Notably, they do not report (or even suggest to later study) their instrument’s internal
consistency, dimensionality or measurement invariance even though, quite likely, some of
these qualities could have been studied in their very sample. Not exposing their instrument to
an empirical inquiry using the same canons bases the entire comparison of the authors on
double standards.
Bad measures do not imply bad constructs
More than defending the (perfectible) qualities of visual aesthetic sensitivity tests, we
want to point out that, even if these tests had been flawed in their psychometric qualities, this
would not discard the construct itself, nor its definition. Should we discard intelligence as a
construct because one intelligence test is deemed to be psychometrically insufficient? Of
course not, because a construct and its measures are different. This brings us to the attacks on
the ability construct definition itself.
The authors argue that the ability conception of aesthetic sensitivity is “meaningful
and useful only if beauty is truly an objective value”. Indeed, Eysenck probably believed in
an “objective beauty”, a hardly defensible idea philosophically. Still, the existence of an
“objective beauty” is not a necessary condition for the study of aesthetic sensitivity, and thus
this point is irrelevant. Since Thorndike (1916), it has been clearly admitted that the aesthetic
value of a stimulus is actually only determined by expert consensus. Also, Child’s (1964)
definition of aesthetic sensitivity, which is currently the most used for the construct, clearly
describes aesthetic sensitivity as the ability to “judge in relation to external standards”, again
COMMENTARY ON CORRADI ET AL. (2019) 5
without claiming objectivity. We believe that investigating the extent to which individuals
agree with experts on aesthetic value is interesting both from a fundamental and from an
applied perspective, regardless of whether objective beauty exists or not.
Unfortunately, even though the authors briefly mention the history of aesthetic
sensitivity research, they largely attack the ability approach of aesthetic sensitivity by
attacking Eysenck’s claims. Despite significant contributions to the field, the ability
conception predates and postdates Eysenck, as several analogous tests existed before Eysenck
(e.g., Thorndike, 1916) some of them are still in use (e.g., Summerfeldt, Gilbert, &
Reynolds, 2015). Further, the commonly used construct definition was provided by Child
(1964), not Eysenck. Thus, Eysenck’s speculations and beliefs being correct or incorrect is
not relevant to the legitimacy of the construct.
The authors propose a measure of aesthetic preferences, not aesthetic sensitivity
The authors themselves acknowledge that their construct be defined as "the extent to
which a given feature influences someone’s liking or preference”. But this is really a
rephrasing of one’s preference for an aesthetic feature. The problem is that several aesthetic
preference tests such as the Barron-Welsh Figure Preference Test (1952) or the Preference
for Balance Test (Wilson & Chatterjee, 2005) which, similarly, use stimuli that vary
according to a specific feature (e.g., balance) and record the examinee’s preference, have
been developed: they are simply called aesthetic preference tests. We would concede that the
term “aesthetic sensitivity” is vague enough to accommodate both approaches, but we do not
see the point of renaming the study of aesthetic preference which is thus not new at all
especially when it involves using a name already used for a now century-old (yet still vivid)
approach. Why not call this a “multidimensional aesthetic preference test” instead?
COMMENTARY ON CORRADI ET AL. (2019) 6
Conclusion
Aesthetic sensitivity has been studied as the ability to identify (consensually/expertly
defined) aesthetic value for over a century, is clearly conceptually defined, and is
incrementally overcoming its psychometric challenges. Corradi et al.’s work involves
manipulating aesthetic features of stimuli and the observation of individual preference: it
should therefore be regarded as an aesthetic preference test. The two research interests are not
mutually exclusive and both merit scientific inquiry, but the authors’ approach should be
distinguished from aesthetic sensitivity, and is not the revolution that they claim.
COMMENTARY ON CORRADI ET AL. (2019) 7
References
Barron, F., & Welsh, G. S. (1952). Artistic Perception as a Possible Factor in Personality
Style: Its Measurement by a Figure Preference Test. The Journal of Psychology,
33(2), 199203. https://doi.org/10.1080/00223980.1952.9712830
Chan, J., Eysenck, H. J., & Götz, K. O. (1980). A new Visual Aesthetic Sensitivity Test: III.
Crosscultural comparison between Hong Kong children and adults, and English and
Japanese samples. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 50(3, Pt 2), 13251326.
https://doi.org/10.2466/pms.1980.50.3c.1325
Child, I. L. (1964). Observations on the Meaning of Some Measures of Esthetic Sensitivity.
The Journal of Psychology, 57(1), 4964.
https://doi.org/10.1080/00223980.1964.9916671
Corradi, G., Chuquichambi, E. G., Barrada, J. R., Clemente, A., & Nadal, M. (2019). A new
conception of visual aesthetic sensitivity. British Journal of Psychology.
https://doi.org/10.1111/bjop.12427
Myszkowski, N., Çelik, P., & Storme, M. (2018). A meta-analysis of the relationship between
intelligence and visual “taste” measures. Psychology of Aesthetics, Creativity, and the
Arts, 12(1), 2433. https://doi.org/10.1037/aca0000099
Myszkowski, N., & Storme, M. (2017). Measuring “Good Taste” with the Visual Aesthetic
Sensitivity Test-Revised (VAST-R). Personality and Individual Differences, 117, 91
100. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.paid.2017.05.041
Summerfeldt, L. J., Gilbert, S. J., & Reynolds, M. (2015). Incompleteness, aesthetic
sensitivity, and the obsessive-compulsive need for symmetry. Journal of Behavior
Therapy and Experimental Psychiatry, 49, Part B, 141149.
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jbtep.2015.03.006
Thorndike, E. L. (1916). Tests of esthetic appreciation. Journal of Educational Psychology,
7(9), 509522.
COMMENTARY ON CORRADI ET AL. (2019) 8
Wilson, A., & Chatterjee, A. (2005). The assessment of preference for balance: Introducing a
new test. Empirical Studies of the Arts, 23(2), 165180.
https://doi.org/10.2190/B1LR-MVF3-F36X-XR64
... The construct validity of tests based on it are however controversial (Gear, 1986;Liu, 1990;Corradi et al., 2019), as it was notably argued that absolute aesthetic standards cannot exist, dismissing any operationalization of Child's definition. Nevertheless, the availability of absolute standards is not a necessary condition for the operationalization of Child's definition (Myszkowski et al., 2020): Aesthetic sensitivity tests rely instead on empirical standards, obtained through expert and/or laypeople consensus. Consequently, they compare an examinees' response with the typical response of experts-as originally suggested by Thorndike (1916)-or use expert agreement to select items-as used in the VAST. ...
... Another sign of construct validity can be found in the concurrent validity of visual aesthetic sensitivity tests. This point is also quite controversial (Corradi et al., 2019;Myszkowski et al., 2020), but this is mainly because the nomological network of visual aesthetic sensitivity is yet to be clearly defined. Notably, Eysenck introduced confusion by originally discussing the construct as intelligence in the aesthetic domain (1940) to then speculate that the construct should be independent from intelligence (Frois and Eysenck, 1995)-which is contradicted in a recent meta-analysis (Myszkowski et al., 2018), which showed across 23 studies that its correlation with intelligence is significant and around 0.30. ...
... Nevertheless, one can reasonably expect that, as is found empirically, visual aesthetic sensitivity would be positively correlated with intelligencebecause common cognitive processes are likely engaged in both measures (Myszkowski et al., 2018), and because it is common to observe relations between sensory perception in other domains and intelligence (e.g., Troche and Rammsayer, 2009)-or with personality traits like openness to aesthetics (Myszkowski et al., 2014)-because individuals with stronger interest in aesthetics may engage in more extensive processing, leading to higher accuracy, as it was for example found (Myszkowski, 2019) that, in these tests, response speed is negatively correlated with accuracy. Therefore, even though the nomological network of visual aesthetic sensitivity is not sufficiently (nor consistently) discussed, the pattern of relations between aesthetic sensitivity and other measures does suggest that visual aesthetic sensitivity measures present evidence of concurrent validity (Myszkowski et al., 2020). ...
... We thank Myszkowski et al. (2020) for their critical comments on our recent work on aesthetic sensitivity (Corradi, Chuquichambi, Barrada, Clemente, & Nadal, 2020). We are also very grateful to the editors of the British Journal of Psychology for enabling this discussion. ...
... First, Myszkowski et al. (2020) claim that 'Since Thorndike (1916), it has been clearly admitted that the aesthetic value of a stimulus is actually only determined by expert consensus'. This statement is wrong historically, psychologically, and neuroscientifically. ...
... Second, Myszkowski et al. (2020) claim that aesthetic sensitivity, 'as the ability to identify (consensually/expertly defined) aesthetic value for over a century, is clearly conceptually defined'. This is misleading. ...
Article
Full-text available
We respond to some of Myszkowski and colleagues' (2020, Br. J. Psychology) critical comments on our recent work on aesthetic sensitivity (Corradi, Chuquichambi, Barrada, Clemente, & Nadal, 2020, Br. J. Psychology). We show that these comments stem mostly from factual inaccuracies.
... 4 Research on the perception of aesthetic stimuli is still developing and, therefore, different researchers use the same terms more or less precisely, which is reflected in the dispute over "visual aesthetic sensitivity". [5][6][7] The second component of aesthetic intelligence is depth of experience, that is the intensity with which our contact with an aesthetic stimulus is experienced. There is a difference between noticing beauty and expressing a judgment that we "like" something (it gives simple, sensual pleasure) and the feeling of extreme emotions, which touch the essence of existence. ...
Article
Full-text available
Background Ferrucci, a philosopher and psychotherapist, presented an original three-factor aesthetic intelligence concept in his book “Beauty and Soul” (2009). The subject of this article is the presentation of work on the construction of a scale for measuring one of the three dimensions of aesthetic intelligence, the ability to integrate beauty (AIB). This is probably the first attempt to empirically operationalize this concept. Methods The three independent studies were carried out with a total of 604 participants. The aim of the first study was to develop the AIBS scale and to test its factor structure. During Study 2 and Study 3, we verified the AIBS structure through the confirmatory analysis and checked its convergent and discriminant validity. Results The outcomes indicate that a one-factor, and seven-item tool is characterized by very good psychometric properties. Moreover, the results suggest that the AIB is indeed positively related to the perception of artworks (6 dimensions of an aesthetic experience), regulation of emotions through artistic creative activities, as well as to aesthetic competencies in art. The AIB is indeed positively related to the greater intensity of light triad traits (humanism, kantianism, faith in humanity) and to the development of the individual in five areas of spirituality. AIB is also only slightly related to the search for meaning and to one dimension of well-being, which is satisfaction and the sense of power.
... The second argument is a fallacy: failing to measure an attribute (well), even repeatedly, does not make a construct unmeasurable. In other words, "bad measures do not imply bad constructs" ( [9], p. 660). Moreover, a number of studies have actually suggested that individuals spontaneously agree on attributes of artworks, even aesthetic quality (e.g., [7,10]). ...
Article
Full-text available
Immersive virtual reality (IVR) takes advantage of exponential growth in our technological abilities to offer an array of new forms of entertainment, learning opportunities, and even psychological interventions and assessments. The field of creativity is a driving force in both large-scale innovations and everyday progress, and imbedding creativity assessment in IVR programs has important practical implications for future research and interventions in this field. Creativity assessment, however, tends to either rely on traditional concepts or newer, yet cumbersome methods. Can creativity be measured within IVR? This study introduces the VIVA, a new IVR-based visual arts creativity assessment paradigm in which user create 3D drawings in response to a prompt. Productions are then rated with modern extensions of a classic product-based approach to creativity assessment. A sample of 67 adults completed the VIVA, further scored using item-response modeling. Results demonstrated the strong psychometric properties of the VIVA assessment, including its structural validity, internal reliability, and criterion validity with relevant criterion measures. Together, this study established a solid proof-of-concept of the feasibility of measuring creativity in IVR. We conclude by discussing directions for future studies and the broader importance and impact of this line of work for the field of creativity and virtual reality.
Chapter
In this chapter, we discuss the social environment as an important factor to consider in understanding creativity. We use as a framework for describing the environment’s effects on creativity Bronfenbrenner’s ecological systems theory (1979, 1986), which proposes that the individual’s psychological development results from interactions with different types of environmental systems that range from local to global—microsystem, mesosystem, exosystem, macrosystems and chronosystem. As we go through these different layers, we discuss existing research, such as research on family effects (birth order, parenting style, etc.), peers, schooling, mentors, the work environment, as well cultural definitions of creativity and of creative products. We also point to research gaps—notably the limited research describing mesosystems and exosystem effects—but conclude that, overall, the social environment plays a substantial role in creativity, calling for further inquiry.KeywordsCreativityCreative environmentSocial environmentCultureChild development
Article
An Runde 1 der Diskussion über den von Karl Otto Götz entwickelten Visual Aesthetic Sensitivity Test beteiligen sich Gerhard Stemberger, Herbert Fitzek, Nils Myszkowski, Riccardo Luccio, Thomas Jacobsen/Barbara E. Marschallek/Selina M. Weiler und Roy R. Behrens.
Article
The first round of the discussion on the Visual Aesthetic Sensitivity Test developed by Karl Otto Götz includes texts from Gerhard Stemberger, Herbert Fitzek, Nils Myszkowski, Riccardo Luccio, Thomas Jacobsen/Barbara E. Marschallek/Selina M. Weiler and Roy R. Behrens.
Article
w/k Zwischen Wissenschaft & Kunst - A peer-reviewed online journal: The first round of the discussion on the Visual Aesthetic Sensitivity Test developed by Karl Otto Götz includes texts from Gerhard Stemberger, Herbert Fitzek, Nils Myszkowski, Riccardo Luccio, Thomas Jacobsen/Barbara E. Marschallek/Selina M. Weiler and Roy R. Behrens. Published in English and German.
Article
Full-text available
What makes individuals experts in judging aesthetic value is actively researched in a variety of ways. In the visual domain, one classical paradigm – used in “T” (for Taste) tests (Eysenck, 1983) – consists in comparing one’s evaluative judgments of beauty with a standard judgment – provided by consensual or expert agreement. The association between general intelligence (g) and performance in “T” tests has been investigated since over 70 years (Eysenck, 1940; Myszkowski, Storme, Zenasni, & Lubart, 2014), but has led to a variety results, from negative weak to positive strong correlations. We aimed at clearing the resulting confusion through a meta-analysis of the correlations observed in the literature (k=23, N=1531). We found a significant positive weak to moderate correlation between g and “T” (ρ = .30, CI95% = [.23; .36], z = 9.00, p < .001), suggesting that common cognitive processes are involved in both g and “T”. Reinforcing this conclusion, no publication bias was found through the regression test, and none of the tested moderators - year of publication, gender, age, “T” measure, g measure – had a significant effect on the correlation.
Article
The Visual Aesthetic Sensitivity Test was applied to 287 male and 252 female Hong Kong children of Chinese extraction, aged from 7 yr. upwards, and to 58 adult males and 144 adult females. Their responses were compared with those of English and Japanese children and adults, and somewhat lower scores recorded for the Hong Kong children and adults. A group of German girls were also tested. Difficulty levels for the items were not dissimilar to those observed in England and Japan.
Article
Balance is a central feature that contributes to the organizational structure of aesthetic visual images. Balance gives unity to an otherwise diverse display. Dynamic balance refers to the way in which disparate elements of an image produce visual forces that compensate for each other. Despite the importance of balance on aesthetic perception and production, few tests are designed to assess sensitivity or preference for this important attribute of images. Here, we introduce the assessment of preference for balance (APB) and report a method to derive an objective balance score. In selecting items for this test, we eliminated images that produce local grouping effects and confound assessment of the effects of dynamic balance per se. Our final test constitutes 130 images comprised of circles or hexagon elements. The objective balance scores accounted for 73% and 78% of the variance, respectively, in subjec- tive preferences for these images.
Article
To test an hypothesis that artists, as distinguished from non-artists, like complex-asymmetrical figures and dislike simple-symmetrical ones, figures were drawn in black ink on 3 X 5 cards. The expressed preferences bore out the hypothesis, and it also held with a second group. The authors suggest that a basis has been established for further investigation of the relationship between such artistic figure preferences and such possible causal factors as good taste, personality style, or a combination of the two. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2012 APA, all rights reserved)
Article
Describes two tests of aesthetic appreciation which can be used as tests of instruction or vocational guidance: (a) a graded series of known degrees of aesthetic merit to be arranged in order, the S's ability being measured inversely by the sum of his deviations from the correct order, and (b) appreciation of the quality of a line of poetry written to complete a couplet, the first line being given. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2012 APA, all rights reserved)
A meta-analysis of the relationship between intelligence and visual "taste" measures
  • N Myszkowski
  • P ßelik
  • M Storme
Myszkowski, N., C ßelik, P., & Storme, M. (2018). A meta-analysis of the relationship between intelligence and visual "taste" measures. Psychology of Aesthetics, Creativity, and the Arts, 12(1), 24-33. https://doi.org/10.1037/aca0000099.